Deductive rationality in validating and testing ...
Recommend Documents
'non-standard' decision making count as irrational? Some have ... The subjects are not judged irrational because they ..... Dan Ariely, Predictably Irrational, 51f.
Testing Bounded Rationality against Full. Rationality in Job Changing Behavior. Bruno Contini. University of Torino, LABORatorio R. Revelli and IZA.
Apr 14, 2014 - Dr Riyad Eid is Associate Professor of Marketing at the College of Business and ...... Automotive Technology and Management, 1(4), 416â.
ECONOMIC & CONSUMER CREDIT ANALYTICS. MOODY'S ANALYTICS ..... at Moody's Analytics, where he manages the company's c
Dr Riyad Eid is Associate Professor of Marketing at the College of Business and Economics, United Arab. Emirates University, UAE ..... CRM implementation (e.g., Software Selection, ... remains true in smaller organizations (Daniel. & Myers ...
Jun 19, 2011 - Email: [email protected]. ... Essentially, we are testing whether consumption choices can be modeled as resulting ..... We now apply our measure to a set of consumption data collected by the marketing firm ACNeilson.
Bolton gratefully acknowledges financial support from the National Science ... 201 you should change trains at King's Cross. Yet if you took this map as a guide ... 202. Gary E. Bolton and Axel Ockenfels than the measures used by ERC or FS). ... Test
Apr 19, 2016 - and tissues in the human body and need to be validated for their predictive ... efficacy, and toxicity of
The use of survey data on exchange rate expectations to test the rational expectations .... ary process with at most a moving average representation of order j!1.
[2] Amit Bhatia and Emilio Frazzoli. Incremental search methods for reachability analysis of continuous and hybrid systems. In HSCC, volume 2993 of Lecture ...
International Conference on Software and Systems Engineering and their ...
phase and use those scenarios in system test to systematically determine test
cases.
Jan 16, 2002 - Algebraic class testing is an object-oriented software testing method based on algebraic ...... Front: returns the value in the cell A[Head].
Nov 15, 1999 - When the Whitlam government came to power, related formations such as 'economically rational' were used to describe the arguments of the.
Mar 13, 2018 - Abstract: Complete inactivation of infectious Ebola virus (EBOV) is ...... J.B. Physicochemical inactivation of Lassa, Ebola, and Marburg viruses ...
These fundamentals of a evolutionarily rational theory of intuition can be subjected .... fact or decision, in relation to other knowledge; thus, rationality is based on ...
Designing, Testing, and Validating a Focused Stem Cell Microarray .... Hoechst dye labeling, Sox-1, Sox-2, and TERT, have been combined with negative ...
system for monitoring and control using a common and open infrastructure, i.e. .... The tool is called TidSim, short for âNewspaper Simulatorâ in Swedish. The first ...
Deductive geometry is the art of deriving new geometric facts from ... grade
students are already practicing — and enjoying — deductive reasoning as they
solve.
where Ossi+1 = hfBindingj j hBindingj Uji 2 Set(T DBi)g EDBi+1 C ommiti,. EDBi+1 is (EDBi U). ..... Manual, 1981. 25] R. Fagin ... 30] H. Gaifman and E. Shapiro. .... icates using test and assignments which attempt to determine the values of the.
studies support the model theory, pose some difficulties for rule theories, and show the influence on .... the premises (Braine & O'Brien, 1991; Rips, 1983, 1994).
(easy); pictures of Charlie Brown vs. pictures of other characters from the Peanuts .... explanation of why one's action on the trial was correct or incorrect.
partir de problemas de condicionales múltiples como: Si e, entonces b; Si a, ... comparación con los condicionales formulados mediante si, entonces; sólo si; y a ...
What is the relation between the decision-maker's mindset and emotions? ....
brain scanning using functional magnetic resonance imaging (fRMI). The results.
Catherine Alexander,. Durham University ..... seamless official organization was multiply fissured (Alexander, 2006). ..... King's Court Communications Inc.
Deductive rationality in validating and testing ...
Walter Schroyens (Walter[email protected]) ... Walter Schaeken (Walter. .... The hypothetical thinking model (Evans & Over, 2004; Evans et al.,. 2003) and ...
Deductive rationality in validating and testing conditional inferences.
Walter Schroyens ([email protected]) University of Gent, Department of Psychology Henry Dunantlaan, 2, B-9000, Gent, Belgium
and
Walter Schaeken ([email protected]) University of Leuven, Department of Psychology, Tiensestraat, 102, B-3000, Leuven, Belgium.
Acknowledgments We gratefully acknowledge the of the Flanders (Belgium) Fund for Scientific Research (G.0320.05) and the Canadian Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council (NSERC 297517). Experiment 1 was presented at a Cognitive Science Society meeting (Schroyens, 2005a). We thank those reviewers who engaged seriously with the theoretical narrative and provided constructive criticisms to improve upon it.
Abstract We asked people to validate conditional inferences (e.g, “A, therefore C” with ‘if A then C’). People are more likely to look for falsifications (‘A and not-C’) versus confirmations (‘A and C’), given a forced choice. Second, falsification rates are lower for logically valid versus invalid inferences. Logically valid inferences are inferences that follow necessarily. Experiment 1 (N = 96) shows that emphasising this logicality constraint increases falsification rates in the validation task and corroborates that validation-by-falsification increases logically correct inference evaluations. Experiment 2 (N = 41) corroborates the other way round that people who are more likely to make logically correct evaluations, show higher falsification performance in the validation task. The results support mental-models theory and suggest alternative theories similarly need to specify how people would go about looking for counterexamples. We proffer such a specification for two alternatives to the model theory.
1
Introduction Our beliefs are hypotheses about the world we live in, the creatures in it and our interactions with them and each other. Expectations are grounded by deriving inferences from our beliefs. Forming and testing hypotheses is thus of capital interest in marrying our beliefs with the changing environment we inhabit. Many such beliefs reflect conditional relationships. Reasoning about conditionals has accordingly attracted the interest of cognitive scientists of all backgrounds. There exists abundant evidence people take counterexamples into account (e.g., Cummins, Lubart, Alksnis, & Rist, 1991; De Neys, Schaeken, & d’Ydewalle, 2003). These studies, however, have been conducted with knowledge-rich materials. These materials, mostly causal conditionals, are rich in associated background knowledge and have been pre-tested and classified as yielding few or many counterexamples. The results typically show that when there are more counterexamples, people are generally less certain about the conclusion countered by the counterexample. Consider, for instance the following two formally equivalent arguments, -
If a woman has sex, then she will become pregnant. Hence, given that this woman is pregnant, it follows that she has had sex.
-
If a dog has fleas, then it will scratch itself. Hence, given that this dog scratches itself, it follows that it has fleas.
Most readers will consider the latter conclusion less plausible, as there are many causes for scratching, while there are only few ways of getting pregnant. It is generally assumed that there is an automatic activation of background knowledge. Theories that address commonsense reasoning about knowledge-rich conditionals proffer a largely passive, data-driven “search” for counterexamples (see, e.g., Oaksford & Chater, 1998).
2
This stands in contrast with theories of deductive reasoning that posit an active goal-directed search. In these theories counterexamples are often not activated by semantic association; they are actively looked for to test inferences and constructed on the basis of the negation of the inference one aims to test (Schroyens & Schaeken, 2003; Schroyens et al., 2001). Theories that posit a goal-directed search for counterexamples have mostly focused on explaining performance on knowledge-lean deductive inference problems. For instance: (1)
If letter is an A then the number is a 2. The number is 2; hence the letter is an A.
Performance on such problems is consistent with the idea that people engage in an active counterexample search to test putative inferences drawn from an initial problem treatment (see, e.g., Johnson-Laird & Byrne, 1991; Schroyens et al., 2001). Being able to explain performance on problems such as (1), however, provides only indirect and inconclusive evidence for an active search for counterexamples. We thus set out to provide more direct evidence. But why would people engage in a critical thinking exercise in the first place? A counterexample search can establish logical validity. For arguments to be logically valid its conclusion must necessarily be true, given that the premises are true. When there is an acceptable alternative to the conclusion (which means the conclusion is possibly false), we know the conclusion is not necessarily true. When there is no such alternative, the conclusion necessarily follows. Consider the following logically valid Modus Ponens (MP) argument. (2)