Men, Women, and Science 1
1
Running head: MEN, WOMEN, AND SCIENCE
2 3 4 5
Men, Women, and Science
6
Why the Differences and What Should Be Done?
7 8
Steve Stewart-Williams
9
School of Psychology, University of Nottingham Malaysia Campus, Semenyih
10 11
Lewis G. Halsey
12
Department of Life Sciences, University of Roehampton, London
13 14 15 16
The authors would like to thank Volker Behrends, Tom Reeve, and Martha
17
Villegas-Montes for their perceptive comments on an early draft of this paper.
18
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Steve Stewart-
19
Williams at the School of Psychology, University of Nottingham Malaysia Campus.
20
Email:
[email protected]
21 22 23 24 25 26
Word count: 20,500
Men, Women, and Science 2
27
Abstract
28
It is a well-known and widely lamented fact that men outnumber women in a number
29
of fields in STEM, including physics, mathematics, and computer science. The most
30
common explanations for the gender gaps are discrimination and social norms, and
31
the most common policy prescriptions are targeted at these ostensible causes.
32
However, a great deal of evidence in the behavioral sciences suggests that
33
discrimination and social norms are only part of the story. Other plausible contributors
34
include relatively large mean sex differences in career and lifestyle preferences, and
35
relatively small mean differences in cognitive aptitudes – some favoring males, others
36
favoring females – which are associated with progressively larger differences the
37
further above the mean one looks. A more complete picture of the causes of the
38
unequal sex ratios in STEM may productively inform policy debates, and is likely to
39
improve women’s situation across the STEM fields.
40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47
Public Significance Statements A review of the literature suggests that gender gaps in STEM fields have many causes, including average sex differences in preferences and cognitive specialties. Anti-female discrimination, though it demonstrably exists, is probably not the primary cause of STEM gender gaps in modern Western nations. Policy prescriptions founded on the notion of pervasive anti-female bias are unlikely to have positive effects.
48 49 50
KEYWORDS: Discrimination; Equality; Gender; Sex Differences; STEM.
Men, Women, and Science 3
51
Men, Women, and Science
52
Why the Differences and What Should Be Done?
53 54
Never has the issue of gender disparities been as widely discussed, or as
55
bitterly contested, as it has been in recent years. From the Oscars to the political
56
podium, from TV shows to the workplace, disparities are identified and debate
57
inevitably ensues. In the occupational realm, one of the primary focuses of this debate
58
has been the differential representation of men and women in STEM (science,
59
technology, engineering, and math).1 This was epitomized by the infamous “Google
60
memo,” in which then-Google employee James Damore (2017) questioned the extent
61
to which observed gender disparities in STEM are a product of discrimination. The
62
memo, and Damore’s subsequent dismissal from Google, provoked a great deal of
63
discussion and debate about the nature and nurture of human sex differences.
64
Unfortunately, much of this debate was decidedly inaccurate in its presentation of the
65
scientific research on the topic. This is the case even of our most prestigious scientific
66
journals; Nature, for instance, ran an article claiming that sex differences in
67
occupational outcomes were due entirely to discrimination (Chachra, 2017). No
68
doubt, discrimination is part of the explanation. However, a great deal of research
69
suggests that other factors contribute as well to the relative dearth of women in
70
STEM, and that these factors quite possibly play a larger role than discrimination
71
does. In this article, we survey the various lines of evidence bearing on this issue.
1
Strictly speaking, the issue is not STEM per se, but rather STEM fields that have a strong spatial or mathematical component. According to Ceci, Ginther, Kahn, and Williams (2014), the STEM fields should be divided into GEEMP fields (geoscience, engineering, economics, mathematics/computer science, and the physical sciences) and LPS fields (life science, psychology, and social science). Men outnumber women in GEEMP fields, but women are at parity with men, or even sometimes outnumber them, in LPS fields.
Men, Women, and Science 4
72
We divide the task into six parts. First, we look at research suggesting that
73
men and women differ, on average, in their career and lifestyle preferences, and that
74
these differences are due in part to biological causes. Second, we consider the
75
possibility that men and women differ, on average, in certain cognitive aptitudes –
76
that men, for instance, score somewhat higher on tests of spatial ability whereas
77
women score somewhat higher on verbal tests. Third, we look at the controversial
78
suggestion that men are more variable than women in cognitive ability, such that there
79
are more men at the top of the ability distribution, and more men as well at the
80
bottom. Fourth, we look at the issue of gender discrimination in STEM, and the extent
81
to which this explains why more men than women end up in certain fields. Fifth, we
82
look some of the major policy prescriptions aimed at shrinking the STEM gender gap
83
and redressing the gender imbalances. And sixth, we consider whether the appropriate
84
aim of such interventions is a 50:50 sex ratio in every STEM field or simply a level
85
playing field. In other words, should the ultimate goal be equality of outcome or
86
equality of opportunity?
87 88
Sex Differences in Preferences and Priorities
89
To begin with, we examine arguably the most important non-bias explanation
90
for sex differences in STEM representation: the idea that men and women differ – on
91
average – in certain career-relevant preferences. Specifically, we look at sex
92
differences in occupational preferences and sex differences in life priorities. After
93
that, we consider the extent to which these differences are products of nature or
94
nurture, and we look at the evolutionary pressures that might have helped to shape
95
them.
Men, Women, and Science 5
96
Occupational Preferences
97
A large literature in psychology shows that men and women differ, on
98
average, in the kinds of occupations that interest them (Morris, 2016). One of the most
99
important recent papers on this topic was a comprehensive meta-analysis by Su,
100
Rounds, and Armstrong (2009). The paper focused on two main areas: preferences for
101
general types of occupations (e.g., those focused on people vs. things) and preferences
102
for specific careers (e.g., engineering vs. mathematics). In both cases, the authors
103
found substantial sex differences that plausibly help to explain observed STEM
104
gender gaps.
105
Starting with general occupational types, by far the largest sex difference was
106
that for interest in “people jobs” vs. “things jobs.” People jobs are jobs that center on
107
interacting with other human beings; things jobs are jobs that center on working with
108
objects, machines, or abstract rules. Members of both sexes can be found at every
109
point on the people vs. things continuum; however, more men than women exhibit a
110
preference for things jobs, whereas more women than men exhibit a preference for
111
people jobs. Averaging across studies, Su et al. (2009) found an effect size of d = .93
112
for the people vs. things sex difference. This is notably larger than most human sex
113
differences (Lippa, 2009; Stewart-Williams & Thomas, 2013), and indeed than most
114
effects in psychology (Eagly, 1995). To get an intuitive sense of the magnitude of the
115
difference, if one were to pick pairs of people at random, one man and one woman,
116
the man would be more things-oriented than the woman around 75% of the time.
117
The people vs. things sex difference immediately suggests an explanation – or
118
rather a partial explanation – for the fact that men outnumber women in fields such as
119
physics, engineering, and mathematics, whereas women are at parity with or even
120
outnumber men in fields such as psychology and the social sciences: The former
Men, Women, and Science 6
121
fields are of interest to more men than women, and the latter more women than men,
122
and people tend to gravitate to fields that are of greater interest to them. This is not
123
merely a plausible-sounding speculation; Yang and Barth (2015) have shown that
124
interest in things vs. people accounts for much (although not all) of the variance in
125
people’s occupational outcomes.
126
Research looking at preferences for specific occupations leads to a similar
127
conclusion. As Su et al. (2009) report, males on average express considerably more
128
interest than females in engineering (d = 1.11), and somewhat more interest in science
129
and mathematics (d = .36 and .34, respectively). These differences are present by
130
early adolescence and closely match the observed numbers of men and women
131
working in the fields in question. Su et al. (2009) point out that, if we assume for the
132
sake of argument that people working in a given field tend to come from the 25% of
133
people most interested in that field, sex differences in occupational interests would
134
account for the entirety of the engineering gender gap and much of the gap in science
135
and mathematics. In short, sex differences in occupational preferences are far from
136
trivial, and plausibly make a substantial contribution to observed occupational gender
137
gaps.
138
Life Priorities
139
Gender gaps in STEM – and especially the higher echelons of STEM fields –
140
may also be shaped in part by average sex differences in life priorities. As with
141
occupational preferences, people vary a lot in their life priorities, and the full range of
142
priorities can be found within each sex. Nonetheless, some priorities are more
143
common among men than women, and others among women than men (Hakim, 2005;
144
Schwartz & Rubel, 2005). One longitudinal study, for instance, found that, among
145
adults identified as mathematically gifted in early adolescence, the average man
Men, Women, and Science 7
146
reported placing more importance on career success and income, whereas the average
147
woman reported placing more importance on work-life balance and making time for
148
one’s family and friends (Benbow, Lubinski, Shea, & Eftekhari-Sanjani, 2000;
149
Lubinski, Benbow, & Kell, 2014). These differences were particularly pronounced
150
among people with children, largely because women’s priorities changed after they
151
became mothers (Ferriman, Lubinski, & Benbow, 2009). Moreover, sex differences in
152
self-reported priorities were evident in real-world behaviour. For example, as
153
Lubinski et al. (2014) observed, over the course of the last fifteen years, the men in
154
their sample had worked an average of 51 hours per week, whereas the women had
155
worked an average of 40.
156
Of course, sex differences in lifestyle preferences do not explain why the sex
157
ratio is so much more male-biased in math-intensive STEM fields than in most others.
158
Still, the differences do plausibly help to explain the fact that, in STEM and
159
elsewhere, men outnumber women among the minority in the higher echelons: Rising
160
to the top is a priority for fewer women than men, and thus fewer women than men
161
are willing to make the sacrifices required to achieve that goal. To be clear, some
162
women are willing to make those sacrifices, and the majority of men are not.
163
However, more men than women are willing, and this is plausibly part of the reason
164
that the sex ratio at the top is so often male-biased. Note that, according to one large
165
US study (N ≈ 4,000), the sex difference in career-mindedness is not a result of
166
women thinking that career advancement is impossible for them. The average woman
167
views career advancement as just as achievable as the average man, but as less
168
desirable (Gino, Wilmuth, & Brooks, 2015).
Men, Women, and Science 8
169
The Nature and Nurture of Sex Differences in Occupational Preferences
170
Sex differences in occupational preferences suggest one possible reason that
171
more men than women go into math-intensive STEM fields. The reason, put simply,
172
is that more men than women want to go into these fields. To the extent that this is so,
173
it reduces the need to posit workplace discrimination as the root cause of gender
174
disparities in STEM. Still, even if occupational preferences explained all of the STEM
175
gender gap (which we are certainly not suggesting), this would not imply that
176
discrimination played no role. After all, it could be argued that the preference
177
differences themselves are products of discriminatory socialization practices and
178
sexist cultural norms. No doubt, social factors help to determine which occupations
179
people choose or end up in. However, several lines of evidence suggest that sex
180
differences in this arena are shaped to an important degree by unlearned biological
181
factors.
182
First, sex differences in occupational preferences have remained remarkably
183
stable throughout the half-century or so that psychologists have measured them, even
184
in the face of significant shifts in women’s social roles and place in society (Su et al.,
185
2009). In particular, the sex difference in interest in things vs. people seems
186
stubbornly resistant to change. One analysis, for instance, found that whereas the
187
number of women pursuing high-status professions increased a great deal since the
188
1970s, the number pursuing things-related professions remained virtually static
189
(Lippa, Preston, & Penner, 2014). Notably, this was the case despite the fact that,
190
during that same period, a wide range of initiatives were established to try to entice
191
women into those very professions.
192 193
Second, the same sex differences in occupational preferences have been found in every society where psychologists have looked for them. In one large study (N ≈
Men, Women, and Science 9
194
200,000), Lippa (2010) found the differences in 53 out of 53 nations: a level of cross-
195
cultural unanimity almost unheard of within psychology. Importantly, the gender gap
196
in occupational preferences was no larger in nations with higher levels of gender
197
inequality, suggesting that gender inequality is not a major determinant of the gap.
198
Meanwhile, other research suggests that the gender gap in STEM employment (as
199
opposed to STEM-related job preferences) is actually smaller in more gender unequal
200
nations, perhaps in part because economic hardship means that people in those nations
201
have less scope to act on their personal preferences, and a greater need to place
202
financial security above self-fulfillment in choosing a suitable career (Stoet & Geary,
203
2018).
204
Third, at least some of the relevant sex differences appear in nascent form
205
early in the developmental process. The first glimmer of the people vs. things
206
difference, for instance, may be evident in the first few days of life. Connellan, Baron-
207
Cohen, Wheelwright, Batki, and Ahluwalia (2000) famously presented 102 newborn
208
babies with two objects, one after the other: a human face and a mechanical mobile.
209
Many babies looked for equal amounts of time at both. However, among those who
210
looked for longer at one than the other, more boys than girls looked for longer at the
211
mobile (43% vs. 17%), whereas more girls than boys looked for longer at the face
212
(36% vs. 25%; although see Spelke, 2005). A similar pattern has been observed in a
213
number of nonhuman primates: Newborn female macaques are more attentive to faces
214
than are newborn males (Simpson et al., 2016), and female macaques and vervet
215
monkeys spend more time playing with toy dolls provided by experimenters than do
216
males of their respective species (Alexander & Hines, 2002; Hassett, Siebert, &
217
Wallen, 2008).
Men, Women, and Science 10
218
Finally, occupational preferences have been convincingly linked to prenatal
219
hormonal exposure (Levy & Kimura, 2009). Girls with congenital adrenal
220
hyperplasia (or CAH), which involves exposure to high levels of testosterone in the
221
womb, tend to have more male-typical career preferences than other girls (Beltz,
222
Swanson, & Berenbaum, 2011; Berenbaum & Beltz, 2011). Similarly, in non-clinical
223
populations, the average prenatal testosterone levels of workers in a field are
224
negatively correlated with the proportion of women working in that field (Manning,
225
Reimers, Baron-Cohen, Wheelwright, & Fink, 2010). The correlations between
226
prenatal hormones and occupational outcomes tend to be relatively modest; in the
227
Manning et al. study, for instance, they range from around .1 to .6. This is presumably
228
partly a product of measurement error and partly because prenatal hormones are only
229
one influence among many. Nonetheless, in light of the hormonal data, and the other
230
data surveyed in this section, it seems reasonable to conclude that sex differences in
231
occupational preferences are not purely a product of culture or socialization. Biology
232
plays a role as well.
233
Evolutionary Rationale
234
Although we have good reason to think that there is an innate contribution to
235
men and women’s occupational and lifestyle preferences, we have much less idea why
236
this might be the case. The most plausible evolutionary explanation is for sex
237
differences in lifestyle preference. In most parental species, females invest more than
238
males into offspring (Janicke, Häderer, Lajeunesse, & Anthes, 2016; Trivers, 1972).
239
Among mammals, for instance, females gestate and nurse the young, and females
240
usually provide the bulk of the direct parental care. In our species, sex differences in
241
parental investment are comparatively modest: Both sexes tend to invest substantially
242
in their young, rather than only the females. But there is still a difference: Men in all
Men, Women, and Science 11
243
known cultures invest less into offspring than women, and this has probably been the
244
case for most of our evolutionary history (Stewart-Williams & Thomas, 2013).
245
Importantly, the minimum biological investment is also notably smaller for men than
246
for women. Women’s minimum is a nine-month pregnancy and – until recently –
247
several years of breastfeeding. Men’s minimum is the time and effort required to
248
impregnate the woman.
249
As a result of these sex differences in parental investment, ancestral men could
250
potentially produce many more offspring than ancestral women, simply by mating
251
with multiple partners (Clutton-Brock & Vincent, 1991). Consequently, human males
252
evolved to be more interested than females in mating with multiple partners (Schmitt,
253
2005; Schmitt & Project, 2003), less choosy about their low-commitment sexual
254
partners (Buss & Schmitt, 1993; Kenrick, Groth, Trost, & Sadalla, 1993), and – of
255
particular relevance to the present topic – more inclined to compete and take risks to
256
obtain the status and resources that helped to make them attractive to women (Byrnes,
257
Miller, & Schafer, 1999; Daly & Wilson, 2001; Deaner, 2013; M. Wilson & Daly,
258
1985). In light of this theoretical framework – which is well-supported by research in
259
other species (Andersson, 1994; Janicke et al., 2016) – it is little surprise that more
260
men than women prioritize the pursuit of status over family, whereas more women
261
than men prioritize family and work-life balance.
262
Evolutionary explanations for sex differences in occupational preferences are
263
somewhat more of a stretch. For most of human evolution, there were no scientists, no
264
technologists, no engineers or mathematicians. As such, any innate contribution to sex
265
differences in interest in these vocations must be a byproduct of traits selected for
266
other reasons. One possibility is that the differences trace back to the sexual division
267
of labor among our hunter-gatherer forebears, and specifically the fact that women
Men, Women, and Science 12
268
specialized in caring for the young whereas men specialized in hunting and perhaps
269
waging war with other groups (a division of labor found also among our close
270
relatives, the chimpanzees; Muller, Wrangham, & Pilbeam, 2017). To fit them to
271
these roles, women may have evolved a stronger attentiveness to the needs of the
272
young, and by extension, to people in general, whereas men may have evolved a
273
stronger interest in the tools used for hunting and warfare (Geary, 2010; Hrdy, 2009).
274
Sex differences in interest in people-focused vs. things-focused jobs may just be an
275
adaptively neutral side effect of these ancient, more primal differences. It is worth
276
emphasizing that, although this hypothesis seems reasonable enough, it has yet to be
277
rigorously tested. Regardless of the explanation, however, the evidence for an innate
278
contribution to the relevant sex differences is strong.
279 280 281
Sex Differences in Aptitudes Sex differences in occupational preferences are not the only reason we might
282
expect uneven sex ratios in certain STEM fields, even if discrimination were entirely
283
removed from the picture. A second, more controversial suggestion is that STEM
284
gender gaps are due in part to average sex differences in a number of STEM-relevant
285
cognitive capacities, which result in somewhat more men than women having a
286
suitable profile of aptitudes for working in some STEM fields. This statement could
287
easily be misconstrued, so it is important to be absolutely clear what is meant.
288
First, the claim is not that men perform better than women in every cognitive
289
domain. On the contrary, men perform better in some domains whereas women
290
perform better in others. The best-known examples are that men score higher than
291
women on most tests of spatial ability, whereas women score higher than men on
292
most tests of language ability, including verbal comprehension, reading, and writing
Men, Women, and Science 13
293
(Guiso, Monte, Sapienza, & Zingales, 2008; Halpern, 2012; Reynolds, Scheiber,
294
Hajovsky, Schwartz, & Kaufman, 2015).
295
Second, even in areas where men do perform better, the claim is not that all
296
men – or even most – perform better than all or most women. As with occupational
297
preferences, members of both sexes vary enormously in every cognitive aptitude, and
298
the distribution for men overlaps almost entirely with that for women (Hyde, 2005).
299
However, for some aptitudes, the distribution for one sex is shifted somewhat to the
300
right of that for the other, such that the average score for the former is somewhat
301
higher than that for the latter. In saying this, it is worth stressing that the average score
302
does not describe all members of the group, or even the typical member, but merely
303
represents the central tendency within a broad array of scores. Most people fall above
304
or below the average.
305
Third, the claim is not that these cognitive sex differences are especially large.
306
On the contrary, at the center of the distribution, they tend to be rather small (Hyde,
307
2005; Hyde, Lindberg, Linn, Ellis, & Williams, 2008; Stewart-Williams & Thomas,
308
2013). The only reason they matter at all is that even small differences at the mean are
309
associated with progressively larger differences the further from the mean one looks
310
(see Figure 1). For jobs requiring normal-range abilities – including many STEM jobs
311
– cognitive sex differences are likely to make little difference: The pool of potential
312
female candidates is similar in size to the pool of males. However, for jobs requiring
313
exceptional abilities, the sex ratio of potential candidates may be skewed in favor of
314
one sex or the other – even when the relevant sex differences in the general population
315
are small or even negligible (Baye & Monseur, 2016; Halpern, 2012; Halpern et al.,
316
2007; Pinker, 2002).
317
--------------------Insert Figure 1 about here--------------------
Men, Women, and Science 14
318
319 320 321
Figure 1. For two groups, A and B, where the average score on a normally distributed
322
variable is higher for the former than the latter, the ratio of A-to-B gets progressively
323
larger the higher above the average one looks. For both groups, fewer and fewer
324
people occupy each segment above the mean, with the percentage decline getting
325
larger with each further step. For instance, the number of people falling between 1 and
326
2 standard deviations above the mean is 40% of that falling between the mean and 1
327
standard deviation, whereas the number of people falling between 2 and 3 standard
Men, Women, and Science 15
328
deviations above the mean is only 15% of that falling between 1 and 2 standard
329
deviations. This is the case for both groups. However, because the lower-scoring
330
group (B) starts this accelerating decline before the higher-scoring group (A), the
331
percentage decline for the lower-scoring group is always larger than that for the
332
higher-scoring one. The net result is that the ratio of A-to-B gets progressively larger
333
for scores above the mean. Meanwhile, the ratio of B-to-A gets progressively larger
334
for scores below the mean. The sex difference depicted in Figure 1 is large – a full
335
standard deviation between the average for each sex – and thus the skew quickly
336
becomes large as well. However, even small differences at the mean may be
337
associated with high levels of skew at sufficiently extreme levels of any given trait.
338 339
Fourth, the claim is not that women lack the cognitive talents to make it in
340
STEM. Most people lack the cognitive talents, and of those who do possess them,
341
some are men and some are women. The claim is simply that, because of small
342
average differences in a small subset of abilities, somewhat more men than women are
343
suited to work in some areas of STEM – and for the same reason, somewhat more
344
women than men are suited to work in others.
345
The Relevant Differences
346
With these important qualifications in mind, let us now consider some of the
347
sex differences in cognitive aptitudes that may help to explain the uneven sex ratios
348
found in some STEM areas. The first concerns spatial abilities. As mentioned, the
349
average score on most spatial tests is somewhat higher for men than for women. This
350
is a well-established finding (Voyer, Voyer, & Bryden, 1995), especially with respect
351
to mental rotation (Maeda & Yoon, 2013), and it seems reasonable to think it might be
352
part of the reason that somewhat more men than women gravitate to fields that require
Men, Women, and Science 16
353
above-average spatial abilities – fields such as physics and engineering. Consistent
354
with this suggestion, more than fifty years of research in educational psychology
355
indicates that spatial ability is indeed an important predictor of STEM success (Wai,
356
Lubinski, & Benbow, 2009).
357
A second, less widely appreciated cognitive sex difference is that, on average,
358
males as a group score higher than females as a group on tests of mechanical
359
reasoning – that is, tests of the ability to solve problems involving mechanical
360
principles and physical laws (Flores-Mendoza et al., 2013; Hedges & Nowell, 1995;
361
Lemos, Abad, Almeida, & Colom, 2013). Unlike most cognitive sex differences, this
362
one appears to be rather large, even at the mean, and is thus larger still at the right-
363
hand tail of the distribution (Hedges & Friedman, 1993). As with the spatial sex
364
difference, the difference in mechanical reasoning has clear implications for the
365
gender composition of fields such engineering and physics.
366
A third difference relates to mathematical ability; in this case, however, the
367
findings are much less straightforward. Sex differences in average mathematical
368
ability are generally small and highly variable: In some nations, boys do better on
369
tests of mathematical aptitude; in others, girls do (Baye & Monseur, 2016; Else-Quest,
370
Hyde, & Linn, 2010; Guiso, Monte, Sapienza, & Zingales, 2008; Hyde, Lindberg,
371
Linn, Ellis, & Williams, 2008; Stoet, Bailey, Moore, & Geary, 2016). At the same
372
time, though, there appear to be a number of math-related sex differences which may
373
be relevant to STEM outcomes. First, whereas females tend to do better in tests of
374
mathematical computation (Hyde, Fennema, & Lamon, 1990), males tend to do better
375
– at least from adolescence – in tests of mathematical reasoning (that is, tests of the
376
ability to solve problems using mathematical concepts; Benbow, 1988; Halpern, 2012;
377
Hyde et al., 1990). This is a potentially important finding because, as Hyde (1990)
Men, Women, and Science 17
378
notes, mathematical reasoning “is critical for success in many mathematics-related
379
fields, such as engineering and physics” (p. 151). Second, despite small and cross-
380
culturally variable differences in average scores, males consistently outnumber
381
females at the highest levels of mathematical performance (Baye & Monseur, 2016;
382
Makel, Wai, Peairs, & Putallaz, 2016; Reilly, Neumann, & Andrews, 2015; Wai,
383
Cacchio, Putallaz, & Makel, 2010). The upshot is that somewhat more men than
384
women are likely to have the mathematical aptitude to work in math-intensive STEM
385
fields – even though, once again, most men do not.
386
The gender gap in math-intensive fields may be amplified by the fact that,
387
among the minority of people who possess exceptional mathematical abilities, the
388
women are more likely than the men to possess exceptional language abilities as well
389
(Wang, Eccles, & Kenny, 2013). This means that mathematically gifted women have
390
more vocational options than their male counterparts, and consequently that fewer
391
mathematically gifted women end up pursuing a STEM career. To the extent that this
392
explains the gender gap in math-intensive fields, the gap results not from gifted
393
women having fewer options, but rather from them having more.
394
A final cognitive difference bearing on the question of STEM sex ratios relates
395
to Baron-Cohen’s (2003) distinction between systemizing and empathizing.
396
Systemizing refers to the desire and ability to understand or build “systems,”
397
including mechanical systems like cars, physical systems like galaxies, and abstract
398
systems like logic and mathematics. Empathizing, in contrast, refers to the desire and
399
ability to understand people: their thoughts, their desires, their feelings. Virtually
400
every human being possesses both abilities to a greater or lesser extent. On average,
401
though, men score somewhat higher than women on tests of systemizing, whereas
402
women score somewhat higher than men on tests of empathizing (Baron-Cohen,
Men, Women, and Science 18
403
Wheelwright, Hill, Raste, & Plumb, 2001). As usual, these differences are not large
404
among the majority in the normal range. However, among the minority of exceptional
405
empathizers, women outnumber men, and among the minority of exceptional
406
systemizers, men outnumber women (Baron-Cohen et al., 2014). It seems reasonable
407
to suppose that sex differences in systemizing and empathizing are part of the reason
408
that more men than women go into fields such as physics and engineering, whereas
409
more women than men go into fields such as psychology and education. Consistent
410
with this suggestion, Ruzich et al. (2015) observe that STEM workers score
411
consistently above workers in non-STEM fields on measures of systemizing ability.
412
Most commentators agree that sex differences in cognitive aptitudes are too
413
small to explain STEM gender gaps in their entirety, and that sex differences in
414
occupational preferences are a much more important contributor (Ceci, Williams, &
415
Barnett, 2009; Johnson, Carothers, & Deary, 2008). Still, the evidence for the
416
cognitive differences is robust, and it is perfectly plausible that they help to shape men
417
and women’s career choices and trajectories. Indeed, given the clear relevance of the
418
aptitudes in question to STEM, it would be surprising if this were not the case.
419
The Nature and Nurture of Sex Differences in Aptitudes
420
Where do these cognitive sex differences come from? As with sex differences
421
in occupational preferences, scientists do not yet have a complete or definitive
422
answer. Nonetheless, a range of evidence suggests that the differences are not due
423
solely to socialization, but rather have a substantial innate component. First, many of
424
the differences appear early in the developmental process. The sex difference in
425
mental rotation, for instance, can be detected by five months of age (Moore &
426
Johnson, 2008), and the sex difference in language ability can be detected by seven
427
months (Bando, López Bóo, & Li, 2016). These findings do not rule out purely
Men, Women, and Science 19
428
environmental explanations, but they do render them less plausible. At the very least,
429
they eliminate the possibility that social influences appearing after the age of one year
430
could provide a complete explanation for the differences. Certainly, sex differences in
431
cognition may sometimes get larger with time, which one might argue shows that the
432
differences are environmentally determined (see, e.g., Kersey, Braham, Csumitta,
433
Libertus, & Cantlon, 2018; Spelke, 2005). However, there are several responses to
434
this. One is that changes in the magnitude of sex differences are not necessarily a
435
product of social causes alone; to some extent, they may just reflect the natural
436
maturational process – especially when the changes coincide with the onset of
437
puberty. Another response is that, even if the changes were entirely a product of social
438
causes, this would not imply that the initial sex differences were a product of social
439
causes too. The initial differences could well still be innate.
440
Second, many of the traits under discussion have been linked to sex hormones.
441
Spatial ability, for instance, has been linked to both prenatal and pubertal testosterone:
442
Individuals exposed to higher levels of testosterone in the womb, and higher levels at
443
puberty, typically exhibit stronger spatial skills (Berenbaum & Beltz, 2011).
444
Similarly, testosterone supplements appear to boost spatial ability in female-to-male
445
transsexuals (although note that the studies demonstrating this effect tend to have
446
small samples; Slabbekoorn, van Goozen, Megens, Gooren, & Cohen-Kettenis, 1999).
447
In addition to spatial abilities, prenatal testosterone has been linked to higher
448
systemizing, and to lower social skills, empathizing, and verbal ability (Auyeung et
449
al., 2006; Chapman et al., 2006; Lutchmaya, Baron-Cohen, & Raggatt, 2001, 2002;
450
summarized in Baron-Cohen, 2003).
451 452
Third, sex differences in cognitive abilities appear to transcend cultural boundaries. Across cultures, girls typically outperform boys on tests of linguistic
Men, Women, and Science 20
453
ability (Stoet & Geary, 2013), whereas boys typically outperform girls on most spatial
454
tasks (Cashdan, Marlowe, Crittenden, Porter, & Wood, 2012; Lippa, Collaer, &
455
Peters, 2010; although see Hoffman, Gneezy, & List, 2011). Certainly, there is
456
variation in the magnitude of these differences from nation to nation and from age to
457
age, suggesting a sizeable role for malleable social factors. Still, the direction of the
458
spatial/linguistic differences is essentially invariant. This is not what one would
459
expect based on the hypothesis of a purely environmental origin of these differences.
460
Fourth, efforts to eliminate the gaps seem to quickly reach the point of
461
diminishing returns. Wai et al. (2010) looked at the ratio of boys-to-girls in the top
462
.01% of US seventh graders taking a test of mathematical reasoning between 1981
463
and 2010. In the early 1980s, the ratio was 13 boys for every girl. By the early 1990s,
464
this had dropped to just four boys for every girl, perhaps as a result of increasing
465
access to a good math education for girls (see also Hyde et al., 1990). Since then,
466
however, the ratio of boys-to-girls among the top math performers has remained
467
largely the same, despite intensified efforts to eliminate the remaining gap.2
468
Meanwhile, the ratio of girls-to-boys among the top performers on tests of verbal and
469
reading ability has consistently favored girls (Makel et al., 2016; Wai et al., 2010).
470
Again, these findings are not what one would expect based on the assumption that the
471
gaps have a purely environmental origin.
472
Fifth, gay men tend to have spatial and linguistic abilities comparable to those
473
of straight women, whereas lesbians tend to have spatial abilities comparable to those
474
of straight men (but female-typical linguistic abilities; Xu, Norton, & Rahman, 2017).
475
This finding is difficult to explain on the assumption that social forces alone create the
2
Indeed, some research suggests that the ratio of males to females at the top levels of mathematical reasoning has increased in recent years (Lakin, 2013).
Men, Women, and Science 21
476
usual pattern of sex differences. Gay men were presumably subject to essentially the
477
same gender-specific social forces as straight men, and lesbians the same gender-
478
specific social forces as straight women. As such, the near-reversal of the usual spatial
479
vs. language pattern is hard to reconcile with the claim that this pattern is due
480
primarily to social forces. Other variables, such as prenatal hormones, plausibly play a
481
larger role.
482
Finally, some of the most popular sociocultural explanations for STEM gender
483
gaps are flawed in a number of ways. This includes the claim that the gaps are a
484
product of a widespread stereotype that “girls can’t do math,” which persuades girls
485
and women that math is not for them, or which causes them to underperform in math
486
as a result of their anxiety about confirming the denigrating stereotype (a putative
487
example of a phenomenon known as stereotype threat; Spencer, Steele, & Quinn,
488
1999). Although such theories are very popular, they face a number of critical
489
challenges. To begin with, it is unclear whether the theories can account for the data,
490
even in principle. How, for example, would a blanket stereotype about female
491
mathematical inferiority explain the fact that girls get better grades than boys in math
492
class, or that they do better at mathematical computation but worse at mathematical
493
reasoning? It is also debatable to what extent the social influences point in the
494
direction the theory presupposes. According to one study, by four years of age, girls
495
tend to assume that boys are academically inferior, and by seven, boys assume the
496
same thing (Hartley & Sutton, 2013). In a similar vein, teachers tend to view their
497
female students as superior at math (and reading), even when aptitude tests indicate
498
that the boys are doing better (Robinson & Lubienski, 2011). Popular culture often
499
mirrors these trends, with girls depicted as academically superior to boys (consider,
Men, Women, and Science 22
500
for instance, Bart and Lisa Simpson). In short, there is no simple story about the social
501
influences to which boys and girls are exposed.
502
Alongside these theoretical concerns, recent research directly challenges the
503
notion that stereotype threat is a major contributor to STEM gender gaps (Stoet &
504
Geary, 2012). A meta-analysis of studies looking at the impact of stereotype threat on
505
girls’ performance in math, science, and spatial tests found a near zero effect, and
506
evidence of substantial publication bias (Flore & Wicherts, 2015). Soon afterwards, a
507
large, pre-registered study found no effect of stereotype threat on women’s math
508
performance (Finnigan & Corker, 2016). Finally, an analysis of thousands of real-life
509
chess games revealed that, in spite of stereotypes about male superiority at the
510
chessboard, women in fact played better when competing against men than when
511
competing against other women: the exact opposite of what stereotype threat would
512
predict (Stafford, 2017). At the very least, the effect of stereotype threat appears to be
513
more modest than originally assumed.
514
Evolutionary Rationale
515
It seems reasonable to conclude that the cognitive sex differences considered
516
in this section are shaped to an important degree by unlearned biological factors. As
517
with sex differences in occupational preferences, however, it is not at all obvious why
518
this might be the case. Some evolutionary psychologists argue that sex differences in
519
spatial ability trace to the fact that Homo sapiens is an effectively polygynous species:
520
that is, a species in which males have somewhat greater reproductive variability than
521
females (Betzig, 2012; Labuda, Lefebvre, Nadeau, & Roy-Gagnon, 2010). In
522
polygynous species, the argument goes, males tend to have larger ranges than females,
523
and therefore tend to evolve stronger spatial and wayfaring skills (Gaulin, 1992). The
524
polygyny-related spatial sex difference may have been further amplified in our species
Men, Women, and Science 23
525
by the fact that human males are specialized for hunting and tracking animals, and
526
perhaps for engaging in coalitional warfare with neighboring groups (Silverman &
527
Phillips, 1998).
528
Many evolutionary psychologists are unpersuaded by these ideas, however. In
529
their view, cognitive sex differences were not specifically favored by natural
530
selection, but rather are byproducts of other differences that were. Clint, Sober,
531
Garland Jr, and Rhodes (2012) argue, for instance, that the male advantage in spatial
532
skills is simply an adaptively neutral side effect of hormonal sex differences that were
533
selected for other reasons. If this is right, then the spatial sex difference may have an
534
innate basis but not be a direct product of natural selection. At this stage, the ultimate
535
origins of human cognitive sex differences are uncertain. What does seem certain,
536
however, is that the differences are not solely a product of social forces. To some
537
extent – perhaps to an important extent – they are a part of human nature.
538 539 540
Sex Differences in Variability We see, then, that small mean differences in certain STEM-relevant aptitudes
541
result in somewhat more males than females occupying the right-hand tail of the
542
distribution (Reilly et al., 2015). However, even if there were no differences at the
543
mean, males could still outnumber females among the minority at the right-hand tail.
544
This is because males and females differ in another way as well. In a wide variety of
545
traits, males as a group are more variable than females: The male distribution is
546
slightly flatter, and stretches out somewhat further on both sides of the mean (see
547
Figure 2). This is the case for a range of physical traits, including birth weight, adult
548
weight, adult height, and running speed (Lehre, Lehre, Laake, & Danbolt, 2009),
549
average heart rate during exercise (Hossack & Bruce, 1982), daily energy expenditure
Men, Women, and Science 24
550
(Westerterp & Speakman, 2008; Yamauchi et al., 2007), basal metabolic rate
551
(Westerterp & Goran, 1997; Yamauchi et al., 2007), and various aspects of brain
552
structure (Ritchie et al., 2018). It also appears to be the case for a range of
553
psychological traits, including creativity (Karwowski et al., 2016), general knowledge
554
(Feingold, 1992), physical aggression (Archer & Mehdikhani, 2003), and at least four
555
of the Big 5 personality traits: extraversion, openness, agreeableness, and
556
conscientiousness (Borkenau, McCrae, & Terracciano, 2013). Of particular relevance
557
to the present topic, males appear to be more variable than females in a number of
558
cognitive traits relevant to STEM (Baye & Monseur, 2016; Feingold, 1992). In this
559
section, we discuss these differences and where they might have come from.
560
--------------------Insert Figure 2 about here--------------------
561 562
Figure 2. A fundamental sex difference in humans and many other animals: For a
563
wide range of traits, males are more variable than females. As such, although only a
564
small percentage of people occupy either extreme of the distribution, more males do
565
than females, even when the mean scores for both sexes are identical.
566 567
Variability in STEM-Relevant Cognitive Traits
568
To begin with, many studies have found greater variance among males in
569
specific cognitive capacities, including mathematical aptitude, spatial ability, and
Men, Women, and Science 25
570
science knowledge. In one classic paper, Hedges and Novell (1995) analyzed the
571
cognitive test scores of six large, nationally representative US samples, together
572
covering a 32-year period. They found that, for 35 out of the 37 tests examined in the
573
study, male variability was greater than female. Importantly, this included all the tests
574
of mathematics, spatial ability, mechanical reasoning, and science knowledge. In most
575
cases, sex differences in average scores were small. Nevertheless, because males were
576
more variable, they tended to outnumber females among the minority with especially
577
high scores. (An exception was reading comprehension, for which males outnumbered
578
females at the bottom, but females outnumbered males at the top.)
579
Similar results have been found in other nations and using other tests. For
580
example, in a large sample of UK students (N ≈ 320,000), Strand, Deary, and Smith
581
(2006) found that, although sex differences were small at the mean, males
582
outnumbered females at the top and the bottom of the distribution for both
583
quantitative and nonverbal reasoning; for verbal reasoning, in contrast, males
584
outnumbered females only at the bottom (see Lohman & Lakin, 2009, for a US
585
replication of this pattern). Likewise, analyses of OECD and IEA data indicate that, in
586
most countries for which data are available, males are more variable than females in
587
math, reading, and science (Baye & Monseur, 2016; Machin & Pekkarinen, 2008).
588
As well as greater male variability in specific cognitive aptitudes, males may
589
be more variable in general cognitive ability or IQ (Deary, Irwing, Der, & Bates,
590
2007; Feingold, 1992; Strand et al., 2006). The gold-standard study on this topic is
591
Johnson et al. (2008). Unlike earlier studies, which used potentially unrepresentative
592
samples, Johnson et al. utilized IQ data from two population-wide surveys of 11-year-
593
old school children in Scotland. As expected, IQ variability was greater among boys
594
than girls, such that there were more boys than girls at both extremes of the IQ
Men, Women, and Science 26
595
distribution: more at the top, but also more at the bottom (although see Iliescu, Ilie,
596
Ispas, Dobrean, and Clinciu, 2016, for a recent failure to replicate this pattern in a
597
large, nationally representative Romanian sample).
598
To the extent that greater male variability results in more males than females
599
occupying the upper echelons of ability, whether for specific aptitudes or general
600
cognitive ability, this may help to explain the preponderance of males in certain
601
STEM fields (Levy & Kimura, 2009; Steven Pinker, 2002). As Johnson et al. (2008)
602
observe, sex differences in cognitive variability are not large enough to explain the
603
entirety of the STEM gender gap. They may, however, be one more piece of the
604
puzzle. See Box 1 for further discussion.
605
--------------------Insert Box 1 about here--------------------
606 Box 1: Exploring the Implications of Greater Male Variability The claim that men are more variable than women in cognitive ability is controversial. Here are some questions to ask about this claim: 1. Is it sexist? Is it sexist even if it turns out to be true? 2. If it is sexist against women to say that there are somewhat more men than women at the highest levels of ability, is it sexist against men to say that there are also more men than women at the lowest levels? If not, how might we explain this asymmetry? 3. Assume for a moment that males really are more variable in cognitive ability. Should we suppress this information? Could we suppress it, even if we wanted to? 4. Might it be possible instead to emphasize the importance of avoiding exaggerating small average differences, of keeping sight of the variation among individuals within each sex, and of treating individuals as individuals, rather than as instantiations of the statistical properties of the groups to which they belong?
607
Men, Women, and Science 27
608
The Nature and Nurture of Sex Differences in Variability
609
What might explain sex differences in within-sex variability? Given that the
610
magnitude of the differences fluctuates somewhat across cultures and times, it is
611
unlikely that they are a product solely of biological factors (Feingold, 1992; Hyde,
612
Mertz, & Schekman, 2009). However, as with average differences in preferences and
613
aptitudes, several lines of evidence suggest that biological factors play a crucial role.
614
First, greater male variability is found not only in psychological traits, but in
615
traits that are largely impervious to socialization and cultural norms, such as height,
616
birth weight, and BMI (Lehre et al., 2009). The sex differences in psychological
617
variability thus appear to be part of a broader pattern. Considerations of both
618
parsimony and plausibility suggest that this pattern probably has a single, common
619
cause, rather than distinct causes for its physical and psychological components.
620
Second, sex differences in psychological variability emerge in early childhood.
621
The sex difference in IQ variability, for instance, appears before children begin school
622
(Arden & Plomin, 2006). This does not definitively rule out a Nurture Only
623
explanation for the difference. However, it does add some weight to the scales on the
624
biological side of the argument, and it reduces the range of non-biological factors that
625
any Nurture Only explanation can invoke. Whatever the ultimate causes of greater
626
male variability, those causes are in place by the age of three.
627
Third, sex differences in variability are not unique to humans, but are found in
628
many other species. Among red deer, for instance, males are not only larger than
629
females but are also more variable in size (Clutton-Brock, Guinness, & Albon, 1982);
630
among primates, males are more variable in lifespan (Colchero et al., 2016); among
631
guenons, males are more variable in skull size (Cardini & Elton, 2017); and among
632
barn swallows, males are more variable in tail-length (Møller, 1991; Safran &
Men, Women, and Science 28
633
McGraw, 2004). Examples of greater variability in females are notably less common.
634
When we find this pattern in other species, the only realistic explanation is a
635
biological one. When we then find the same pattern in our own species, considerations
636
of parsimony and plausibility again suggest that a biological explanation is
637
appropriate for us too. Indeed, without a strong reason to think otherwise, the default
638
assumption should be that humans fit within the same explanatory framework that
639
applies to the rest of the animal kingdom, and thus that greater male variability in our
640
species has the same root cause as that in our nonhuman kin.
641
Evolutionary Rationale
642
If sex differences in variability are due in large part to innate factors, how
643
might those factors have evolved? Once again, the answer is not yet certain, but
644
biologists have put forward a number of plausible suggestions. One popular
645
suggestion traces greater male variability in general to another, more fundamental sex
646
difference: greater male variability in reproductive success. As a result of sex
647
differences in parental investment, males in many species have greater variability than
648
females in the number of offspring they produce (Clutton-Brock & Vincent, 1991;
649
Trivers, 1972). At one extreme, some males have a very high number of offspring:
650
more than any female. At the other, because mating opportunities are finite, many
651
males have no offspring or very few. Most females, in contrast, fall somewhere in
652
between these extremes. In species where male reproductive variability is high,
653
selection favors any trait that increases a male’s chances of being among the few that
654
have many offspring, rather than the many that have few or none. One such trait
655
appears to be risk-proneness. In many species, selection has favored a greater
656
willingness among males to risk life and limb in the pursuit of status, resources, and
657
mating opportunities. Male risk-taking sometimes paid off and sometimes did not.
Men, Women, and Science 29
658
When it did pay off, however, it paid off so handsomely that, on average, risk-taking
659
males had more offspring than males who were more risk-averse. For females, in
660
contrast, risk-taking offered fewer reproductive advantages, because the ceiling
661
number of offspring for females is so much lower. Thus, males in many species
662
evolved a greater propensity to take risks than did females (Daly & Wilson, 2001).
663
According to one explanation of greater male variability, this calculus applies
664
not only to behaviour but to development: Male development is somewhat more “risk-
665
prone” than female development, such that males have a greater chance of developing
666
especially impressive traits but also a greater chance of developing less impressive
667
ones. The former males have a sufficiently high number of offspring that, on average,
668
males with the risky developmental program have more offspring than those with a
669
more conservative or risk-averse one. As such, the risky male developmental program
670
is selected – and with it, greater male variability (see, e.g., Pomiankowski & Møller,
671
1995; Rowe & Houle, 1996).
672
Might this apply to humans? Compared to most mammals, the human sex
673
difference in reproductive variability is rather modest (Stewart-Williams & Thomas,
674
2013). Nonetheless, genetic and anthropological data strongly suggest that there is
675
still a difference (Betzig, 2012; Labuda et al., 2010; summarized in M. L. Wilson,
676
Miller, & Crouse, 2017, Table 1). This plausibly resulted in the evolution of males
677
who were somewhat more risk-prone than their female counterparts, not just
678
behaviorally but developmentally. In other words, just as men evolved a riskier,
679
boom-or-bust behavioral strategy, so too they evolved a riskier, boom-or-bust
680
developmental strategy – one which sometimes pays off but sometimes backfires.
681
(For other evolutionary explanations of greater male variability, see, e.g., Archer &
682
Mehdikhani, 2003; Hill, 2018; Reinhold & Engqvist, 2013.)
Men, Women, and Science 30
683
Certainly, environmental forces may exert some influence on the size of the
684
variability gap (Hyde et al., 2009), perhaps enlarging it and perhaps sometimes
685
making it smaller. The basic pattern itself, however, is plausibly a part of our
686
evolutionary heritage – one that helps to shape the modern occupational landscape.
687 688 689
Discrimination We have now discussed three reasons why men and women might not be
690
equally represented in STEM, even if there were no discrimination. This does not
691
imply, of course, that there is no discrimination, or that discrimination is not one of
692
the factors shaping STEM gender gaps. Even if fewer women than men are interested
693
in working in math-intensive STEM fields, it could still be the case that those who are
694
interested face a hostile environment in the classroom and the workplace, are subject
695
to disparaging stereotypes and low expectations, and are less likely to be hired,
696
published, cited, or awarded grants than their male colleagues.
697
This is certainly a plausible suggestion; after all, no one denies that there was
698
considerable sexism in science prior to the second wave of the feminist movement,
699
and it might be unduly optimistic to think that this would evaporate entirely in little
700
more than half-a-century. At the same time, though, the discrimination hypothesis
701
represents a rather serious accusation against people working in STEM, and thus it is
702
only fair to look carefully at the evidence for and against the hypothesis. For the
703
reasons given already, gender disparities are not in themselves direct evidence of
704
discrimination; unless the sexes were psychologically identical, equality of
705
opportunity would almost certainly not translate into equality of outcomes (Steven
Men, Women, and Science 31
706
Pinker, 2002; Radcliffe Richards, 1980). Nonetheless, various lines of evidence do
707
bear on the question of how much discrimination remains in the world of STEM.3
708
Discrimination against Women in STEM
709
The most abundant source of objective evidence for sexism against women in
710
STEM comes from experimental studies looking at people’s reactions to hypothetical
711
applicants for STEM jobs. Otherwise identical job applications are given either a
712
female or a male name, and then evaluated by participants naïve to the purpose of the
713
study. In one widely cited paper in this genre, Moss-Racusin, Dovidio, Brescoll,
714
Graham, and Handelsman (2012) had science faculty from six major universities rate
715
applications for a laboratory manager position. They found that the raters – female
716
and male alike – gave higher ratings to supposedly male applicants than they did to
717
supposedly female ones. Specifically, participants rated the males as more competent
718
and hirable, and as deserving a higher salary. In another, earlier study, Steinpreis,
719
Anders, and Ritzke (1999) found that, for middling job applications, academic
720
psychologists – again, female and male alike – expressed greater willingness to hire a
721
male job candidate than an identical female one. For outstanding applications, in
722
contrast, there was no effect of gender.
723
Admittedly, both of these studies had a number of weaknesses, including the
724
fact that the samples included only 127 and 238 participants, respectively. However,
725
the findings are broadly consistent with a large body of research in this area. A meta-
726
analysis of studies looking at simulated employment decisions (N = 22,348) found a
727
weak pro-male bias in male-dominated fields (d = .13), although no gender bias in
3
Note that our discussion applies largely to the Western world, and especially the Anglophone world, as this is where most of the relevant research and commentary has focused. Note also that we limit the discussion to measures of bias other than self-report surveys (e.g., Funk & Parker, 2018), as the latter are vulnerable to complaints of subjectivity and expectation effects.
Men, Women, and Science 32
728
balanced or female-dominated fields (Koch, D'Mello, & Sackett, 2015). The meta-
729
analysis did not focus specifically on STEM-related decisions; however, given that
730
many STEM fields are male-dominated, the results nonetheless increase the
731
plausibility of the STEM-specific findings. Of course, even if those findings are valid,
732
it is not clear whether they generalize to real-world hiring decisions, where decision
733
makers have more experience and are more motivated to make the best choice.
734
Indeed, the Koch et al. meta-analysis showed that pro-male biases were attenuated in
735
just those circumstances, and fake-résumé experiments (in which fictitious job
736
applications are sent out in response to genuine job advertisements, and subsequent
737
call-backs counted) have yielded mixed results with respect to gender bias (Baert,
738
2018). Still, it is possible that bias plays a role in STEM hiring decisions, at least
739
sometimes, and this is something that every academic and STEM worker who cares
740
about gender equality and fairness should take extremely seriously.
741
Moreover, discrimination in hiring is not the only form of discrimination that
742
ought to concern us. Other studies have uncovered other possible examples of
743
discrimination, in STEM and in academia more generally. For example, professors are
744
less likely to respond to informal inquiries about a PhD program when the inquirer is
745
a woman or non-white (Milkman, Akinola, & Chugh, 2015); papers authored by
746
female economists need to be better written to be accepted into top-tier journals
747
(Hengel, 2017); male researchers are somewhat more likely to share their data and
748
published research with other males than with females (Massen, Bauer, Spurny,
749
Bugnyar, & Kret, 2017); and female academics less often give talks at prestigious US
750
universities, even controlling for the rank of the available speakers and even though
751
that women are no more likely to turn down an invitation (Nittrouer et al., 2017).
752
More egregious still, a Japanese medical school was recently accused of lowering
Men, Women, and Science 33
753
women’s scores on an entrance exam in order to reduce the number of women on their
754
program (Cyranoski, 2018). One might point to weaknesses in any particular study.
755
Nonetheless, the overall pattern of findings is disquieting, to say the least.
756
Challenges to the Discrimination Hypothesis
757
At the same time, a number of cautions and qualifications are necessary. First,
758
it is important to emphasize that discrimination is almost certainly not the entire story
759
when it comes to gender gaps in STEM. The gender bias demonstrated in
760
experimental hiring studies, for instance, tends to be relatively subtle, whereas the
761
gender gap in math-intensive STEM fields is relatively large. This implies that the
762
former is unlikely to be a complete explanation of the latter.
763
Furthermore, discrimination alone cannot readily explain why women are less
764
well represented in some fields than in others. Why would discrimination stop women
765
from going into math-intensive STEM fields such as physics and engineering, but not
766
into other prestigious, high-paying fields such as law, medicine, or veterinary science?
767
One might argue that math-intensive fields are particularly inhospitable to women, as
768
a result of the supposedly widespread stereotype that women are intellectually inferior
769
in mathematics. The problem with this idea, however, is that, until recently, many
770
people assumed that women were intellectually inferior in every area, but this did not
771
stop women from approaching parity with men in virtually every other desirable
772
occupation. Why would discrimination only hold women back in math-intensive
773
STEM fields? And why would it hold them back in math-intensive fields everywhere
774
in the world, rather than, say, math-intensive fields in the United States, psychology in
775
South Africa, and law in Scandinavia? Bias and discrimination fail to explain why
776
women are consistently underrepresented in some fields but not in others. In contrast,
Men, Women, and Science 34
777
sex differences in interests and cognitive specializations provide a straightforward
778
explanation of the pattern.
779
Not only does discrimination fail to explain all the data, but the evidence for
780
discrimination in STEM is actually weaker and more mixed than is often assumed.
781
Certainly, as we saw in the previous section, some studies find evidence of anti-
782
female discrimination in the sciences. At the same time, however, other studies fail to
783
find such discrimination, or find discrimination in favor of women (see, e.g., Baert,
784
2018; Bhattacharya, Kanaya, & Stevens, 2017; Blank, 1991; Breda & Hillion, 2016;
785
Lloyd, 1990; Lutter & Schröder, 2014; Miller & Wai, 2015; Riegle-Crumb, King, &
786
Moore, 2016; Veldkamp, Hartgerink, van Assen, & Wicherts, 2017). This raises the
787
possibility that our picture of the level and nature of discrimination in STEM is at
788
least somewhat distorted.
789
The most important voices on this issue are Stephen Ceci and Wendy
790
Williams. In their view, the idea that women are routinely discriminated against in
791
STEM, while true in earlier generations, is no longer true. The culture of science has
792
changed a great deal over the last half century, but people’s beliefs about that culture
793
have not kept pace with the change. Consider hiring practices. Real-world data
794
suggest that, although fewer women apply for math-intensive STEM jobs, those who
795
do are no less likely to be interviewed and no less likely to be offered the job. On the
796
contrary, they are often more likely to be (Ceci & Williams, 2011). This is the
797
opposite of what we would expect if there were pervasive anti-female bias in STEM.
798
If anything, it looks like there may be a pro-female bias, at least in the West.4
4
The situation in non-Western nations is less clear. In some cases, overt anti-female discrimination may still be prevalent (see, e.g., Cyranoski, 2018).
Men, Women, and Science 35
799
Of course, an alternative explanation would be that the female candidates tend
800
to be better than the males, perhaps because those few females who manage to survive
801
and thrive in male-dominated fields tend to be especially gifted. To determine whether
802
there really is a pro-female bias in STEM hiring, Williams and Ceci (2015) conducted
803
a large-scale hiring-decision study: the largest such study to date. The pair sent
804
hypothetical job applications to tenure-track professors in biology, economics,
805
engineering, and psychology, and asked them to assess the applicants’ suitability for a
806
tenure-track position. The final sample included nearly 900 professors from 371 US
807
universities. Averaging across conditions, Williams and Ceci found a 2:1 bias in favor
808
of female applicants. The pro-female bias was found in all four fields and among both
809
male and female faculty. (The only exception was male economics professors, who
810
showed no significant bias in either direction.) Thus, rather than being biased against
811
women, this study suggested that, when it comes to employment decisions, STEM
812
faculty appear to be biased in their favor.5
813
As well as finding little evidence of anti-female bias in hiring, Ceci and
814
Williams find little evidence of bias in promotion, publication, citation, or the
815
awarding of grants (Ceci et al., 2014; Ceci & Williams, 2011; see also Hechtman et
816
al., 2018). Studies that claim to find such bias are often widely discussed and cited
817
(see, e.g., Budden et al., 2008, on gender bias in acceptance rates for papers first-
818
authored by females,6 and van der Lee & Ellemers, 2015; Wennerås & Wold, 1997,
819
on gender bias in grant success). However, according to Ceci and Williams (2011), a
5
A comparable pro-female preference has also been documented outside STEM, in the Australian Public Services (Hiscox et al., 2017). Such findings are consistent with the idea that concerns about anti-female discrimination might sometimes overshoot and inadvertently produce anti-male discrimination instead. 6 Note that a reanalysis of the data by Webb, O’Hara, and Freckleton (2008) found that there was in fact no evidence of gender bias in the review process.
Men, Women, and Science 36
820
systematic review of all the available evidence suggests that deviations from gender
821
fairness are rare, and that they just as often favor women as men. Again, such results
822
are not what we would expect if anti-female bias were endemic.
823
To be clear, Ceci and Williams do not deny that women still face unique
824
challenges and hurdles in STEM. This includes, for example, the poor mesh between
825
the demands of a STEM career and the demands of motherhood – a point we come
826
back to later. But discrimination is no longer a major barrier. As Ceci and Williams
827
(2011) sum up the situation, “the ongoing focus on sex discrimination in reviewing,
828
interviewing and hiring represents costly, misplaced effort. Society is engaged in the
829
present in solving problems of the past” (p. 3157).
830
A Mixed Picture
831
It seems fair to say that the evidence for pervasive discrimination in STEM is
832
equivocal, with some studies finding pro-male bias (Cyranoski, 2018; Moss-Racusin
833
et al., 2012), some finding the reverse (Williams & Ceci, 2015), and some finding a
834
mixture of both (Breda & Hillion, 2016). What should we conclude? In our view,
835
there are two main interpretations. The first is that the apparently mixed findings are
836
not in fact inconsistent. Rather than there being uniform bias against women, or
837
uniform bias against men, there are pockets of bias against both sexes (and quite
838
possibly no gender bias at all at some institutions and in some cases). The second
839
interpretation is that, at this stage, the findings are simply inconclusive: The jury is
840
still out. But this in itself suggests that sex-based discrimination could not be hugely
841
prevalent in STEM; if it were, it would be easier to detect a clear signal and the
842
research would paint a more consistent picture of the situation. This, in turn, suggests
843
that factors other than discrimination are probably the primary explanation for the
844
persistence of gender gaps in STEM.
Men, Women, and Science 37
845
A Hidden Barrier to the Progress of Women in STEM
846
Before shifting topics, we should briefly consider another potential barrier to
847
the progress of women in STEM – one that often is overlooked: stereotypes of the
848
sexist academy. In the quest to promote women in STEM, academics and activists
849
may sometimes inadvertently overstate the ubiquity of bias and discrimination against
850
women in this sector. An unintended consequence may be to scare away some women
851
who would otherwise be interested in a STEM career (Sesardic & De Clercq, 2014;
852
Williams & Ceci, 2015). If women are given the impression that the STEM workplace
853
is a hotbed of sexism, and an unwelcome place for women, many might quite
854
understandably decide to look for other fields in which to make their mark. Ironically,
855
the consequent dearth of women in STEM might then itself be taken as further
856
evidence that STEM is a hotbed of sexism, creating a self-reinforcing, vicious cycle.
857
Needless to say, if the STEM workplace really were a hotbed of sexism, this
858
would be something we would need to confront, even if doing so put off some
859
budding female scientists. However, given that we have reasonable evidence that, for
860
the most part, science is fair for women, and that discrimination is the exception
861
rather than the rule, conveying such a dark image of the STEM workplace might do
862
more harm than good. See Figure 3 for a summary of the many factors contributing to
863
the gender gaps in STEM.
864
--------------------Insert Figure 3 about here--------------------
Men, Women, and Science 38
865 866
Figure 3: Occupational outcomes are a product of many different factors; workplace
867
discrimination is one among many.
868 869 870
Policy Options Sex differences in STEM representation are not just an academic matter. The
871
question of what should be done about these differences – or indeed whether anything
872
should be done – is one of the most widely discussed political issues related to the
873
modern academy. In this section, we look at some of the most important policy
874
prescriptions that have been mooted or implemented over recent years. The discussion
875
is not intended to be exhaustive, but rather aims to highlight broad trends and
876
commonly overlooked consequences of the policies in question. Table 1 provides an
877
overview.
878 879
--------------------Insert Table 1 about here--------------------
Men, Women, and Science 39
880
Table 1
881
Potential Unintended Consequences of Policy Interventions Aimed at Reducing
882
Gender Gaps in STEM Policy Outreach
Potential Unintended Consequences If handled poorly, may inadvertently put undue pressure on girls to pursue a STEM career or may send a discouraging message to boys.
Incentives for women to
Costly.
go into STEM
May push women to make choices less in line with their preferences and long-term interests. Arguably discriminatory against men.
Blinded evaluation of job
May result in fewer women being hired in certain STEM
applications
fields.
Diversity training
Tacit accusation of bias. Dubious efficacy, as quite possibly not targeting the primary causes of current STEM gaps. May sometimes backfire (i.e., increase bias).
Affirmative action and
Abandons the moral principle that we should avoid
quotas
discriminating on the basis of sex. Casts doubt on women’s genuine achievements. May strengthen the stereotype that women cannot succeed in science.
Family-Friendly Policies
If benefits offered to mothers only, may force some couples to avoid gender-atypical parenting arrangements,
Men, Women, and Science 40
even if they would prefer those arrangements. 883 884
Outreach
885
An initial, relatively uncontroversial intervention is outreach: educating
886
children and young people about science-related careers, and emphasizing that these
887
are careers that girls as well as boys should consider. Interventions of this kind would
888
not need to deny that there are average differences between the sexes in STEM-
889
relevant traits. On the contrary, average sex differences provide a strong argument in
890
favor of the interventions. After all, even if gender gaps in STEM representation are
891
primarily a result of sex differences in preferences, aptitudes, and variability, the mere
892
existence of those gaps could still help to sway the career choices of individuals
893
whose interests and talents buck the usual trend. In fields where the gender gap is
894
large, some girls and women who would otherwise pursue a science career might be
895
put off by the fact that many more men than women take that path (Dasgupta & Stout,
896
2014). That being the case, it may always be necessary to encourage and support these
897
individuals, and to encourage everyone else to accept atypical career choices and be
898
tolerant of individual differences. (Notice, incidentally, that the same argument would
899
presumably weigh just as strongly toward encouraging boys and men with atypical
900
career preferences to follow their interests as well.)
901
Of course, as with any intervention, there is a danger of creating harm as well
902
as good. One potential harm could come from outreach programs that focus on girls
903
alone: girls-only science workshops, for instance, or advertising campaigns that depict
904
girls but not boys engaged in science-related activities. Such interventions could
905
inadvertently convey the message to boys that they are no longer welcome in science,
906
and that if they choose to pursue a career in that area, they may face an uphill battle
Men, Women, and Science 41
907
due to institutional favoritism toward girls and women. Girls-only programs could
908
also risk losing the support of people who would otherwise be allies, but who worry
909
that the issue has been captured by a strain of gender politics more concerned about
910
eliminating sex differences than about opening the doors for all.
911
Another potential harm is that well-meaning efforts to encourage girls to
912
pursue careers in STEM could sometimes tip over into excessive pressure to take that
913
road. Susan Pinker (2008) interviewed women who had left successful STEM careers
914
to pursue careers in other areas. Many reported that, as girls and young adults, they
915
were so strongly encouraged to go into STEM that they ended up in jobs they did not
916
especially enjoy. In light of this potential pitfall, we suggest that the aim of outreach
917
efforts should not be to get women into science per se, but rather to give everyone
918
accurate information about STEM career options so that they can make an informed
919
choice about what would suit them best.
920
Incentives for Women to Go into STEM
921
A second type of intervention involves offering incentives to women to go into
922
male-dominated STEM fields. Examples include fee waivers, scholarships, and
923
monetary incentives for completing one’s training in a targeted area. As with
924
outreach, this is already a common practice, and it seems probable that the incentives
925
on offer would encourage more women to make gender-atypical choices (Navarra-
926
Madsen, Bales, & Hynds, 2010).
927
But although the incentives probably work, a number of arguments can be
928
leveled against this practice. One is that it discriminates on the basis of sex: It offers
929
advantages to some individuals but not others, purely on the basis of a fixed biological
930
attribute. Even leaving this aside, however, it is worth considering the wisdom of
931
devoting large amounts of resources to encouraging women to do something they
Men, Women, and Science 42
932
would not otherwise do. Although rarely described that way, this is clearly what the
933
practice amounts to – after all, if the targeted women did want to do it anyway, the
934
incentives would not be necessary. By interfering with women’s choices, it is possible
935
that immediate incentives could nudge some women away from options that might
936
suit them better in the longer term and which might ultimately make them happier.7
937
Certainly, people are not always right about what will make them happy. The
938
question, is though, whether those who call for incentives and other measures to help
939
shrink STEM gender gaps are more likely to be right – or whether women’s happiness
940
is the main motivation behind their efforts.
941
Blinded Evaluation
942
A third intervention is blinded evaluation of job applications, journal article
943
submissions, grant applications, and the like – in other words, removing any evidence
944
of the applicant or author’s sex before beginning the evaluation process. Where this
945
can be done, it is a relatively easy way to neutralize the potentially distorting effects
946
of demographic stereotypes. A possible criticism of the practice, at least as applied to
947
hiring decisions, is that it could only be implemented during the earliest stages of the
948
process: Gender can be concealed in a CV, but not in an interview or job talk.
949
Fortunately, however, a great deal of research suggests that stereotypes exert most of
950
their influence on person perception during those earliest stages, when perceivers
951
have little individuating information about the person being perceived (Koch et al.,
952
2015; Rubinstein, Jussim, & Stevens, 2018). As such, blinded evaluation could well
953
eliminate most of the biasing effects of demographic stereotypes. Another point in
7
To be clear, this is not because STEM does not suit women; clearly, it suits some but not others. The point is that the incentives may encourage some women who might be better suited to other areas to take the STEM option instead.
Men, Women, and Science 43
954
favor of the practice is that blinded evaluation automatically eliminates all forms of
955
bias, including not only anti-female bias but anti-male bias as well. Moreover, if there
956
is little bias in either direction, the policy would cost little and do little damage –
957
unlike some of the more heavy-handed interventions on offer.
958
Despite its many merits, however, blinded evaluation may prove to be a
959
politically unpopular option. If Ceci and Williams (2014; 2015) are right that women
960
are often favored rather than disfavored in science hiring, blinded evaluation of job
961
applications would presumably result in somewhat fewer women being hired than is
962
presently the case. Given the strong push toward increasing the numbers of women in
963
STEM, such an outcome is likely to rule against the policy. This is not just a
964
theoretical possibility; the Australian Public Services recently suspended a blinded
965
evaluation trial when they discovered that the practice slightly increased men’s
966
chances of getting hired, and slightly decreased women’s (Hiscox et al., 2017). Notice
967
that, in abandoning the trial, the policy makers effectively revealed that their goal is
968
equality of outcome rather than equality of opportunity.
969
Diversity Training
970
Another intervention aimed at tackling discrimination in STEM is diversity
971
training, also known as anti-bias training. Diversity training takes many forms, but the
972
common thread is the aim of increasing awareness and tolerance of diversity in the
973
workplace, and of helping people from different backgrounds to avoid bias and work
974
together harmoniously. The practice has become increasingly popular over the last
975
few decades, and is now a billion-dollar industry (Anand & Winters, 2008).
976
In spite of its popularity, though, a number of criticisms and concerns have
977
been raised regarding diversity training. To begin with, in its application to the STEM
978
gender gap, the enterprise is premised on the assumption that bias is the primary cause
Men, Women, and Science 44
979
– or at least a major cause – of the differential representation of men and women in
980
STEM. As we saw earlier, however, the evidence for endemic anti-female bias is
981
inconclusive, and the main cause of STEM gender gaps appears to be average sex
982
differences in people’s vocational preferences. This raises several issues with respect
983
to diversity training.
984
The first is ethical. To mandate diversity training is tacitly to accuse people of
985
bias – probabilistically if not in each individual case – which is a rather serious
986
accusation to level at people on the basis of conflicting and contested evidence. A
987
second issue is practical. If bias is no longer the main driver of the gender gaps in
988
STEM, then interventions targeting bias are unlikely to have a positive impact. And if
989
that is the case, then anti-bias training represents a considerable waste of resources –
990
resources that could otherwise be used more productively. Consistent with this
991
assessment, research on the efficacy of anti-bias training paints a mixed picture at
992
best. Several studies have concluded that the most popular anti-bias programs have
993
little impact on diversity outcomes (Dobbin, Kalev, & Kelly, 2007; Kalev, Dobbin, &
994
Kelly, 2006). Furthermore, in some cases, the programs may actually backfire,
995
increasing bias rather than reducing it (Duguid & Thomas-Hunt, 2015; Moss-Racusin
996
et al., 2014). Of course, it is possible that bias is still pervasive but that we have not
997
yet found effective interventions to tackle it. It is also possible, however, that the
998
programs are not targeting the real root causes of women’s lower representation in
999
politically progressive nations (Ceci & Williams, 2011).
1000
In discussing diversity training, it is worth paying special attention to the
1001
concept of implicit or unconscious bias. This concept has become central to diversity
1002
training over recent decades, based primarily on research using the Implicit
1003
Association Test or IAT, a putative measure of implicit bias. In the last few years,
Men, Women, and Science 45
1004
however, the IAT has come under increasing fire, and with it interventions aimed at
1005
thwarting implicit bias. The main criticisms are as follows: (1) The IAT produces
1006
inconsistent results for individuals. Its test-retest reliability is low (Gawronski,
1007
Morrison, Phills, & Galdi, 2017). (2) The IAT does a poor job of predicting
1008
discriminatory behavior (Oswald, Mitchell, Blanton, Jaccard, & Tetlock, 2015).
1009
Explicit bias is a better predictor. (3) Although it seems to be possible to change
1010
people’s implicit biases, the effects of such changes on behavior are trivially small or
1011
non-existent, even in the immediate wake of the intervention (Forscher et al., 2017).
1012
For all three reasons, it seems unlikely that diversity interventions targeting implicit
1013
bias represent a wise allocation of resources. Indeed, even one of the creators of the
1014
IAT, Anthony Greenwald, recommends against the use of interventions promising to
1015
eliminate implicit bias (cited in Lopez, 2017).
1016
Affirmative Action and Quotas
1017
Another, more heavy-handed strategy would be to implement a policy of
1018
affirmative action for women in science, or even a strict quota system. As discussed
1019
earlier, there is some reason to believe that this is already happening informally:
1020
Women appear to be preferentially hired in at least certain STEM fields (Ceci et al.,
1021
2014; Ceci & Williams, 2011). Some suggest, however, that this process should be
1022
formalized, and that more stringent rules about numbers of women ought to be
1023
established (see, e.g., Wallon, Bendiscioli, & Garfinkel, 2015).8 Among the most
1024
common arguments for affirmative action and quotas are that these policies would
1025
provide a counterweight to existing biases, compensate for past injustices, break the
1026
cultural “habit” of male-dominance in certain areas, increase the pool of same-sex role
8
Indeed, in some countries, this is happening already; the Max Plank institute in Germany, for example, offers jobs that only women can apply for (Max Plank Society, 2017).
Men, Women, and Science 46
1027
models available to girls and women, and increase the diversity of available
1028
perspectives.
1029
Some of these goals seem self-evidently desirable; others are topics of debate.
1030
However, even if we were to accept the desirability of all the goals, there are reasons
1031
to be wary of affirmative action as a means of achieving them, especially if this
1032
involves quotas that depart markedly from existing sex ratios. To begin with, there is
1033
an ethical question. Pro-female favoritism represents an explicit rejection of the
1034
principle of equality of opportunity in favor of discrimination on the basis of sex:
1035
precisely what feminism originally set out to overcome. As the philosopher Janet
1036
Radcliffe-Richards (1980) observed, the moral foundation of the women’s liberation
1037
movement – and indeed of all liberation movements – is the idea that people should
1038
be treated fairly and equitably, and that unjust barriers should be dismantled. A policy
1039
that advantages one demographic group over another necessarily abandons those
1040
ideals. In doing so, it risks leaving the women’s movement without its moral
1041
foundation, thereby reducing the issue to a mere power struggle between competing
1042
groups, rather than a matter of principle.
1043
Certainly, throughout history, men were often advantaged over women in a
1044
similarly unprincipled way. It is not clear, however, why any individual woman today
1045
should be advantaged over any individual man, simply because other men were
1046
advantaged over other women in the past. Reversing historical injustices does not
1047
erase them; it merely adds to the total number of injustices in the world. The question
1048
we face today, therefore, is this: Is the appropriate response to injustice to eliminate it,
1049
or simply to turn it on its head?
1050 1051
Of course, one might argue that affirmative action for women in STEM would not in fact be unjust; instead, the policy would help to equalize men and women’s
Men, Women, and Science 47
1052
chances of advancing in STEM, which are presently unequal due to anti-female
1053
discrimination. As mentioned, however, the evidence for pervasive discrimination in
1054
STEM is equivocal, with some studies suggesting that, at least in some ways, women
1055
are favored over men. Given that advantaging one demographic group over another is
1056
not an ethically trivial act, we should insist on much stronger evidence before
1057
enacting such a policy.
1058
Moreover, it is not only men who might be harmed by affirmative action. In a
1059
number of ways, women themselves could be harmed as well. To begin with,
1060
affirmative action policies may cast a shadow of doubt over women’s genuine
1061
accomplishments. If such policies become widespread, then whenever women win
1062
jobs, grants, or awards, people may find themselves wondering – secretly and despite
1063
their best intentions – whether the women in question were judged by a lower
1064
standard, simply because of their sex (a rather sexist practice in itself, one might
1065
argue). This is not just a pitfall for onlookers; successful women themselves might
1066
end up harboring doubts about their own achievements. As the physicist Stephanie
1067
Meyer (2015) once put it: “How am I supposed to build confidence if I never know
1068
whether I earned my success? Women scientists already suffer from imposter
1069
syndrome; practices that make us think we may be given unearned advantage aren’t
1070
helpful.”
1071
As well as casting doubt on the success of individual women, affirmative
1072
action could harm the image of women in STEM more generally. One of the primary
1073
goals of the women-in-STEM movement has been to eliminate the pernicious and
Men, Women, and Science 48
1074
demonstrably false stereotype that women cannot succeed in science.9 Affirmative
1075
action policies are unlikely to contribute to that project. On the contrary, the policies
1076
may bolster the stereotype. Aside from the fact that they seem to imply that women in
1077
science need the extra help, strong preferences could lower the average level of
1078
performance of women working in STEM. This is not because any individual woman
1079
would perform any worse, but rather is a simple statistical consequence of the fact that
1080
the pool of female STEM candidates is smaller than that of the males. As Figure 4
1081
shows, if equal numbers of top performers are drawn from two samples, but one of
1082
those samples is smaller than the other, the mean level of ability of those from the
1083
smaller sample will necessarily be lower than that from the larger, even if the means
1084
and variances of the two samples are identical. In effect, equalizing the number of
1085
individuals taken from each group would mean lowering the minimum standard for
1086
the smaller group. For less stringent quotas, the minimum standard would not need to
1087
be lowered as much. Nonetheless, it would still need to be lowered.
1088
--------------------Insert Figure 4 about here--------------------
1089
1090
9
Note that we appear to be making slow but steady progress toward this goal (Miller, Nolla, Eagly, & Uttal, 2018).
Men, Women, and Science 49
1091
Figure 4. If equal or similar numbers of top performers are drawn from samples of
1092
different sizes, the average level of ability of those drawn from the smaller sample
1093
will be lower than that of those drawn from the larger. This is the case even if the
1094
means and standard deviations of the two groups are identical.
1095 1096
This could have damaging consequences for women. In the absence of
1097
affirmative action, a person’s sex tells you little about their probable STEM abilities:
1098
Any woman who has been accepted to a given university, or secured a job at a given
1099
institution, is likely to be just as talented as any man at the same university or in the
1100
same institution. However, if strong affirmative action policies are enacted, sex
1101
suddenly does tell you something about women’s probable STEM abilities: It tells
1102
you that they might not necessarily be as good (cf. Haidt & Jussim, 2016). Again, this
1103
is not because women cannot succeed in STEM – some can and some cannot, just like
1104
men. Instead, it is an inevitable consequence of the fact that enacting strong
1105
preferences for members of a smaller group necessarily means lowering the minimum
1106
standard by which members of that group are judged.
1107
Family-Friendly Policies
1108
A final proposal is that STEM career paths could be reconfigured in ways that
1109
would make them more family-friendly. This is a view that Ceci and Williams (2010,
1110
2011) have championed. In their estimation, one of the main remaining barriers to
1111
career success for women in STEM is the incompatibility of jobs in this area with the
1112
demands of motherhood. Not only do women alone get pregnant and nurse their
1113
young, but women are more likely than men to take time out from their careers to care
1114
for their young children. Nowhere is the clash between motherhood and STEM more
Men, Women, and Science 50
1115
apparent than with regard to the academic tenure system in the United States. As Ceci
1116
and Williams (2010) put it:
1117 1118
The tenure structure in academe demands that women having children make their greatest
1119
intellectual contributions contemporaneously with their greatest physical and emotional
1120
achievements, a feat not expected of men. When women opt out of full-time careers to have
1121
and rear children, this is a choice – constrained by biology – that men are not required to
1122
make. (p. 278)
1123 1124
It is worth pointing out that the family-friendliness of STEM jobs varies a
1125
great deal from nation to nation, and that the lack of family-friendly policies would
1126
not explain why women are less well represented in math-intensive fields than in
1127
others. Nonetheless, finding ways to make STEM occupations more compatible with
1128
parenthood could help to level the playing field in math-intensive and non-math-
1129
intensive fields alike. Suitable policies might include increasing the flexibility of the
1130
window in which academics are able to complete the requirements of tenure, and
1131
increasing the provision of subsidized childcare.
1132
Of course, some might take issue with the “assumption” that women are the
1133
primary caregivers for their young. But this is not an assumption in any normative
1134
sense; it is simply an observation about what tends to happen. And given that it is
1135
what tends to happen - and that it is not something we know how to change, even if it
1136
were ethically acceptable to do so – family-friendly policies might help to equalize
1137
men and women’s opportunities by removing a barrier that faces more women than
1138
men. Furthermore, if enacted in a gender neutral way, such that mothers or fathers
1139
could avail themselves of any parental benefits, the policies would not exert any
1140
special pressure on women to take the primary caregiver role. Either sex could take it,
Men, Women, and Science 51
1141
if they so desired (although see Antecol, Bedard, & Stearns, in press, on possible
1142
unintended consequences of such policies).
1143 1144 1145
Levelling the Playing Field vs. Equalizing Sex Ratios Having considered a range of possible policy interventions, we should now
1146
step back and ask another, more fundamental question: What should the ultimate goal
1147
of these interventions be? Should we strive for a 50:50 sex ratio in every profession
1148
where one sex currently dominates? Or should we strive instead simply to eliminate
1149
bias and equalize people’s opportunities, then let the cards fall where they may?
1150
If men and women were identical in their aptitudes and aspirations, these
1151
would quite possibly amount to the same thing: Levelling the playing field would
1152
automatically result in a 50:50 sex ratio. Given, however, that men and women are not
1153
identical in their aptitudes and aspirations, we have no reason to expect gender parity,
1154
even under conditions of perfect fairness. On the contrary, the natural expectation
1155
would be that men and women would not be at parity, but rather that men would be
1156
more common in some fields, and women in others, as a result of their freely made
1157
choices. To the extent that this is the case, it becomes much more difficult to justify
1158
pursuing a 50:50 sex ratio in every field. Most women do not want a career in science
1159
and nor do most men. Why should the small fraction of women who do want such a
1160
career be the same size as the small fraction of men? To put it another way, as long as
1161
everyone has the opportunity to pursue a STEM career, and as long as the selection
1162
process is fair, why would it be important to get as many women as men into jobs that
1163
fewer women want?
Men, Women, and Science 52
1164
The Pursuit of Happiness
1165
One way to start tackling this question is to observe that a 50:50 sex ratio in all
1166
STEM fields is not actually a good in itself, but is only a good to the extent that it
1167
increases aggregate happiness and social wellbeing. Importantly, though, to the degree
1168
that occupational disparities are a product of men and women acting on their own
1169
preferences and pursuing their own best interests, it is doubtful that forcing a 50:50
1170
sex ratio would actually achieve these ends.
1171
To begin with, men and women could have different life outcomes, but still be
1172
happy with their lives. One longitudinal study found that, among two cohorts of
1173
individuals identified as academically gifted as children, men and women had
1174
somewhat different aspirations and took somewhat different paths, but ended up
1175
similarly happy with their careers, their relationships, and their lives overall (Lubinski
1176
et al., 2014). Thus, even among those best positioned to achieve their life ambitions,
1177
occupational gender parity appears not to be necessary for happiness.
1178
Not only might it not be necessary, but policies that artificially engineer
1179
gender parity – financial incentives and quotas, for instance – could potentially lower
1180
aggregate happiness. To the extent that these policies work, they necessarily mean
1181
that some people will be funneled into occupations that are less in line with their
1182
tastes and talents. To get more women into university physics programs, for instance,
1183
would require persuading at least some women to choose that option when they
1184
otherwise would not have done so. (At the same time, unless enrolment numbers were
1185
increased, it would also mean turning away some men who otherwise would have.)
1186
The women in question presumably would not come from the ranks of housewives or
1187
secretaries; more than likely they would be women who would otherwise have gone
1188
into other, equally prestigious fields, such as law or medicine. Is there any reason to
Men, Women, and Science 53
1189
think that these women would be happier doing physics? Given that people tend to
1190
make the decisions they think will suit them best and be most satisfying for them, it
1191
seems plausible to think that, on average, they might be somewhat less happy. Again,
1192
people are not always right about what will make them happy. What reason, though,
1193
do we have to think that STEM policymakers are more likely to be right? What reason
1194
do we have to think that third-parties – academics, activists, and politicians – have a
1195
better idea than women themselves about what choices women should make?10
1196
Admittedly, this whole line of argument is premised on the assumption that
1197
our aim as a society should be to maximize happiness, and some might reject that
1198
assumption. Anyone who does, though, should be expected to make a strong case for
1199
their position. Why should we put a statistical, collective goal – i.e., more equal sex
1200
ratios in STEM – above the happiness and autonomy of the flesh-and-blood
1201
individuals who constitute those collectives? Why should policymakers’ preference
1202
for gender parity take precedence over individual men and women’s preferences
1203
regarding their own careers and lives?
1204
Sex Differences as a Sign of Social Health
1205
A recurring theme of discussions of occupational gender disparities is the
1206
often-unspoken assumption that sex differences are inherently problematic, or that
1207
they constitute direct evidence of sexism and the curbing of women’s opportunities.
1208
Some research, however, points to the opposite conclusion. A growing body of
1209
evidence suggests that, in nations with greater wealth and higher levels of gender
1210
equality, sex differences are often larger than they are in less wealthy, less equal
1211
nations. This is true for a wide range of variables, including attachment styles, the Big
10
One might also argue that, even if policymakers did have a better idea, they would still have no right in a free society to interfere with women’s choices (or with men’s).
Men, Women, and Science 54
1212
Five personality traits, choice of academic speciality and occupation, crying,
1213
depression, enjoyment of casual sex, intimate partner violence, mathematical ability,
1214
mental rotation, self-esteem, subjective wellbeing, and values (summarized in
1215
Schmitt, 2015). Importantly, it is also true of objectively measurable traits such as
1216
height, BMI, and blood pressure, which gives us some reason to think that the pattern
1217
is not simply a product of cross-cultural differences in the ways that people answer
1218
questionnaires or take tests.
1219
What, then, is the cause of the pattern? One possibility is that when people are
1220
free to develop relatively unrestrainedly, nascent differences between individuals –
1221
and average differences between the sexes – have more opportunity to emerge and
1222
grow. In the case of psychological traits, the suggestion would be that men and
1223
women in wealthier, more developed nations have greater freedom to pursue what
1224
interests them and to nurture their own individuality. This freedom may, in turn, result
1225
in larger psychological sex differences (Schmitt, Realo, Voracek, & Allik, 2008).
1226
Regardless of the explanation, though, if certain sex differences are larger in
1227
societies with better social indicators, then rather than being products of a sexist or
1228
oppressive society, these differences may be indicators of the opposite: a
1229
comparatively free and fair one (Sommers, 2013). If so, this casts society’s efforts to
1230
eradicate the sex differences in an entirely new light. Rather than furthering gender
1231
equality, such efforts may involve attacking a positive symptom of gender equality.
1232
By mistaking the fruits of our freedom for evidence of oppression, we may institute
1233
policies that, at best, burn up time and resources in a futile effort to cure a
1234
misdiagnosed disease, and at worst actively limit people’s freedom to pursue their
1235
own interests and ambitions on a fair and level playing field.
Men, Women, and Science 55
1236
The Sexist Assumption Underlying the Demand for Parity
1237
Finally, the strong emphasis on increasing the numbers of women in male-
1238
dominated fields is arguably somewhat sexist. As Susan Pinker (2008) points out, it
1239
tacitly assumes that women do not know what they want, or that they want the wrong
1240
things and thus that wiser third-parties need to “fix” their existing preferences.
1241
Furthermore, it tacitly assumes that the areas in which men dominate are superior. The
1242
psychologist Denise Cummins (2015) put the point well when she observed that, “The
1243
hidden assumption underlying the push to eliminate gender gaps in traditionally male-
1244
dominated fields is that such fields are intrinsically more important and more valuable
1245
to society than fields that traditionally attract more women.” Given that traditionally
1246
female-dominated fields include education, healthcare, and social care, this
1247
assumption is not only sexist; it is also clearly false. As Judith Kleinfeld observed:
1248 1249
We should not be sending [gifted] women the message that they are less worthy human
1250
beings, less valuable to our civilization, lazy or low in status, if they choose to be teachers
1251
rather than mathematicians, journalists rather than physicists, lawyers rather than engineers.
1252
(cited in Steven Pinker, 2002, p. 359)
1253 1254
Certainly, many female-dominated fields pay less, on average, than male-
1255
dominated STEM fields.11 There is a great deal of debate about the reasons for this,
1256
and the extent to which it is a product of sexism vs. the fact that, on average, women
1257
view pay as a less important consideration in choosing a career than do men, and see
1258
things such as job security and flexible work hours as more important (see, e.g.,
11
Note that this is not always the case. Various non-STEM professions, including law, medicine, and pharmacy, pay considerably more than STEM, and now attract more women than men (Susan Pinker, 2010).
Men, Women, and Science 56
1259
Lubinski et al., 2014; Redmond & McGuinness, 2017). Such matters are beyond the
1260
scope of this article. We would point out, however, that even if sexism were the entire
1261
explanation for current pay disparities, the most appropriate solution would
1262
presumably be to strive for fair pay in female-dominated fields, not to try to get more
1263
women into fields that pay more but which, on average, they find less appealing. And
1264
to the extent that the explanation is that women place less weight on a high income in
1265
choosing a career, efforts to get women to prioritize income tacitly assume, once
1266
again, that women’s existing priorities are misguided, and that they ought to adopt
1267
more male-typical priorities instead.
1268
To be clear, we entirely agree that we should try to root out sexism wherever it
1269
still lurks, and tear down any lingering barriers to the progress of women in STEM (as
1270
well as any barriers to the progress of men). These are eminently good goals.
1271
However, for the reasons discussed, a 50:50 sex ratio is not a good goal.
1272 1273
Conclusion: Many Factors at Play
1274
In summary, any exhaustive discussion of the relative dearth of women in
1275
certain STEM fields must take into account the burgeoning science of human sex
1276
differences. If we assume that men and women are psychologically indistinguishable,
1277
then any disparities between the sexes in STEM will be seen as evidence of
1278
discrimination, leading to the perception that STEM is highly discriminatory. Such a
1279
perception, however, is almost certainly false. A large body of research points to the
1280
following three conclusions:
1281 1282
(1) that men and women differ, on average, in their occupational preferences, aptitudes, and
1283
levels of within-sex variability;
Men, Women, and Science 57 1284
(2) that these differences are not due solely to sociocultural causes but have a substantial
1285
innate component; and
1286
(3) that these differences, coupled with the demands of bearing and rearing children, are the
1287
main source of the gender disparities we find in STEM today. Discrimination appears to play a
1288
smaller role, and in some cases may favor women, rather than disfavoring them.
1289 1290
These conclusions have important implications for the way we handle STEM
1291
sex differences. Based on the foregoing discussion, we suggest that the approach that
1292
would be most conducive to maximizing individual happiness and autonomy would
1293
be to strive for equality of opportunity, but then to respect men and women’s
1294
decisions regarding their own lives and careers, even if this does not result in gender
1295
parity across all fields. Approaches that focus instead on equality of outcomes –
1296
including quotas and affirmative action – may exact a toll in terms of individual
1297
happiness. To the extent that these policies override people’s preferences, they
1298
effectively place the goal of equalizing the statistical properties of groups above the
1299
happiness and autonomy of the individuals within those groups. Moreover, policies
1300
aimed at achieving equality of outcomes necessarily involve abandoning one of the
1301
principles that made the women’s movement possible in the first place: the principle
1302
that we should treat all people fairly and avoid discriminating on the basis of sex.
1303
Some might derive different conclusions from the emerging understanding of human
1304
sex differences. Either way, though, it seems hard to deny that this understanding
1305
should be factored into the discussion.
1306
Men, Women, and Science 58
1307
References
1308 1309 1310 1311 1312 1313 1314 1315 1316 1317 1318 1319 1320 1321 1322 1323 1324 1325 1326 1327 1328 1329 1330 1331 1332 1333 1334 1335 1336 1337 1338 1339 1340 1341 1342 1343 1344 1345 1346 1347 1348 1349 1350 1351 1352 1353 1354 1355
Alexander, G. M., & Hines, M. (2002). Sex differences in response to children's toys in nonhuman primates (Cercopithecus aethiops sabaeus). Evolution and Human Behavior, 23, 467-479. Anand, R., & Winters, M.-F. (2008). A retrospective view of corporate diversity training from 1964 to the present. Academy of Management Learning and Education, 7, 356-372. Andersson, M. (1994). Sexual selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Antecol, H., Bedard, K., & Stearns, J. (in press). Equal but inequitable: Who benefits from gender-neutral tenure clock stopping policies? American Economic Review. Archer, J., & Mehdikhani, M. (2003). Variability among males in sexually selected attributes. Review of General Psychology, 7, 219-236. Arden, R., & Plomin, R. (2006). Sex differences in variance of intelligence across childhood. Personality and Individual Differences, 41, 39-48. Auyeung, B., Baron-Cohen, S., Chapman, E., Knickmeyer, R., Taylor, K., & Hackett, G. (2006). Foetal testosterone and the child systemizing quotient. European Journal of Endocrinology, 155, S123-S130. Baert, S. (2018). Hiring discrimination: An overview of (almost) all correspondence experiments since 2005. In S. M. Gaddis (Ed.), Audit studies: Behind the scenes with theory, method, and nuance (pp. 63-77). Cham, Switzerland: Springer. Bando, R., López Bóo, F., & Li, X. (2016). Sex differences in language and socioemotional skills in early childhood. IDB Working Paper Series IDB-WP-714. Baron-Cohen, S. (2003). The essential difference: Male and female brains and the truth about autism. New York: Basic Books. Baron-Cohen, S., Cassidy, S., Auyeung, B., Allison, C., Achoukhi, M., Robertson, S., . . . Lai, M.-C. (2014). Attenuation of typical sex differences in 800 adults with autism vs. 3,900 controls. PLOS ONE, 9, e102251. Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Hill, J., Raste, Y., & Plumb, I. (2001). The "Reading the Mind in the Eyes" Test revised version: A study with normal adults, and adults with Asperger syndrome or high-functioning autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42, 241-251. Baye, A., & Monseur, C. (2016). Gender differences in variability and extreme scores in an international context. Large-scale Assessments in Education, 4. Beltz, A., Swanson, J., & Berenbaum, S. (2011). Gendered occupational interests: Prenatal androgen effects on psychological orientation to Things versus People. Hormones and Behavior, 60, 313-317. Benbow, C. P. (1988). Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability in intellectually talented preadolescents: Their nature, effects, and possible causes. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11, 169-183. Benbow, C. P., Lubinski, D., Shea, D. L., & Eftekhari-Sanjani, H. (2000). Sex differences in mathematical reasoning ability at age 13: Their status 20 years later. Psychological Science, 11, 474-480. Berenbaum, S. A., & Beltz, A. M. (2011). Sexual differentiation of human behavior: Effects of prenatal and pubertal organizational hormones. Frontiers in Neuroendocrinology, 32, 183-200. Betzig, L. (2012). Means, variances, and ranges in reproductive success: Comparative evidence. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, 309-317.
Men, Women, and Science 59
1356 1357 1358 1359 1360 1361 1362 1363 1364 1365 1366 1367 1368 1369 1370 1371 1372 1373 1374 1375 1376 1377 1378 1379 1380 1381 1382 1383 1384 1385 1386 1387 1388 1389 1390 1391 1392 1393 1394 1395 1396 1397 1398 1399 1400 1401 1402 1403 1404 1405
Bhattacharya, D., Kanaya, S., & Stevens, M. (2017). Are university admissions academically fair? Review of Economics and Statistics, 99, 449-464. Blank, R. M. (1991). The effects of double-blind versus single-blind reviewing: Experimental evidence from the American Economic Review. American Economic Review, 81, 1041-1067. Borkenau, P., McCrae, R. R., & Terracciano, A. (2013). Do men vary more than women in personality? A study in 51 cultures. Journal of Research in Personality, 47, 135-144. Breda, T., & Hillion, M. (2016). Teaching accreditation exams reveal grading biases favor women in male-dominated disciplines in France. Science, 353, 474-478. Budden, A. E., Tregenza, T., Aarssen, L. W., Koricheva, J., Leimu, R., & Lortie, C. J. (2008). Double-blind review favours increased representation of female authors. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23, 4-6. Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (1993). Sexual strategies theory: An evolutionary perspective on human mating. Psychological Review, 100, 204-232. Byrnes, J. P., Miller, D. C., & Schafer, W. D. (1999). Gender differences in risk taking: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 367-383. Cardini, A., & Elton, S. (2017). Is there a “Wainer’s rule”? Testing which sex varies most as an example analysis using GueSDat, the free Guenon Skull Database. Hystrix, the Italian Journal of Mammalogy, 28, 147-156. Cashdan, E., Marlowe, F. W., Crittenden, A., Porter, C., & Wood, B. M. (2012). Sex differences in spatial cognition among Hadza foragers. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, 274-284. Ceci, S. J., Ginther, D. K., Kahn, S., & Williams, W. M. (2014). Women in academic science: A changing landscape. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 15, 75-141. Ceci, S. J., & Williams, W. M. (2010). Sex differences in math-intensive fields. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 19, 275-279. Ceci, S. J., & Williams, W. M. (2011). Understanding current causes of women’s underrepresentation in science. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 3157-3162. Ceci, S. J., Williams, W. M., & Barnett, S. M. (2009). Women's underrepresentation in science: Sociocultural and biological considerations. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 218-261. Chachra, D. (2017). To reduce gender biases, acknowledge them. Nature, 548, 373. Chapman, E., Baron-Cohen, S., Auyeung, B., Knickmeyer, R., Taylor, K., & Hackett, G. (2006). Fetal testosterone and empathy: Evidence from the Empathy Quotient (EQ) and the "Reading the Mind in the Eyes" Test. Social Neuroscience, 1, 135-148. Clint, E. K., Sober, E., Garland Jr, T., & Rhodes, J. S. (2012). Male superiority in spatial navigation: Adaptation or side effect? Quarterly Review of Biology, 87, 289-313. Clutton-Brock, T. H., Guinness, F. E., & Albon, S. D. (Eds.). (1982). Red deer: Behaviour and ecology of two sexes. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Clutton-Brock, T. H., & Vincent, A. C. J. (1991). Sexual selection and the potential reproductive rates of males and females. Nature, 351, 58-60. Colchero, F., Rau, R., Jones, O. R., Barthold, J. A., Conde, D. A., Lenart, A., . . . Vaupel, J. W. (2016). The emergence of longevous populations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.
Men, Women, and Science 60
1406 1407 1408 1409 1410 1411 1412 1413 1414 1415 1416 1417 1418 1419 1420 1421 1422 1423 1424 1425 1426 1427 1428 1429 1430 1431 1432 1433 1434 1435 1436 1437 1438 1439 1440 1441 1442 1443 1444 1445 1446 1447 1448 1449 1450 1451 1452 1453 1454
Connellan, J., Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Batki, A., & Ahluwalia, J. (2000). Sex differences in human neonatal social perception. Infant Behavior and Development, 23, 113-118. Cummins, D. (2015). Why the STEM gender gap is overblown. PBS.org. Retrieved 22 March, 2018, from https://www.pbs.org/newshour/nation/truth-womenstem-careers Cyranoski, D. (2018). Japanese university investigates claim that it downgraded women’s test scores. Nature. Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (2001). Risk-taking, intrasexual competition, and homicide. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 47, 1-36. Damore, J. (2017). Google's ideological echo chamber: How bias clouds our thinking about diversity and inclusion. Internet Archive. Retrieved 1 March, 2018, from https://web.archive.org/web/20170809220001/https://diversitymemo-static.s3us-west-2.amazonaws.com/Googles-Ideological-Echo-Chamber.pdf Dasgupta, N., & Stout, J. G. (2014). Girls and women in science, technology, engineering, and mathematics: STEMing the tide and broadening participation in STEM careers. Policy Insights from the Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 21-29. Deaner, R. O. (2013). Distance running as an ideal domain for showing a sex difference in competitiveness. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 42, 413-428. Deary, I. J., Irwing, P., Der, G., & Bates, T. C. (2007). Brother-sister differences in the g factor in intelligence: Analysis of full, opposite-sex siblings from the NLSY1979. Intelligence, 35, 451-456. Dobbin, F., Kalev, A., & Kelly, E. (2007). Diversity management in corporate America. Contexts, 6, 21-27. Duguid, M. M., & Thomas-Hunt, M. C. (2015). Condoning stereotyping? How awareness of stereotyping prevalence impacts expression of stereotypes. Journal of Applied Psychology, 100, 343-359. Eagly, A. H. (1995). The science and politics of comparing men and women. American Psychologist, 50, 145-158. Else-Quest, N. M., Hyde, J. S., & Linn, M. C. (2010). Cross-national patterns of gender differences in mathematics: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 136, 103-127. Feingold, A. (1992). Sex differences in variability in intellectual abilities: A new look at an old controversy. Review of Educational Research, 61, 61-84. Ferriman, K., Lubinski, D., & Benbow, C. P. (2009). Work preferences, life values, and personal views of top math/science graduate students and the profoundly gifted: Developmental changes and gender differences during emerging adulthood and parenthood. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 517-532. Finnigan, K. M., & Corker, K. S. (2016). Do performance avoidance goals moderate the effect of different types of stereotype threat on women’s math performance? Journal of Research in Personality, 63, 36-43. Flore, P. C., & Wicherts, J. M. (2015). Does stereotype threat influence performance of girls in stereotyped domains? A meta-analysis. Journal of School Psychology, 53, 25-44. Flores-Mendoza, C., Widaman, K. F., Rindermann, H., Primi, R., Mansur-Alves, M., & Pena, C. C. (2013). Cognitive sex differences in reasoning tasks: Evidence from Brazilian samples of educational settings. Intelligence, 41, 70-84.
Men, Women, and Science 61
1455 1456 1457 1458 1459 1460 1461 1462 1463 1464 1465 1466 1467 1468 1469 1470 1471 1472 1473 1474 1475 1476 1477 1478 1479 1480 1481 1482 1483 1484 1485 1486 1487 1488 1489 1490 1491 1492 1493 1494 1495 1496 1497 1498 1499 1500 1501 1502 1503
Forscher, P. S., Lai, C. K., Axt, J. R., Ebersole, C. R., Herman, M., Devine, P. G., & Nosek, B. A. (2017). A meta-analysis of change in implicit bias. PsyArXiv. Funk, C., & Parker, K. (2018). Women and men in STEM often at odds over workplace equity. Washington, DC: Pew Research Center. Gaulin, S. J. C. (1992). Evolution of sex-differences in spatial ability. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 35, 125-151. Gawronski, B., Morrison, M., Phills, C. E., & Galdi, S. (2017). Temporal stability of implicit and explicit measures: A longitudinal analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 43, 300-312. Geary, D. C. (2010). Male, female: The evolution of human sex differences (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Gino, F., Wilmuth, C. A., & Brooks, A. W. (2015). Compared to men, women view professional advancement as equally attainable, but less desirable. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112, 12354-12359. Guiso, L., Monte, F., Sapienza, P., & Zingales, L. (2008). Culture, gender, and math. Science, 320, 1164-1165. Haidt, J., & Jussim, L. (2016). Hard truths about race on campus. Wall Street Journal. Retrieved 22 March, 2018, from https://www.wsj.com/articles/hard-truthsabout-race-on-campus-1462544543 Hakim, C. (2005). Sex differences in work-life balance goals. In D. M. Houston (Ed.), Work-Life Balance in the 21st Century (pp. 55-79). London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Halpern, D. F. (2012). Sex differences in cognitive abilities (4th ed.). New York, NY: Psychology Press. Halpern, D. F., Benbow, C. P., Geary, D. C., Gur, R. C., Hyde, J. S., & Gernsbacher, M. A. (2007). The science of sex differences in science and mathematics. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 8, 1-51. Hartley, B. L., & Sutton, R. M. (2013). A stereotype threat account of boys' academic underachievement. Child Development, 84, 1716-1733. Hassett, J. M., Siebert, E. R., & Wallen, K. (2008). Sex differences in rhesus monkey toy preferences parallel those of children. Hormones and Behavior, 54, 359364. Hechtman, L. A., Moore, N. P., Schulkey, C. E., Miklos, A. C., Calcagno, A. M., Aragon, R., & Greenberg, J. H. (2018). NIH funding longevity by gender. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Hedges, L. V., & Friedman, L. (1993). Gender differences in variability in intellectual abilities: A reanalysis of Feingold’s results. Review of Educational Research, 63, 94-105. Hedges, L. V., & Nowell, A. (1995). Sex differences in mental test scores, variability and numbers of high-scoring individuals. Science, 269, 41–45. Hengel, E. (2017). Publishing while female. Are women held to higher standards? Evidence from peer review. Cambridge Working Paper Economics: 1753. Hill, T. P. (2018). An evolutionary theory for the variability hypothesis. arXiv:1703.04184v6 [q-bio.PE]. Hiscox, M. J., Oliver, T., Ridgway, M., Arcos-Holzinger, L., Warren, A., & Willis, A. (2017). Going blind to see more clearly: Unconscious bias in Australian Public Service (APS) shortlisting processes. Behavioural Economics Team of the Australian Government. Retrieved 20 March, 2018, from https://www.pmc.gov.au/domestic-policy/behavioural-economics/going-blind-
Men, Women, and Science 62
1504 1505 1506 1507 1508 1509 1510 1511 1512 1513 1514 1515 1516 1517 1518 1519 1520 1521 1522 1523 1524 1525 1526 1527 1528 1529 1530 1531 1532 1533 1534 1535 1536 1537 1538 1539 1540 1541 1542 1543 1544 1545 1546 1547 1548 1549 1550 1551 1552 1553
see-more-clearly-unconscious-bias-australian-public-service-aps-shortlistingprocesses Hoffman, M., Gneezy, U., & List, J. A. (2011). Nurture affects gender differences in spatial abilities. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 14786-14788. Hossack, K. F., & Bruce, R. A. (1982). Maximal cardiac function in sedentary normal men and women: Comparison of age-related changes. Journal of Applied Physiology: Respiratory, Environmental and Exercise Physiology, 53, 799804. Hrdy, S. B. (2009). Mothers and others: The evolutionary origin of mutual understanding. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hyde, J. S. (2005). The gender similarities hypothesis. American Psychologist, 60, 581-592. Hyde, J. S., Fennema, E., & Lamon, S. J. (1990). Gender differences in mathematics performance: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 107 Hyde, J. S., Lindberg, S. M., Linn, M. C., Ellis, A. B., & Williams, C. C. (2008). Gender similarities characterize math performance. Science, 321, 494-495. Hyde, J. S., Mertz, J. E., & Schekman, R. (2009). Gender, culture, and mathematics performance. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 106, 8801-8807. Iliescu, D., Ilie, A., Ispas, D., Dobrean, A., & Clinciu, A. I. (2016). Sex differences in intelligence: A multi-measure approach using nationally representative samples from Romania. Intelligence, 58, 54-61. Janicke, T., Häderer, I. K., Lajeunesse, M. J., & Anthes, N. (2016). Darwinian sex roles confirmed across the animal kingdom. Science Advances, 2, e1500983. Johnson, W., Carothers, A., & Deary, I. J. (2008). Sex differences in variability in general intelligence: A new look at the old question. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3, 518-531. Kalev, A., Dobbin, F., & Kelly, E. (2006). Best practices or best guesses? Assessing the efficacy of corporate affirmative action and diversity policies. American Sociological Review, 71, 589-617. Karwowski, M., Jankowska, D. M., Gralewski, J., Gajda, A., Wiśniewska, E., & Lebuda, I. (2016). Greater male variability in creativity: A latent variables approach. Thinking Skills and Creativity, 22, 159-166. Kenrick, D. T., Groth, G., Trost, M. R., & Sadalla, E. K. (1993). Integrating evolutionary and social exchange perspectives on relationships: Effects of gender, self-appraisal, and involvement level on mate selection criteria. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 951-969. Kersey, A. J., Braham, E. J., Csumitta, K. D., Libertus, M. E., & Cantlon, J. F. (2018). No intrinsic gender differences in children’s earliest numerical abilities. NPJ Science of Learning, 3. Koch, A. J., D'Mello, S. D., & Sackett, P. R. (2015). A meta-analysis of gender stereotypes and bias in experimental simulations of employment decision making. Journal of Applied Psychology, 100, 128-161. Labuda, D., Lefebvre, J.-F., Nadeau, P., & Roy-Gagnon, M.-H. (2010). Female-tomale breeding ratio in modern humans: An analysis based on historical recombinations. American Journal of Human Genetics, 86, 353-363. Lakin, J. M. (2013). Sex differences in reasoning abilities: Surprising evidence that male–female ratios in the tails of the quantitative reasoning distribution have increased. Intelligence, 41, 263-274.
Men, Women, and Science 63
1554 1555 1556 1557 1558 1559 1560 1561 1562 1563 1564 1565 1566 1567 1568 1569 1570 1571 1572 1573 1574 1575 1576 1577 1578 1579 1580 1581 1582 1583 1584 1585 1586 1587 1588 1589 1590 1591 1592 1593 1594 1595 1596 1597 1598 1599 1600 1601 1602
Lehre, A.-C., Lehre, K. P., Laake, P., & Danbolt, N. C. (2009). Greater intrasex phenotype variability in males than in females is a fundamental aspect of the gender differences in humans. Developmental Psychobiology, 51, 198-206. Lemos, G. C., Abad, F. J., Almeida, L. S., & Colom, R. (2013). Sex differences on g and non-g intellectual performance reveal potential sources of STEM discrepancies. Intelligence, 41, 11-18. Levy, J., & Kimura, D. (2009). Women, men, and the sciences. In C. H. Sommers (Ed.), The science on women and science (pp. 202-284). Washington, DC: AEI Press. Lippa, R. A. (2009). Sex differences in personality traits and gender-related occupational preferences across 53 nations: Testing evolutionary and socialenvironmental theories. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 39, 619-636. Lippa, R. A. (2010). Sex differences in personality traits and gender-related occupational preferences across 53 nations: Testing evolutionary and socialenvironmental theories. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 39, 619-636. Lippa, R. A., Collaer, M. L., & Peters, M. (2010). Sex differences in mental rotation and line angle judgments are positively associated with gender equality and economic development across 53 nations. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 39, 990-997. Lippa, R. A., Preston, K., & Penner, J. (2014). Women's representation in 60 occupations from 1972 to 2010: More women in high-status jobs, few women in things-oriented jobs. PLOS ONE, 9, e95960. Lloyd, M. E. (1990). Gender factors in reviewer recommendations for manuscript publication. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 23, 539-543. Lohman, D. F., & Lakin, J. M. (2009). Consistencies in sex differences on the Cognitive Abilities Test across countries, grades, test forms, and cohorts. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 79, 389-407. Lopez, G. (2017). For years, this popular test measured anyone’s racial bias. But it might not work after all. Vox. Retrieved 22 March, 2018, from https://www.vox.com/identities/2017/3/7/14637626/implicit-association-testracism Lubinski, D., Benbow, C. P., & Kell, H. J. (2014). Life paths and accomplishments of mathematically precocious males and females four decades later. Psychological Science, 25, 2217-2232. Lutchmaya, S., Baron-Cohen, S., & Raggatt, P. (2001). Foetal testosterone and vocabulary size in 18- and 24-month-old infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 24, 418-424. Lutchmaya, S., Baron-Cohen, S., & Raggatt, P. (2002). Foetal testosterone and eye contact in 12-month-old human infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 25, 327-335. Lutter, M., & Schröder, M. (2014). Who becomes a tenured professor, and why? Panel data evidence from German sociology, 1980–2013. MPIfG Discussion Paper 14/19 Machin, S., & Pekkarinen, T. (2008). Global sex differences in test score variability. Science, 322, 1331-1332. Maeda, Y., & Yoon, S. Y. (2013). A meta-analysis on gender differences in mental rotation ability measured by the Purdue Spatial Visualization Tests: Visualization of Rotations (PSVT:R). Educational Psychology Review, 25, 6994.
Men, Women, and Science 64
1603 1604 1605 1606 1607 1608 1609 1610 1611 1612 1613 1614 1615 1616 1617 1618 1619 1620 1621 1622 1623 1624 1625 1626 1627 1628 1629 1630 1631 1632 1633 1634 1635 1636 1637 1638 1639 1640 1641 1642 1643 1644 1645 1646 1647 1648 1649 1650 1651 1652
Makel, M. C., Wai, J., Peairs, K., & Putallaz, M. (2016). Sex differences in the right tail of cognitive abilities: An update and cross cultural extension. Intelligence, 59, 8-15. Manning, J. T., Reimers, S., Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., & Fink, B. (2010). Sexually dimorphic traits (digit ratio, body height, systemizing–empathizing scores) and gender segregation between occupations: Evidence from the BBC internet study. Personality and Individual Differences, 49, 511-515. Massen, J. J. M., Bauer, L., Spurny, B., Bugnyar, T., & Kret, M. E. (2017). Sharing of science is most likely among male scientists. Scientific Reports, 7, 12927. Max Planck Society. (2017). More opportunities for female scientists. Max-PlanckGesellschaft. Retrieved 16 May, 2018, from https://www.mpg.de/11767653/lise-meitner-programme Meyer, S. (2015). Women in science: What explains gaps? Part I. Psychology Today. Retrieved March 20, 2018, from https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/rabble-rouser/201510/women-inscience-what-explains-gaps-part-i Milkman, K. L., Akinola, M., & Chugh, D. (2015). What happens before? A field experiment exploring how pay and representation differentially shape bias on the pathway into organizations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 100, 16781712. Miller, D. I., Nolla, K. M., Eagly, A. H., & Uttal, D. H. (2018). The development of children's gender‐science stereotypes: A meta‐analysis of 5 decades of U.S. draw‐a‐scientist studies. Child Development. Miller, D. I., & Wai, J. (2015). The bachelor’s to Ph.D. STEM pipeline no longer leaks more women than men: A 30-year analysis. Frontiers in Psychology, 6. Møller, A. P. (1991). Sexual selection in the monogamous barn swallow (Hirundo rustica). I. Determinants of tail ornament size. Evolution, 45, 1823-1836. Moore, D. S., & Johnson, S. P. (2008). Mental rotation in human infants: A sex difference. Psychological science, 19, 1063-1066. Morris, M. L. (2016). Vocational interests in the United States: Sex, age, ethnicity, and year effects. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 63, 604-615. Moss-Racusin, C. A., Dovidio, J. F., Brescoll, V. L., Graham, M. J., & Handelsman, J. (2012). Science faculty’s subtle gender biases favor male students. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109, 16474-16479. Moss-Racusin, C. A., van der Toorn, J., Dovidio, J. F., Brescoll, V. L., Graham, M. J., & Handelsman, J. (2014). Scientific diversity interventions. Science, 343, 615616. Muller, M. N., Wrangham, R. W., & Pilbeam, D. R. (Eds.). (2017). Chimpanzees and human evolution. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Navarra-Madsen, J., Bales, R. A., & Hynds, D. L. (2010). Role of scholarships in improving success rates of undergraduate Science, Technology, Engineering and Mathematics (STEM) majors. Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences, 8, 458-464. Nittrouer, C. L., Hebl, M. R., Ashburn-Nardo, L., Trump-Steele, R. C. E., Lane, D. M., & Valian, V. (2017). Gender disparities in colloquium speakers at top universities. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Oswald, F. L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., & Tetlock, P. E. (2015). Using the IAT to predict ethnic and racial discrimination: small effect sizes of unknown societal significance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108, 562-571.
Men, Women, and Science 65
1653 1654 1655 1656 1657 1658 1659 1660 1661 1662 1663 1664 1665 1666 1667 1668 1669 1670 1671 1672 1673 1674 1675 1676 1677 1678 1679 1680 1681 1682 1683 1684 1685 1686 1687 1688 1689 1690 1691 1692 1693 1694 1695 1696 1697 1698 1699 1700 1701
Pinker, Steven. (2002). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York, NY: Viking. Pinker, Steven. (2010). On women, STEM and hidden bias. Minding the Campus. Retrieved 17 May, 2018, from https://www.susanpinker.com/wpcontent/uploads/2014/08/On-Women-STEM-and-Hidden-Bias.pdf Pinker, Susan. (2008). The sexual paradox: Troubled boys, gifted girls, and the real difference between the sexes. New York, NY: Scribner. Pomiankowski, A., & Møller, A. P. (1995). A resolution of the lek paradox. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 260, 21-29. Radcliffe Richards, J. (1980). The sceptical feminist: A philosophical enquiry. Oxon, UK: Routledge. Redmond, P., & McGuinness, S. (2017). The gender wage gap in Europe: Job preferences, gender convergence and distributional effects. IZA DP No. 10933 Reilly, D., Neumann, D. L., & Andrews, G. (2015). Sex differences in mathematics and science achievement: A meta-analysis of National Assessment of Educational Progress assessments. Journal of Educational Psychology, 107, 645-662. Reinhold, K., & Engqvist, L. (2013). The variability is in the sex chromosomes. Evolution, 67, 3662-3668. Reynolds, M. R., Scheiber, C., Hajovsky, D. B., Schwartz, B., & Kaufman, A. S. (2015). Gender differences in academic achievement: Is writing an exception to the gender similarities hypothesis? Journal of Genetic Psychology, 176, 211-234. Riegle-Crumb, C., King, B., & Moore, C. (2016). Do they stay or do they go? The switching decisions of individuals who enter gender atypical college majors. Sex Roles, 74, 436-449. Ritchie, S. J., Cox, S. R., Shen, X., Lombardo, M. V., Reus, L. M., Alloza, C., . . . Deary, I. J. (2018). Sex differences in the adult human brain: Evidence from 5216 UK Biobank participants. Cerebral Cortex, bhy109-bhy109. Robinson, J. P., & Lubienski, S. T. (2011). The development of gender achievement gaps in mathematics and reading during elementary and middle school: Examining direct cognitive assessments and teacher ratings. American Educational Research Journal, 48, 268-302. Rowe, L., & Houle, D. (1996). The lek paradox and the capture of genetic variance by condition dependent traits. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 263, 1415-1421. Rubinstein, R. S., Jussim, L., & Stevens, S. T. (2018). Reliance on individuating information and stereotypes in implicit and explicit person perception. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 75, 54-70. Ruzich, E., Allison, C., Chakrabarti, B., Smith, P., Musto, H., Ring, H., & BaronCohen, S. (2015). Sex and STEM occupation predict Autism-Spectrum Quotient (AQ) scores in half a million people. PLOS ONE, 10, e0141229. Safran, R. J., & McGraw, K. J. (2004). Plumage coloration, not length or symmetry of tail-streamers, is a sexually selected trait in North American barn swallows. Behavioral Ecology, 15, 455-461. Schmitt, D. P. (2005). Sociosexuality from Argentina to Zimbabwe: A 48-nation study of sex, culture, and strategies of human mating. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 247-275.
Men, Women, and Science 66
1702 1703 1704 1705 1706 1707 1708 1709 1710 1711 1712 1713 1714 1715 1716 1717 1718 1719 1720 1721 1722 1723 1724 1725 1726 1727 1728 1729 1730 1731 1732 1733 1734 1735 1736 1737 1738 1739 1740 1741 1742 1743 1744 1745 1746 1747 1748 1749 1750 1751
Schmitt, D. P. (2015). The evolution of culturally-variable sex differences: Men and women are not always different, but when they are… it appears not to result from patriarchy or sex role socialization. In V. A. Weekes-Shackelford & T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), The evolution of sexuality (pp. 221-256). New York, NY: Springer. Schmitt, D. P., & Project, M. o. t. I. S. D. (2003). Universal sex differences in the desire for sexual variety: Tests from 52 nations, 6 continents, and 13 islands. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 85-104. Schmitt, D. P., Realo, A., Voracek, M., & Allik, J. (2008). Why can’t a man be more like a woman? Sex differences in Big Five personality traits across 55 cultures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 168-182. Schwartz, S. H., & Rubel, T. (2005). Sex differences in value priorities: Cross-cultural and multimethod studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 1010-1028. Sesardic, N., & De Clercq, R. (2014). Women in philosophy: Problems with the discrimination hypothesis. Academic Questions, 27, 461-473. Silverman, I., & Phillips, K. (1998). The evolutionary psychology of spatial sex differences: Evolutionary theory and data. In C. B. Crawford & D. Krebs, L. (Eds.), Handbook of evolutionary psychology: Ideas, issues, and applications (pp. 595-612). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Simpson, E. A., Nicolini, Y., Shetler, M., Suomi, S. J., Ferrari, P. F., & Paukner, A. (2016). Experience-independent sex differences in newborn macaques: Females are more social than males. Scientific Reports, 6, 19669. Slabbekoorn, D., van Goozen, S. H. M., Megens, J., Gooren, L. J. G., & CohenKettenis, P. T. (1999). Activating effects of cross-sex hormones on cognitive functioning: A study of short-term and long-term hormone effects in transsexuals. Psychoneuroendocrinology, 24, 423-447. Sommers, C. H. (2013). What 'lean in' misunderstands about gender differences. The Atlantic. Retrieved 12 January, 2017, from https://www.theatlantic.com/sexes/archive/2013/03/what-lean-inmisunderstands-about-gender-differences/274138/ Spelke, E. S. (2005). Sex differences in intrinsic aptitude for mathematics and science? A critical review. American Psychologist, 60, 950-958. Spencer, S. J., Steele, C. M., & Quinn, D. M. (1999). Stereotype threat and women's math performance. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 35, 4-28. Stafford, T. (2017). Female chess players outperform expectations when playing men. psyarxiv.com/bpy3t. Steinpreis, R. E., Anders, K. A., & Ritzke, D. (1999). The impact of gender on the review of the Curricula Vitae of job applicants and tenure candidates: A national empirical study. Sex Roles, 41, 509-528. Stewart-Williams, S., & Thomas, A. G. (2013). The ape that thought it was a peacock: Does evolutionary psychology exaggerate human sex differences? Psychological Inquiry, 24, 137-168. Stoet, G., Bailey, D. H., Moore, A. M., & Geary, D. C. (2016). Countries with higher levels of gender equality show larger national sex differences in mathematics anxiety and relatively lower parental mathematics valuation for girls. PLoS ONE, 11, e0153857. Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2012). Can stereotype threat explain the gender gap in mathematics performance and achievement? Review of General Psychology, 16, 93-102.
Men, Women, and Science 67
1752 1753 1754 1755 1756 1757 1758 1759 1760 1761 1762 1763 1764 1765 1766 1767 1768 1769 1770 1771 1772 1773 1774 1775 1776 1777 1778 1779 1780 1781 1782 1783 1784 1785 1786 1787 1788 1789 1790 1791 1792 1793 1794 1795 1796 1797 1798 1799 1800
Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2013). Sex differences in mathematics and reading achievement are inversely related: Within- and across-nation assessment of 10 years of PISA data. PLoS ONE, 8, e57988. Stoet, G., & Geary, D. C. (2018). The gender-equality paradox in science, technology, engineering, and mathematics education. Psychological Science. Strand, S., Deary, I. J., & Smith, P. (2006). Sex differences in Cognitive Abilities Test scores: A UK national picture. British Journal of Educational Psychology, 76, 463-480. Su, R., Rounds, J., & Armstrong, P. I. (2009). Men and things, women and people: A meta-analysis of sex differences in interests. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 859884. Trivers, R. L. (1972). Parental investment and sexual selection. In B. Campbell (Ed.), Sexual selection and the descent of man: 1871-1971 (pp. 136-179). Chicago, IL: Aldine Press. van der Lee, R., & Ellemers, N. (2015). Gender contributes to personal research funding success in The Netherlands. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112, 12349-12353. Veldkamp, C. L. S., Hartgerink, C. H. J., van Assen, M. A. L. M., & Wicherts, J. M. (2017). Who believes in the storybook image of the scientist? Accountability in Research, 24, 127-151. Voyer, D., Voyer, S., & Bryden, M. P. (1995). Magnitude of sex differences in spatial abilities: A meta-analysis and consideration of critical variables. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 250-270. Wai, J., Cacchio, M., Putallaz, M., & Makel, M. C. (2010). Sex differences in the right tail of cognitive abilities: A 30-year examination. Intelligence, 38, 412423. Wai, J., Lubinski, D., & Benbow, C. P. (2009). Spatial ability for STEM domains: Aligning over 50 years of cumulative psychological knowledge solidifies its importance. Journal of Educational Psychology, 101, 817-835. Wallon, G., Bendiscioli, S., & Garfinkel, M. S. (2015). Exploring quotas in academia. Robert Bosch Stiftung project number: 12.5.8050.0239.0. Retrieved 22 March, 2018, from http://www.embo.org/documents/science_policy/exploring_quotas.pdf Wang, M.-T., Eccles, J. S., & Kenny, S. (2013). Not lack of ability but more choice: Individual and gender differences in choice of careers in science, technology, engineering, and mathematics. Psychological Science, 24, 770-775. Webb, T. J., O’Hara, B., & Freckleton, R. P. (2008). Does double-blind review benefit female authors? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23, 351-353. Wennerås, C., & Wold, A. (1997). Nepotism and sexism in peer-review. Nature, 387, 341-343. Westerterp, K. R., & Goran, M. I. (1997). Relationship between physical activity related energy expenditure and body composition: A gender difference. International Journal of Obesity, 21, 184-188. Westerterp, K. R., & Speakman, J. R. (2008). Physical activity energy expenditure has not declined since the 1980s and matches energy expenditures of wild mammals. International Journal of Obesity, 32, 1256-1263. Williams, W. M., & Ceci, S. J. (2015). National hiring experiments reveal 2:1 faculty preference for women on STEM tenure track. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112, 5360-5365.
Men, Women, and Science 68
1801 1802 1803 1804 1805 1806 1807 1808 1809 1810 1811 1812 1813 1814 1815
Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (1985). Competitiveness, risk taking, and violence: The young male syndrome. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6, 59-73. Wilson, M. L., Miller, C. M., & Crouse, K. N. (2017). Humans as a model species for sexual selection research. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 284 Xu, Y., Norton, S., & Rahman, Q. (2017). Sexual orientation and neurocognitive ability: A meta-analysis in men and women. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews. Yamauchi, T., Kim, S.-N., Lu, Z., Ichimaru, N., Maekawa, R., Natsuhara, K., . . . Ishii, M. (2007). Age and gender differences in the physical activity patterns of urban schoolchildren in Korea and China. Journal of Physiological Anthropology, 26, 101-107. Yang, Y., & Barth, J. M. (2015). Gender differences in STEM undergraduates' vocational interests: People-thing orientation and goal affordances. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 91, 65-75.