There have been many discussions about whether all observational propositions ... In algebraic quantum field theory, some von Neumann algebra is associated.
Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science
On the Problem
of Hidden
Quantum
25
Variables
Field
in Algebraic
Theory
Yuichiro KITAJIMA* Abstract
have
been many
in nonrelativistic
There
quantum
without
contradiction.
not
observational
all
interpreted operator field
theory.
algebras
about
mechanics
way. point
Then
can be taken
I point
be
Jauch
present
in order out
that
as definite,
paper, all
in addition
1.
propositions
as simultaneously
and Piron,
to apply not
all observational
taken
in nonrelativistic
In the view
whether
can
Von Neumann, propositions
in this algebraic
discussions
definite
and Bell have shown
quantum
I examine
mechanics
these
theorems
these theorems
to algebraic
observational
propositions
to nonrelativistic
quantum
that
can
be
from
an
quantum in local mechanics.
Introduction
In algebraic quantum field theory, some von Neumann algebra is associated with each bounded open set in Minkowski space-time. Any projection in that algebra is regarded as an observational proposition in the set in Minkowski space -time to which it is associated. Some physically proper conditions are imposed on that von Neumann algebra, which is called a local algebra. A state on a local algebra gives the probability of an observational proposition in the bounded open set in Minkowski space-time to which that local algebra is associated. There have been many discussions about whether there exist hidden variables that determine truth-values of all observational propositions about a given nonrelativistic quantum mechanical system, and whether the probability given by a quantum mechanical state can be regarded as that probability measure on the set of all hidden variables. For example, von Neumann (1955), and Jauch and Piron (1963) mathematically defined such hidden variables, and showed that there is none in quantum mechanics. But they imposed a condition for incompatible observa tional propositions on hidden variables. Bell (2004) argued that it is not physically proper to impose that condition on hidden variables although it is proper to impose it on quantum mechanical states (pp. 4-6). Then Bell (2004) defined a hidden variable which was not bound by the condition on incompatible observational propositions, and showed that no such hidden variable in nonrelativistic quantum * International
Buddhist
University -25-
26
Yuichiro
KITAJIMA
Vol. 15
mechanics exists (pp. 6-8). In sections 3, 4 and 5, we will see those arguments from an operator algebraic point of view and it will be seen that there is no hidden variable in either algebraic quantum field theory or nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. On the other hand, for a local algebra in algebraic quantum field theory as well as for the set of all bounded operators on a Hilbert space in quantum mechanics, some subset of the set of all observational propositions does admit hidden variables. Halvorson and Clifton (1999) defined these sets from an operator algebraic point of view (see also Clifton, 1999), and named them 'beable algebras' following Bell's terminology (Bell, 2004, chapters 5, 7 and 19). In Section 6, we will look at Clifton's interpretation of algebraic quantum field theory in terms of beable alge bras.
2. 2.1.
Operator In
of
all
let
present
bounded
paper, operators
we
use
the
following
on
a Hilbert
space
{A•¸B(H)|AB=BA
P(_??_)
_??_•¿_??_•L is
for
denote
the
set
called
the
center
Definition
2.1.
ƒÏ satisfies
A
A
if ƒÖ(A2)=[ƒÖ(A)]2
Definition if
(_??_) are
A
orthogonal
2.4.
Let _??_
called
projections
any I
a
Where _??_ denote
the
unital
is a subset
is denoted
Where_??_is
let „H(_??_)
on
If S
which
in _??_.
and
element
is
the
on
any
von
each
Definition
B•¸S}.
functional ƒÏ
state ƒÖ for
2.3.
all
notation. H
of
the
by B(H),
a von is a von center
set
letS•L
Neumann
algebra,
Neumann
algebra,
of _??_.
C*-algebra _??_
is called
a
state
if
conditions:
where
2.2.
all
of _??_
for
2. ƒÏ(I)=1
Definition
of
linear
following
1. ƒÏ(A*A)_??_0
algebra
preliminaries
algebras
the
denote
Mathematical
A•¸_??_;
identity
a
unital
element
equivalent
if
of
von
non-zero
Neumann
there
is a
is called
is
called
projections
algebra.
partial
a
dispersion-free
state
A•¸_??_.
algebra _??_
family
a
in _??_.
C*-algebra _??_
self-adjoint
Neumann
be
operator
in _??_
Two
isometry
a ƒÐ-finite
von is
countable.
projections
V in _??_ such
Neumann
P that
and
Q
in
P=VV*
P and
Q=V*V. If
Definition
two
projections
P
2.5.
be
Let _??_
and
a
Q
von
are
equivalent,
Neumann -26-
we
algebra.
shall
A
write
projection
P•`Q.
P
in _??_
is
said
to
No. 1
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
be finite is
if
an
P•`Q_??_P
Abelian
Definition
2.6.
If Q
for
such
then _??_
is
If
for
such
that
of
type
to
be
_??_ is
said
all
can
is
of
there
type
is
I.
to
be
a
be
infinite.
If
P_??_P
Abelian.
non-zero
If _??_
orthogonal
P no
II
and
in „H(_??_)
non-zero
and
of
the
type
finite
algebra
there
is of
Abelian
type
I
equivalent
II
is a
Abelian
identity
projection
and
the
Abelian
and
non-zero
identity
projections,
finite
projection,
operator
projection
then _??_
is
in _??_ is finite,
the
identity
operator
is
to
an
Abelian
projection, _??_
of on
(Kadison
type
is
space
Ringrose,
there
expressed
I1
a Hilbert
and
Then
be
said to
Q
said
to
be
then _??_
is said
in _??_ is infinite,
then
type II•‡.
algebra.
and _??_
be
is
said
algebra.
in „H(_??_),
mutually
has
operators
2.1
to
it is
In.
type
non-zero
bounded
Neumann
if _??_
Neumann
Proposition
_??_
of no
P
projection
is of
P
Neumann
said
n
type
If _??_
be
has
von
is
of
of
and
II1.
to
von
of
be
If _??_
type
said
sum
non-zero
Q_??_P,
of
A
to
a
then
projection
then _??_
the
any
II.
If _??_
set
Q_??_P,
Otherwise,
algebra,
be
non-zero
in _??_ is
P=Q.
Neumann
Let _??_
any
that
operator
implies
von
27
are
said
is a von
1997,
projections
be
von
of
Neumann
Theorem
PI,
PII1,
type
III.
Neumann
algebra. algebra
6.5.2). PII•‡,
and
of
Let _??_ PIII
in
The type
be
a
I.
von
the
center
of
is of
type
II•‡
as
_??_ =_??_PI_??_PII1_??_PII•‡_??__PIII where _??_PI
is
or PII•‡=0
and _??_PIII
Definition algebra in _??_
of
type
2.7. if
such
A
for
any
that
I
or is
von
PI=0, _??_PII1 of
type
Neumann
non-zero
is of
III
or
algebra
projection
type
II1
or
PII1=0, _??_PII•‡
PIII=0.
P
is
called
in
the
a properly center
infinite
of _??_,
there
von is
a
Neumann
projection
Q
P•`Q•ƒP.
Any local algebra in algebraic quantum field theory is properly infinite (Baum gartel, 1995, Corollary 1.11.6). Definition there
2.8.
is
a
Definition
I-PƒÏ
density
2.9.
is
A
called
state ƒÏ
on
operator
Let ƒÏ
D
be
a
a such
is
the
of ƒÏ.
Neumann
algebra _??_
that ƒÏ(A)=tr(DA)
normal
PƒÏ:=sup{P|P support
von
a
state projection
-27-
on
is for
a
von
of _??_
Neumann such
called any
a
normal
operator
algebra _??_.
that ƒÏ(P)=0}
state
A•¸_??_.
Define
if
_??_ƒÏ _??_ƒÏ
28
Yuichiro
Definition
2.10.
Let ƒÏ
be
a
normal
KITAJIMA
state
on
a
von
,_??_:={A•¸_??_|ƒÏ(AB-BA)=0 ,_??_is
called
the
centralizer
of ƒÏ
Vol. 15 Neumann
for
all
algebra _??_.
Define
B•¸_??_}.
of _??_.
A centralizer of any normal state on a von Neumann algebra _??_is a von Neumann subalgebra of _??_ (Kitajima, 2004, Lemma 8). 2.2. Lattice theory Definition 2.11. A set _??_ is called a partially ordered set if there is a binary relation _??_ on _??_ which satisfies the following conditions: 1. •Ía•¸_??_ 2. •Ía,
b•¸_??_
3. •Ía,
b,
Definition b
in _??_ have
Definition the
and
[[a_??_b
b_??_c]•Ëa_??_c].
ordered
upper
bound
greatest
A
b_??_a]•Ëa=b]; and
partially
least the
2.13.
satisfies
a•Éb
element,
if
non-empty
following
set _??_ is and they
subset
a•¸I
and
b_??_a
imply
b•¸I.
2.
a•¸I
and
b•¸I
imply
a•Éb•¸I.
2.14.
mapping
A
a•¨a•Û
1.
a•Éa•Û=1
2.
a_??_b
3.
(a•Û)•Û=a
When
Definition
lattice _??_
from _??_ and
implies
a_??_b•Û,
we
2.15.
for
Definition
is
2.16.
a
greatest
exist,
I
of
a
are
a
lattice lower
denoted
lattice _??_
is
if
any
bound
elements a•Èb.
by 0
and
called
an
1
a The
and least
respectively.
ideal
of _??_ if
An
An
0
and
itself
1 is
called
satisfying
the
orthocomplemented following
when
there
conditions:
a•Û_??_b•Û; any
element
a•¸_??_.
a•Ûb.
orthocomplemented for
a von
with
into
a•Èa•Û=0;
write
b=a•É(b•Èa•Û) When _??_
called
I
conditions:
1.
Definition
when
A
a
and
[[a_??_b
c•¸_??_
2.12.
element
a
[a_??_a];
any
Neumann
elements
lattice _??_ a,
algebra,
orthocomplemented
is
b•¸_??_
such
P(_??_)
is
called that
an
(a•Èb)•Éc=(a•Éc)•È(b•Éc)
-28-
orthomodular
orthomodular
lattice _??_ is called
(a•Éb)•Èc=(a•Èc)•É(b•Èc)
an
lattice
a_??_b.
a Boolean
lattice.
lattice
when
is
No. 1
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
29
for any elementsa, b and c in _??_. As easily seen, a Boolean lattice is an orthomodular lattice.
3.
von
Neumann
In this section we see von Neumann's 'impossibility algebraic point of view (Proposition 3.1).
proof' from
an operator
Definition 3.1. Let _??_ be a von Neumann algebra. A mapping Exp from the set of all self-adjoint operators in _??_to R is called a dispersion-free expectation value assignment on N if it satisfiesfollowing conditions. 1. _??_
and
Exp for
(aR+bS)=aExp(R)+bExp(S)for any
a,
any
self-adjoint
operators
R,
S
in
b•¸R.
2.
Exp(R2)=[Exp(R)]2
3.
Exp(I)=1.
for
any
self-adjoint
operator
R
in _??_.
Von Neumann defined a dispersion-free expectation value assignment on the set (BH) of all bounded operators on an infinite dimensional Hilbert space H (von Neumann, 1955, pp. 311-312) and showed there is no dispersion-free expectation value assignment on B(H) (von Neumann, 1955, p. 321). In Proposition 3.1 we state this fact more generally.
Lemma 3.1. Let Exp be a dispersion-freeexpectationvalue assignment on a von Neumann algebra _??_.Then Exp can be extendedto a dispersion-freestate on _??_. Proof.
Define
a mapping ƒÖ
from _??_
to C
as
ƒÖ (A):=Exp(A*+A/2)+iExp(i(A*-A)/2) Let
A
expressed
and
B as
be a+ib
any
operators (a,
b•¸R).
in _??_
and
let
(•ÍA•¸_??_). c be
Since
ƒÖ (A*A)=Exp(A*A)=Exp(|A|2)=[Exp(|A|)]2_??_0,
-29-
any
complex
number.
c can
be
30
Yuichiro
KITAJIMA
Vol. 15
and
ƒÖ is
a
state
on _??_.
(R)=Exp(R). We Doring
For
any
self-adjoint
Therefore ƒÖ prove
the
is a
following
operator
R, ƒÖ(R2)=[ƒÖ(R)]2
dispersion-free
theorem,
state
making
because ƒÖ
on _??_.
reference
to
the
proof
of
Lemma
19
of
(2005).
Proposition 3.1. There is no dispersion-freeexpectationvalue assignment on a von Neumann algebra without direct summand of type I1. Proof.
1. that set
Let _??_ there
{P1,
tions
be
is P2,
...,
Pn}
in _??_ such
ƒÖ on _??_.
a von
(2_??_n•ƒ•‡)
There
expectation
of
mutually By
only are
Lemma
2
(V*)ƒÖ(V)=ƒÖ(V*V)=ƒÖ(Pk). sion-free
of
Pi=I.
Since ƒ°ni=1ƒÖ(Pi)=1,
By
algebra expectation
that ƒ°ni=1
(Pk)=0(k•‚j). Pk=V*V.
Neumann
a dispersion-free
a partial of
Misra This
value
type
In, where
value
assignment
orthogonal
Lemma one
3.1
there
of ƒÖ(Pk)s,
isometry
2_??_n•ƒ•‡.
Suppose
on _??_. and
There
equivalent
projec
is a dispersion-free say ƒÖ(Pj),
V in _??_ such
is that
is
unity, Pj=VV*
state and ƒÖ and
(1967) ƒÖ(Pj)=ƒÖ(VV*)=ƒÖ(V)ƒÖ(V*)=ƒÖ is a
assignment
contradiction.
on _??_. - 30-
So
there
is no
disper
a
No. 1
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
2.
Let _??_
algebra
of
Ringrose
either
a properly
type
II1.
(1997)
there
that
similar 3.
is no
manner By
to
a von
Lemma
2.1
Neumann
P
algebra
is no
that
is
P=VV*
of
type
Jauch
and
and
In
direct
Neumann
Kadison
.
It
and
follows
P•Û=V*V
.
assignment
that We
on _??_
can in
a
(2_??_n•ƒ1). expectation
I1
a von of
P•`P•Û
value
type
or
6.5.6
that
dispersion-free
without
4.
Lemma
expectation
where _??_
there
and
algebra1
in _??_ such
V in _??_ such
case
Neumann
6.3.3
dispersion-free
the
Proposition
von
is a projection
isometry
there
infinite
By
there
is a partial
prove
on
be
31
value
assignment
summand.•
Piron
Jauch and Piron (1963) evaluated von Neumann's argument (especially the condition 1 in Definition 3.1) as follows (see also Bell, 2004, pp. 4-5). Concerning states, it is difficult to justify the additivity of the expectation values on non-compatible observables. (p. 828) Then they defined the following truth-value Definition
4.1
omodular
(Jauch-Piron
lattice.2
We
if ƒÊ
satisfies
assignment
truth-value
call
a
assignment).
mapping ƒÊ
following
assignment (p. 833).
from _??_
to {0,
Let _??_ 1} a
be
Jauch-Piron
an
orth
truth-value
conditions:
1. ƒÊ(1)=1; 2. ƒÊ(a•Éb)=ƒÊ(a)+ƒÊ(b) 3.
for
If ƒÊ(a)=ƒÊ(b)=1,
any
elements
a,
b•¸_??_ such
that
a•Ûb;
then ƒÊ(a•Èb)=1.
Jauch and Piron proved that there is no Jauch-Piron truth-value assignment in quantum mechanics (Jauch and Piron, 1963, Theorem II). We prove Theorem II of Jauch and Piron (1963) in another way (Proposition 4.1). Lemma
4.1.
lattice _??_.
1 A
Let
For
type
I•‡
Neumann 2 Jauch following
1
any
von
a
Neumann
algebra and
be
Jauch-Piron
elements
Piron condition
a,
algebra,
are
properly
(1963) (p.
(P) •Ía,
truth-value
assignment
on
an
orhomodular
b•¸_??_,
a type
II•‡
von
Neumann
algebra
and
a type
III
von
infinite.
defined
an
orthocomplemented
lattice _??_
that
satisfies
the
831).
b•¸_??_[a_??_b•¨(a•Èb•Û)•Éb=(b•Èa•Û)•Éa]
As is easily seen, an orthocomplemented orthomodular lattice. - 31-
lattice that
satisfies condition
(P) is an
32
Yuichiro
KITAJIMA
Vol. 15
1. ƒÊ(a•Û)=1-ƒÊ(a); 2.
a_??_b•¨ƒÊ(a)_??_ƒÊ(b);
3. ƒÊ(a•Èb)=ƒÊ(a)ƒÊ(b). Proof. 2.
1.
Since
1=ƒÊ(a•Éa•Û)=ƒÊ(a)+ƒÊ(a•Û), ƒÊ(a•Û)=1-ƒÊ(a).
If
a_??_b,
then
(b•Û)
a_??_(b•Û)•Û,
that
is, a•Ûb•Û.
Since
1_??_ƒÊ(a•Éb•Û)=ƒÊ(a)+ƒÊ
=1+ƒÊ(a)-ƒÊ(b), ƒÊ(a)_??_ƒÊ(b). 3.
If
either ƒÊ(a)
or ƒÊ(b)
is
0, ƒÊ(a•Èb)=0
since
a•Èb_??_a
and
a•Èb_??_b.
Therefore ƒÊ(a•Èb)=ƒÊ(a)ƒÊ(b).
Proposition 4.1. Let _??_ be an orthomodular lattice. Thefollowing conditions are equivalent. 1.
For
ment ƒÊ
any
such
2. _??_ Proof.
non-zero
element
a•¸_??_
there
is
a
Jauch-Piron
truth-value
assign
that ƒÊ(a)=1. is
a
1•Ë2
Boolean
Let
lattice.
a and
b be
•È b)•É(a•Èb•Û)_??_a.
any
elements
Because _??_
is
in _??_. an
Since
a•Èb_??_a a
orthomodular
and
a•Èb•Û_??_a,
(a
lattice,
a=(a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û)•É(a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û) Suppose
that
- Piron
a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û•‚0.
truth-value
Lemma
assignment ƒÊ
4.1 ƒÊ(a)=1
since
It such
follows
that
there
is
a
Jauch
that ƒÊ(a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û)=1.
a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û_??_a.
By
Further,
1=ƒÊ(a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û) =ƒÊ(a•È((a•Èb)•Û•È(a•Èb•Û)•Û) =ƒÊ(a)(1-ƒÊ(a)ƒÊ(b))(1-ƒÊ(a)(1-ƒÊ(b))) =(1-ƒÊ(b))ƒÊ(b) =0(•æƒÊ(b)=0 This
2•Ë1
or
is a contradiction.
b)•É(a•Èb•Û). This Let
a
_??_.
prove,
be
any
Theorem
making non-zero
Define _??_a
Lemma
4.1)
1).
Therefore
By
we
(•æ
(•æƒÊ(a)=1)
36.7 reference
element
a•È((a•Èb)•É(a•Èb•Û))•Û=0, of
Maeda to
(1970), _??_
Lemma
in _??_ and
that is
11.3
of
let _??_ be
the
a
Boolean
Maeda set
is,
a=(a•È
lattice.
(1980). of
all
proper
ideals
of
as
_??_a :={J•¸_??_|a_??_}. _??_ais partially has is
an not
ordered
upper
by
bound
empty
set
inclusion.
in _??_a because •¾_??_a
because
{0}•¸_??_a.
Zorn's
Every
linearly
is a proper lemma
ordered
ideal
such
implies
subset _??_a that
that _??_a
of _??_a
a_??_•¾_??_a. _??_a has
a
maximal
element _??_a. Let
b and
c _??_Ja.
c be Define
any
elements
in _??_ such
J•L as -32-
that
b•Èc•¸Ja
and
b_??_Ja.
Suppose
that
No. 1
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
33
J•L:={y•¸_??_|•Îx•¸Ja[y_??_b•Éx]}. J•L is an
ideal.
a•¸J•L.
Then
is an
Ja_??_J•L there
element
x2
in
since
is
an
Ja
such
b•¸J•L.
element
Because x1 in
that
Ja
Ja
such
a_??_c•Éx2
.
is
a maximal
that
element
a_??_b•Éx1.
Because _??_
in _??_a,
Similarly
is a
Boolean
there
lattice,
a_??_(b•Éx1•Éx2)•È(c•Éx1•Éx2)=(b•Èc)•É(x1•Éx2)•¸Ja. This
contradicts
that
a_??_Ja.
Therefore
c•¸Ja.
Therefore
any
elements
b,
c•¸_??_
, b•Èc•¸Ja•Ìb•¸Ja If
b_??_Ja, such
Define
a
then
b•Û•¸Ja
that
d•Ûe
since and
mapping ƒÊa
or
b•¸Ja
e_??_Ja,
from _??_
or
b•Û•¸Ja.
d•¸Ja to
{0,
c•¸Ja. Therefore
because 1}
e•Û•¸Ja
for and
any
elements
d,
e•¸_??_
d_??_e•Û.
as
1(x_??_Ja) ƒÊ a(x)=
Then ƒÊa
is
a Jauch-Piron
In quantum lattice.
theory,
Therefore
0(x•¸Ja)
truth-value
assignment,
and ƒÊa(a)=1.•
the set of all observational
there
is no
Jauch-Piron
propositions
truth-value
is not
assignment
a Boolean
in quantum
theory.
5.
Gleason
Bell (2004) stated that the condition 3 of Definition 4.1 is a' quite peculiar property' of quantum mechanical states (p. 6). If this condition cannot be justified, the argument of Jauch and Piron does not hold. Then we define a truth-value assignment which is not bounded the condition on incompatible observational propositions as follows. Definition the
set
additive
5.1 of
all
(A
finitely
additive
projections
truth-value
in assignment
a
truth-value von
assignment).
Neumann
on _??_
if ƒÊ
algebra _??_ satisfies
to
{0,
following
1}
A
mapping ƒÊfrom
is
called
a finitely
conditions:
1. ƒÊ(I)=1; 2.
For
Hamhalter
any
mutually (1993)
orthogonal proved
the
projections following
P, Q•¸_??_, ƒÊ(P•ÉQ)=ƒÊ(P)+ƒÊ(Q). lemma
using
a
generalised
Gleason's
theorem (see, e.g. Maeda, 1990, Theorem 12.1 or Hamhalter, 2003, Chapter 5). Lemma
5.1 (Hamhalter,
1993, Lemma 5.1). -33-
Let _??_be a von Neumann algebra
34
Yuichiro
without
direct
assignment
on _??_.
The prove
it
in
let ƒÊ
be
Let ƒÊ
It
be By
be
to
be
to
in
von
Neumann
a
a
finitely
additive
dispersion-free
Corollary
5.2
algebra
truth-value
truth-value
state
of
on _??_.
Hamhalter
(1993).
We
there .
summand
on _??_
truth-value
and
assignment
state
Kadison
is a
direct
let
P,
of
type I2,
Q
be
any
then ƒÊ(P•ÈQ)=1.
additive
of
without
assignment
a dispersion-free
6.1.7
that
a
a finitely
Theorem
follows
let ƒÊ
extended
If ƒÊ(P)=ƒÊ(Q)=1,
extended
-P•ÈQ=V*V
and
proved
additive
in _??_.
Proof. ƒÊ can
be
was
be
finitely
projections
I2
Vol. 15
way.
Let _??_
a
type can
lemma
another
5.2.
of
Then ƒÊ
following
Lemma
.
summand
KITAJIMA
and
partial
on _??_.
Ringrose
isometry
on _??_.
Let
P,
(1997),
V
Q be
By any
Lemma
5.1,
projections
in _??_
(P•ÉQ-Q)•`(P-P•ÈQ).
in _??_ such
that
P•ÉQ-Q=VV*,
P
Because
ƒÖ (VV*)=ƒÖ(V)ƒÖ(V*)=ƒÖ(V*)ƒÖ(V)=ƒÖ(V*V)
by Lemma 2 of Misra (1967), ƒÖ (P•ÈQ)=ƒÖ(P-V*V)=ƒÖ(P)-ƒÖ(V*V) =ƒÖ(P)-ƒÖ(VV*)=ƒÖ(P)-ƒÖ(P•ÉQ-Q) =ƒÖ(P)+ƒÖ(Q)-ƒÖ(P•ÉQ). Therefore
if ƒÖ(P)=ƒÖ(Q)=1,
then ƒÖ(P•ÈQ)=1
(cf.
Hamhalter,
2003,
Example
10.
1.1). •
We
can
prove
Theorem I2.
5.1. Then
Proof.
For
any
is
1•Ë2
Let
Abelian
By
Lemma
lattice tion (P)=1 We
in _??_
any
the
in _??_
finitely
there
is
additive
direct
summand
a finitely
additive
a
truth-value
on
P(_??_).
P=(P•ÈQ)•É(P•ÈQ•Û)
of
type
truth-value
of finitely
an
Since
and Maeda
assignment
Since P(_??_) for
is
in _??_.
Kadison
is
without
algebra.
Therefore _??_
36.7
Proposition
prove
P
assignment 4.1,
of
there
algebra
4.1.
equivalent.
Neumann
5.2
Theorem
by can
von
projections
2.5.3 by
P
any
Proposition
that ƒÊ(P)=1.
PQ=QP.
Proposition
Neumann
projection
Proposition
Q be
using
are
truth-value
Then P,
von
such
an
by
(_??_). 2•Ë1
a
theorem
conditions
non-zero
Jauch-Piron lattice
be
following
assignment ƒÊ 2. _??_
following
Let _??_
the
1.
the
Abelian
any
von
PQ=QP,
Neumann
Boolean P,
Q•¸P
algebra.
P=(P•ÈQ)•É(P•ÈQ•Û)
(1997).
Then
(1970).
Therefore
for
truth-value
a
projections
Ringrose
additive
on _??_ is a is
P(_??_) any
by is
a
non-zero
assignment
Boolean projec
1 such
that ƒÊ
4.1. • following
theorem -34-
using
Proposition
3.1
(cf.
Hamhalter,
No. 1
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory
35
2003, Theorem 7.3.1).
Theorem 5.2. Let _??_ be a von Neumann algebra that has neither direct summand of type I1 nor direct summand of type I2. Then there is no finitely additive truth - value assignment on _??_. Proof. Suppose that there is a finitely additive truth-value assignment on a von Neumann algebra _??_ which has neither direct summand of type I1 nor direct sum mand of type I2. It followsthat there is a dispersion-free state on _??_ by Lemma 5.1. This contradicts Proposition 3.1, since a dispersion-free state on _??_ is a dispersion -free expectation value assignment on _??_.Therefore there is no finitely additive truth-value assignment on _??_. By Theorem 5.2 no finitely additive truth-value can be assignedsimultaneously to all projections on the Hilbert space whose dimensionis greater than 2. Moreover, no finitely additive truth-value can be assigned to all projections which belong to any local algebra in algebraic quantum field theory because any local algebra is a properly infinite von Neumann algebra (Baumgartel, 1995,Corollary 1.11.6). 6.
Clifton's
interpretation
of algebraic
quantum
field
theory
Theorem 5.2 shows that there is no finitely additive truth-value assignment on any local algebra. But some subalgebra of a local algebra can be assigned a finitely additive truthvalue and a state on that subalgebra can be regarded as a mixture of finitely additive truth-value assignments. Halvorson and Clifton (1999) called such a subalgebra a beable algebra, following Bell's terminology (Bell, 2004, chap ters 5, 7 and 19). For example, Bell (2004) said the following: We will exclude the notion of 'observable' in favour of that of 'beable'. The beables of the theory are those elements which might correspond to elements of reality, to things which exist. Their existence does not depend on 'observation'. (p. 174) A beable
Definition
6.1
- algebra, beable is,
if
states
algebra
(Halvorson
let _??_ algebra and on _??_
is defined
be
a
for ƒÏ
only such
if
and
unital if there
the following.
Clifton,
C*-subalgebra and is
only a
if ƒÏ|_??_
probability
1999,
p.
of _??_
and
is
a
measure
that
-35-
2447).
mixture 1 on
Let _??_
let ƒÏ of the
be
a
be
state
dispersion-free space
S
of
a
unital
on _??_. _??_ states, dispersion-free
C* is that
a
36
Yuichiro
KITAJIMA
ƒÏ(A)=•çsƒÖs(A)dƒÊ(s)
Vol. 15
(•ÍA•¸_??_).
Clifton (2000) determined the maximal beable algebra for each faithful normal state in a von Neumann algebra under the condition that the beable algebra is determined solely in terms of the faithful normal state and the algebraic structure of the von Neumann algebra (Clifton, 2000, Proposition 1). The following theorem is a generalaized Clifton's theorem. Theorem
6.1
algebra3
on
of ƒÏ.
a
2. ƒÐ(_??_)=_??_
for
is be
uniquely
set
of
state ƒÏ
a separable with
the
ously
set
mechanics
normal
are states
hyperfinite
for
such
have
no
to
algebraic
a
faithful
Another
states
3 Since
local
(Bratteli 4
To
Clifton 5 In
and
represent assumed
physically
(Haag,
1996,
the
S
Neumann
be
the
following
support
conditions.
that ƒÏ•KƒÐ=ƒÏ.4 and
in
of
2. the
center
of
propositions.
concerns
Corollary
are
Robinson,
this
1987,
condition
reasonable
models,
in
Proposition any
local
V. 6).
-36-
of the
operators
on
have
simultane
quantum of
2004,
field
theory
nonrelativistic
quan
problem
a von
faithful
determined
states
maximal
solely
in
assignment.
truth-value
assignments, by
the
faithful algebra _??_
normal The
truth-value
vectors
concerns
Neumann
of
which
beable terms
of
If
algebra that
we
state
regard
it is natural
Reeh
-Schlieder
theorem
von
Neumann
algebras
are ƒÐ-finite
is
2.5.6).
solely in
set of
(Kitajima,
algebraic
3).
algebras
Proposition
is determined
the
terms
bounded
which
One
many
is
these
all
interpretation
When
separating
1.3.3),
of
in
theory.
invalid
and
as
solely
interpretation
on S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H(_??_ƒÏ, _??_)Sas cyclic
regarded
projections
Proposition
which
an
set
of
trivial.
there 2000,
state
that _??_
all
interpretation. are
be
in S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H(_??_ƒÏ, _??_)S coincides
modal
field
this
factor,5
have
is the
projections
modal
definite
section
von
let
determined
interpretation
normal
1995,
such
are
Kochen-Dieks
(Clifton,
algebras
(Baumgartel,
the
all
(1995))
centralizers
problem
dispersionfree
of
quantum
III1
nontrivial
and
satisfy
1
When _??_
set
Clifton
problems
trivial
which
Kochen-Dieks
which
are
a ƒÐ-finite
S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H(_??_ƒÏ,_??_)S, where„H(_??_ƒÏ,_??_) is
Clifton's
the
type
centralizers
on _??_
algebra.
in
of
of
let _??_
Conditions
algebra
the
under
two
be
on _??_
in S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H(_??_ƒÏ, _??_)S can
local
Therefore
extension
and
to as
local
space,
values 12).
There
a
(DefKD(W)
definite
Corollary
tum
that
Hilbert
state
of _??_.
in
on
respect
projections
propositions
normal
an
of ƒÏ
Let _??_
normal
automorphism ƒÐ
expressed
all
a
for ƒÏ.
with
centralizer _??_ƒÏ, _??_
definite
any
11).
be
of _??_
algebra
maximal
can
Theorem
let ƒÏ
C*-subalgebra
beable
The
a
space,
a
Then _??_ the
be
is
3. _??_
2004,
Hilbert
Let _??_ 1. _??_
is
(Kitajima,
a
terms
of ƒÏ 1 of
algebra
and
Clifton is
the
algebraic
structure
of _??_,
(2000). a hyperfinite
type
III1
factor
to
No. 1 think all
On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory that
for
any
projections
dispersion-free
in
(_??_ƒÏ, _??_)S are when „H(_??_ƒÏ
a set
false
{Pi|i•¸N}
(ƒÖ(Pi)=0 a set
projections,
there
that ƒÖ•L(•Éi•¸NPi)=1 Then •Éi•¸NPi regarded
any
is
a
a valid
and
Pi
for
is false
section
nonrelativistic
5 we pointed
which
out
other
examined
than
any
this
S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H
holds.
countably
But infinite
on S•Û_??_S•Û_??_„H(_??_ƒÏ, _??_)S such
(Kitajima,
i•¸N.
2005,
Therefore
Proposition
this
state
3.1). cannot
be
that
Remarks there
is no
hidden
quantum quantum
interpretation
of the Kochen-Dieks
the
whether
i•¸N
in
variable
in algebraic
mechanics. field theory
Therefore as well as
mechanics.
quantum mechanics to algebraic interpretation. In nonrelativistic tions
for
state,
orthogonal
state ƒÖ•L
any
Concluding
6 we saw Clifton's
is an extension
projections
is a normal
as well as nonrelativistic problems in algebraic
quantum
In section
If ƒÖ mutually
whenever
assignment.
7. In
i•¸N). of
(ƒÖ(•Éi•¸NPi)=0)
orthogonal
dispersion-free
truth-value
quantum field theory there are interpretation
is false
mutually
{Pi|i•¸N}
and ƒÖ•L(Pi)=0 is true
as
of
for
, _??_)S contains
non-zero
state ƒÖ, •Éi•¸NPi
37
quantum
modal
field theory
of nonrelativistic
and saw problems with this there are some interpreta
interpretation.
field theory
quantum
interpretation
quantum field theory, quantum mechanics
Kochen-Dieks
algebraic
of algebraic
modal
It therefore
can be interpreted
needs
to be
in another
way.
Acknowledgements The version
author of this
would
like
to thank
a referee
for valuable
comments
on an earlier
paper.
References
[1]
Baumgartel, H. (1995). Operatoralgebraicmethods in quantum field theory, Akademic Verlag, Berlin.
[2]
Bell, J. S. (2004). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics (Secondedition), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
[3]
Clifton, R. (1995). Independently motivating the Kochen-Dieks modal interpreta tion of quantum mechanics. British Journal for Philosophy of Science,46, 33-57.
[4]
Clifton, R. (1999). Beables in algebraic quantum theory, in J. Butterfield and C. Pagonis (eds.), From physics to philosophy, Cambridge University Press, pp. 12-44.
[5]
Clifton, R. (2000). The modal interpretation of algebraic quantum field theory. Physics Letters A, 271, 167-177.
[6]
Doring, A. (2005). Kochen-Specker theorem for von Neumann algebras. Interna tional Journal of Theoretical Physics, 44, 139-160. -37-
38
Yuichiro
KITAJIMA
Vol. 15
[7] [8]
Haag, R. (1996). Local quantum physics (Second edition), Springer, Berlin. Halvorson, H. and Clifton, R. (1999). Maximal beables subalgebras of quantum mechanical observables. International Journal of TheoreticalPhysics, 38, 2441-2484.
[9]
Hamhalter, J. (1993). Pure Jauch-Piron States on von Neumann Algebras. Annales de l'Institut Poincare, 58, 173-187. Hamhalter, J. (2003). Quantum measure theory, Kluwer, Dordrecht. Jauch, J. M. and Piron, C. (1963). Can hidden variables be excluded in quantum mechanics?. Helvetica Physica Acta, 36, 827-837. Kadison, R.V. and Ringrose, J. R. (1997). Fundamentals of the theory of operator algebras, American Mathematical Society, Providence, Rhode island. Kitajima, Y. (2004). A remark on the modal interpretation of algebraic quantum field theory. Physics Letters A, 331, 181-186. Kitajima, Y. (2005). Interpretations of quantum mechanics in terms of beable alge bras. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 44, 1141-1156. Maeda, F. and Maeda, S. (1970). Theory of symmetric lattices, Springer, Berlin. Maeda, S. (1980). Lattice theory and quantum logic, Maki-Shoten, Tokyo (In Japanese). Maeda, S. (1990). Probability measures on projections in von Neumann algebras. Reviews in Mathematical Physics 1, 235-290.
[10] [11] [12] [13] [14] [15] [16] [17] [18]
Misra, B. (1967). When can hidden variables be excluded in quantum mechanics?. Nuovo Cimento, 47A, 841-859.
[19]
von Neumann, J. (1955). Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics, Princeton University Press, New Jersy.
-38-