Reciprocity and the Law of War - Harvard International Law Journal

39 downloads 64243 Views 361KB Size Report
Justice regulates rights and duties, and is a single entity—majes- .... LAW OF WAR INSTRUCTOR'S GUIDE]; see also U.S. Army Center for Law and Mil. ..... The parties did not call upon the Court to demarcate the border, but merely asked to.
\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 1

25-JUN-09

7:50

VOLUME 50, NUMBER 2, SUMMER 2009

Reciprocity and the Law of War Sean Watts*

This Article examines how the principle of reciprocity operates within the international law of war. Tracing the historical development and application of the law, the Article demonstrates that the existing law of war derives from a set of rules that are contingent on reciprocity. Contrary to common understanding, reciprocity strongly influences states’ interpretation and application of the law of war. The Article first identifies an obligational component of reciprocity that restricts operation of the law to contests between parties with parallel legal commitments. Second, the Article identifies an observational component of the principle of reciprocity that permits parties to suspend or terminate observance when confronted with breach. Although the principle of reciprocity was softened by late twentieth century legal instruments, it continues to form a critical component of the law of war and guides both pragmatic and theoretical discourse. Regardless of normative conclusions about reciprocity as a precondition to application of the law, the Article’s reciprocity-cognizant framework for understanding the law of war provides a useful platform for reform efforts.

Observe what Justice is and what Reciprocity. In my opinion, Justice rules between individuals, Reciprocity between States. Justice regulates rights and duties, and is a single entity—majestic, powerful, impartial. She wears a bandage over her eyes, and regards neither personalities nor Reciprocity. On the other hand, Reciprocity proclaims to the whole world: “I am not Justice, and I pay no regard to her. I am the Goddess of the Market and have my eyes open, and in the market of the nations I myself am the price of Justice.”1 Wyndham A. Bewes I. INTRODUCTION The principle of reciprocity has long been foundational to international law and the law of war specifically.2 Reciprocity has a particularly strong † Assistant Professor of Law, Creighton University School of Law, and Professor, The U.S. Army Judge Advocate General’s School, Army Reserve (DIMA). I wish to thank Professors Michael Kelly, Palma Strand, and Geoff Corn as well as Lieutenant Colonels Eric Talbot Jensen and Thomas “Mick” Wagoner for generous reviews and input on a draft of this Article. I would also like to thank Colleen McGarry and Erin McManis for their excellent research assistance. 1. Wyndham A. Bewes, Reciprocity in the Enjoyment of Civil Rights, 3 PROBLEMS OF THE WAR 133, 133 (1917) (external quotation marks omitted). 2. Jurists, soldiers, and policymakers are by now familiar with the question of how best to refer to the law regulating the conduct of hostilities, or jus in bello. Momentum appears to favor the term “International Humanitarian Law” (“IHL”) as a replacement for the traditional term “Law of War” or its modern variants, “Law of Armed Conflict” and “Law of International Armed Conflict.” See YORAM DINSTEIN, THE CONDUCT OF HOSTILITIES UNDER THE LAW OF INTERNATIONAL ARMED CONFLICT 2 (2004). Com-

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

366

unknown

Seq: 2

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

intuitive appeal as a condition on war rules. Few would consider practicable a legal regime that required one side to “fight with one hand tied behind its back” while its enemy exercised free reign.3 Until recently, reciprocity has been an important tool in marketing the law of war to its end users: combatants and commanders.4 The U.S. Military’s law of war training routinely includes inducement of reciprocity by adversaries as one of many reasons for integrating international law into military doctrine and operations.5 The Army’s law of war instructional materials caution soldiers to this effect.6 Conditions of reciprocity pervade modern law of war treaties and their forebears. The pre- and post-Westphalian customs that formed the groundwork of the law of war reflected exclusive codes rather than universal moral norms. As such, they were highly susceptible to suspension in cases of permentators have offered competing justifications for adopting each term. In my presentations and instruction on jus in bello, I have used each term, usually out of consideration for my particular audience. On balance, however, I have found arguments offered for retaining the term “Law of War” most persuasive. Foremost, the term “Law of War” best directs attention to the soldiers and combatants that bear the hardship and personal danger of its implementation. Although the term IHL undoubtedly embodies the longstanding goal of humanizing warfare, it conveys a unitary purpose not vindicated by either the history or letter of the law itself. Indeed, one of the goals of this piece is to highlight that practical military concerns, including emphasis on internal discipline, merit equal billing with concerns of humanity. In fact, the two are in some respects mutually supporting. 3. Sir Lauterpacht has observed similarly, “[I]t is impossible to visualize the conduct of hostilities in which one side would be bound by rules of warfare without benefiting from them and the other side would benefit from rules of warfare without being bound by them.” Hersch Lauterpacht, The Limits of the Operation of the Law of War, 30 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 206, 212 (1953); see also Alan Dershowitz, Should We Fight Terror with Torture?, THE INDEPENDENT, July 3, 2006 (quoting Aharon Barak, President of the Supreme Court of Israel), available at http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/americas/alandershowitz-should-we-fight-terror-with-torture-406412.html. 4. The U.S. Navy publishes a legal guide for its commanders. DEP’T OF THE NAVY, ANNOTATED SUPPLEMENT TO THE COMMANDER’S HANDBOOK ON THE LAW OF NAVAL OPERATIONS, NWP1-14M/ MCWP5-2.1/COMDTPUB P5800.1 (1997). The guide observes, “Some obligations under the law of armed conflict are reciprocal in that they are binding on the parties only so long as both sides continue to comply with them.” Id. at 6–21. The Handbook excludes rules of a humanitarian nature from the condition of reciprocity and reserves non-reciprocity-based suspension of law to the National Command Authority. Id. 5. A U.S. Army training circular, written to help commanders conduct routine law of war instruction, remarks, “Observing these rules will encourage the enemy to do the same, increase the chances of an enemy surrender, and make the return to peace easier.” HEADQUARTERS, DEP’T OF THE ARMY, INSTRUCTOR’S GUIDE, THE LAW OF WAR, TRAINING CIRCULAR 27–10–3, at 4 (1985) [hereinafter U.S. ARMY LAW OF WAR INSTRUCTOR’S GUIDE]; see also U.S. Army Center for Law and Mil. Operations, Annual Law of War Briefing, Slide 5 (on file with author) (advising soldiers that adherence to the law of war provokes reciprocal adherence by enemies); Briefing, The Judge Advocate General’s School, The Framework of the Law of War (July 7, 2008) (on file with author) (remarking that observing the law of war encourages reciprocal treatment and observance by enemy forces). 6. U.S. ARMY LAW OF WAR INSTRUCTOR’S GUIDE, supra note 5, at 25. The Guide poses the following question in a section of sample questions and answers: Question: Why should we obey the Hague and Geneva conventions when the enemy does not obey them? Answer: As soldiers, you obey these rules because the commander-in-chief requires you to obey them . . . . Our standards are set; we will not lower them by accepting the reprehensible standard of our enemies . . . . Moreover, strict adherence to these rules may pressure the enemy into complying with the requirements of the Conventions. Id.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 3

25-JUN-09

7:50

367

ceived military necessity or in conflicts with enemies from foreign cultural and religious traditions. For their part, early law of war treaties included reciprocal commitment to and reciprocal observance of the law of war as preconditions to their operation. Even after explicit and often draconian conditions on reciprocity fell out of favor, reciprocity persisted beneath the surface of the law of war. Limits on application, requirements of state affiliation, and conditions on armed groups’ conduct and characteristics continued to limit operation of the law of war. Such conditions operated similarly to conditions of reciprocity by effectively denying application of the law of war to all but peer competitors committed to reciprocal observance of the law of war. Against this strong historical and textual tradition, some have argued that reciprocity is no longer a condition of the modern law of war. Grounded primarily in the theory that the nature of the law of war has changed—that restraint in war is based no longer on promissory compromises between sovereigns—this view has gained significant traction and influenced the interpretive approaches of a number of legal authorities. Adherents of this modern view support their claims with compelling textual and normative arguments.7 Thus jurists and policymakers who give primacy to sovereignty, national security, and adherence to limits on the operation and scope of the law of war have clashed with those who seek to humanize war further through evolution or even reconceptualization of the law. Reciprocity is underappreciated as an element of disagreement in this clash of views. Shared misunderstandings about the nature of the existing law and failure to appreciate persistent strains of reciprocity in the law of war explain some disagreement over and disappointment with the law. The tension between these views presents an opportunity to assess how reciprocity has shaped the existing law of war and what role, if any, it should continue to play. Reciprocity continues to form a critical component of the law of war and structures both theoretical and pragmatic discourse. As recently as 2002, the United States explicitly cited concerns of non-reciprocity in its decision to deny application of the law of war to Taliban fighters in Afghanistan.8 This 7. See INGRID DETTER, THE LAW OF WAR 404 (2d ed. 2000) (highlighting for purposes of discussion Michael Bothe’s view on reciprocity in Michael Bothe, Les Conflicts, REVUE GENERAL DE DROIT INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC 93 (1978)); 1 JEAN-MARIE HENCKAERTS & LOUISE DOSWALD-BECK, CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW 498 (2005) (“The obligation to respect and ensure respect for international humanitarian law does not depend on reciprocity.”); FRANCOISE BOUCHET-SAULNIER, THE PRACTICAL GUIDE TO HUMANITARIAN LAW 187 (Laura Brav & Clementine Olivier trans., Rowan & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2d ed. 2007) (2006). 8. See Decision re Application of the Geneva Convention on Prisoners of War to the Conflict with AlQaeda and the Taliban, Memorandum from Alberto R. Gonzales, Counsel to the President, Office of Counsel to the President, to George W. Bush, President of the United States (Jan. 25, 2002), reprinted in THE TORTURE PAPERS 118, 121 (Karen J. Greenberg & Joshua L. Dratel eds., 2005); Memorandum from Jay S. Bybee, Assistant Attorney Gen., Office of Legal Counsel, Dep’t of Justice, to Alberto R. Gonzales, Counsel to the President, and William J. Haynes II, Gen. Counsel of the Dep’t of Def., Application of

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

368

unknown

Seq: 4

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Article suggests that a productive reform dialogue must include a reciprocity-cognizant understanding of the law of war. This Article offers three conclusions about reciprocity that will facilitate debate over the current and future law of war. First, the law of war has long been conditioned on notions of reciprocal obligation and observation. Even as formal mechanisms have faded from use, similarly-minded limits on the operation of the law have persisted below the surface, vindicating the same concerns that informed traditional insistence on reciprocity. Second, states have recently shown a willingness to adapt the principle to changing conceptions of humanity in warfare. In particular, rules on treaty interpretation that minimize the role of reciprocity have fostered widespread agreement that many law of war provisions operate as obligations owed erga omnes rather than as bilateral concessions of a contractual nature. In both the law of war and human rights law, states have consented to peremptory norms that are not subject to traditional reservations of reciprocity. Finally, this Article observes that the law of war has failed to keep pace with the evolution of how and why states fight. Insistence on reciprocity, grounded in early and mid-twentieth century law of war treaties, increasingly clashes with states’ own strategic and tactical responses to conflict and may distract from military and political effectiveness. An analysis of the law of war that considers the impact of reciprocity could resolve the current theoretical and doctrinal debate over conflict regulation. II. THE PRINCIPLE

OF

RECIPROCITY

French legal scholar Louis Le Fur observed that reciprocity lies at the root of all international law.9 Le Fur’s observation was characteristic of early twentieth century scholarship and political views about international law.10 Treaties and Laws to al Qaeda and Taliban Detainees (Jan. 22, 2002), reprinted in THE TORTURE PAPERS 81, 103 (Karen J. Greenberg & Joshua L. Dratel eds., 2005) [hereinafter Bybee Memorandum]. Evaluating whether the Geneva Conventions applied to the 2001 armed conflict with Afghanistan, the Office of Legal Counsel observed, “If Afghanistan could be found in material breach for violating ‘a provision essential to the accomplishment of the object or purpose of the [Geneva Conventions],’ suspension of the Conventions would have been justified.” Id. ´ 9. FRITS KALSHOVEN, BELLIGERENT REPRISALS 24 (1971) (referencing LOUIS LE FUR, DES REPRESAILLES EN TEMPS DE GUERRE (1919)). Later writers confirm the pervasiveness of reciprocity in the international system. Elisabeth Zoller notes that reciprocity was a central principle of primitive life. ELISABETH ZOLLER, PEACETIME UNILATERAL REMEDIES 14 (1984). Lacking hierarchies, primitive tribes relied on reciprocity to order relations between equal members. Id. (citing BRONISLAW MALINOVSKY, CRIME AND CUSTOM IN SAVAGE SOCIETY (1926)). Zoller concludes that the international legal system is in some senses a similarly primitive legal system, lacking de jure hierarchies and authorities and thus reliant on reciprocity to govern relations. Id. 10. See, e.g., PASQUALE FIORE, INTERNATIONAL LAW CODIFIED AND ITS LEGAL SANCTIONS 325 (Edwin M. Borchard trans., Baker, Voohis & Co. 1918) (1890) (observing that states alone can establish particular rules for their relations by reciprocal agreement); WILLIAM EDWARD HALL, A TREATISE ON INTERNATIONAL LAW 408 (A. Pearce Higgins ed., 8th ed. 1924) (“It is obviously an implied condition of the obligatory force of every international contract that it shall be observed by both of the parties to it.”); OPPENHEIM’S INTERNATIONAL LAW 579 (2d ed. 1912) (“Violation of a treaty by one of the con-

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 5

25-JUN-09

7:50

369

Reciprocity was an essential component of the system of sovereign, de jure equals. The prominence of reciprocity was especially apparent in diplomacy, the primary medium of state interaction.11 For instance, states frequently included conditions of reciprocity in the immunities and privileges they afforded diplomatic personnel and public property.12 In 1938, the British House of Lords observed that the customary immunity recognized between states could “be taken to flow from reciprocity, each foreign state within the community of nations accepting some subtraction from its full sovereignty in return for a similar concession on the side of the others.”13 International relations theorists have developed complex models to explain how reciprocity shapes states’ interactions.14 Seeking to resolve ambiguity inherent in the principle,15 Robert Keohane identifies two tracting States does not ipso facto cancel such treaty, but it is in the discretion of the other party to cancel it on the ground of violation. 11. D.W. Greig, Reciprocity, Proportionality, and the Law of Treaties, 34 VA. J. INT’L L. 295, 298–99 (1994). Sovereign immunity “ ‘may be taken to flow from reciprocity, each sovereign State within the community of nations accepting some subtraction from its full sovereignty in return for similar concessions on the side of the others.’ ” Id. at 299 (quoting Compania Naviera Vascongada v. S.S. Cristina [1938] A. C. 485 (U.K.)). 12. In 1961, the International Law Commission (“ILC”) issued a recommendation for an international conference on consular relations. The ILC draft articles sparked discussion regarding reciprocity. Specifically, states disagreed about how to apply the Conventions to consular delegations. Whereas the ILC preferred to insulate delegations from reciprocity-based limitations, states ultimately preserved a measure of reciprocity through an article on non-discrimination. The article states: 1. In the application of the provisions of the present Convention the receiving State shall not discriminate as between States. 2. However, discrimination shall not be regarded as taking place: (a) where the receiving State applies any of the provisions of the present Convention restrictively because of a restrictive application of that provision to its consular posts in the sending State; (b) where by custom or agreement States extend to each other more favourable treatment than is required by the provisions of the present Convention. Vienna Convention on Consular Relations art. 72, Apr. 24, 1963, 21 U.S.T. 77, 596 U.N.T.S. 261; see also Herbert Briggs, Codification Treaties and Provisions on Reciprocity, Non-Discrimination or Retaliation, 56 AM. J. INT’L L. 475, 475 (1962); Ernest L. Kerley, Some Aspects of the Vienna Conference on Diplomatic Intercourse and Immunities, 56 AM. J. INT’L L. 88, 98–99 (1962). 13. Arthur Lenhoff, Reciprocity: The Legal Aspect of a Perennial Idea, 49 NW. U. L. REV. 619, 623 (1954) (quoting Compania Naviera Vascongada v. S.S. Cristina [1938] A. C. 485 (U.K.)). Lenhoff also notes a contemporaneous British extension of reciprocal immunity to the then-insurgent, de facto Franco government in Spain. Id. (citing The Arantzazu Mendi [1939] A. C. 256). 14. See Robert O. Keohane, Reciprocity in International Relations, 25 INT’L ORG. 1 (1986). Reciprocity as a condition for observance of international law fits well with rational choice and state interest compliance and formation theories for international law. Even international law skeptics admit the role of reciprocity in conditioning states’ relations. Professors Goldsmith and Posner posit reciprocity-conditioned “cooperation” as one of four models of state behavior associated with international law. JACK L. GOLDSMITH & ERIC A. POSNER, THE LIMITS OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 12 (2005). The four models include: coincidence of interest (two states pursuing compatible goals without consulting the other), coordination (agreement on and pursuit of similar interests), cooperation (“[S]tates reciprocally refrain from activities . . . that would otherwise be in their immediate self-interest in order to reap larger medium- or long-term benefits.”), and coercion (use of force to bend another state to act contrary to its own interests). Id. at 12. 15. Alvin Gouldner notes that a number of important sociological studies of reciprocity decline to define the principle. Alvin W. Gouldner, The Norm of Reciprocity: A Preliminary Statement, 25 AM. SOC.

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

370

unknown

Seq: 6

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

manifestations of reciprocity in international relations, distinguished by the nature and level of interaction involved. They are “specific reciprocity” and “diffuse reciprocity.” Specific reciprocity describes situations in which actors in a bilateral relationship trade items or acts of roughly equivalent value in a sequential exchange or interaction.16 Contracts are clear examples of specific reciprocity, as they operate through promissory exchanges of similarly valued goods or services. Keohane notes that while specific reciprocity is a temperamental form of cooperation that can frustrate those who seek stable, beneficial agreements, it can ensure cooperation in the anarchic world of international relations.17 Arrangements based on specific reciprocity are typically temporary and often isolated. Consistent with realist skepticism, specific reciprocity discounts promissory arrangements as merely epiphenomenal evidence of momentary state interest, rather than reflective of lasting or meaningfully binding norms on state behavior. Diffuse reciprocity describes interactions between a state and a group, rather than an individual actor or peer.18 Keohane notes that diffuse reciprocity’s broader scope of commitment to accepted standards of behavior reduces unnecessary and inefficient conflict. Yet he cautions that diffuse reciprocity can only be achieved where the actors share compatible interests and norms of obligation.19 Absent these prerequisites, diffuse reciprocity exposes parties to exploitation.20 Thus while the principle of reciprocity is recognized as a general tenet of international law, it does not operate uniformly across the spectrum of international relations. Legal scholars disagree on its precise contours. The operation and applicability of reciprocity frequently depend on the legal source of the obligation, the political standing of the actor to whom the obligation is owed, and subjective evaluations of the nature of the obligation itself. This section identifies two main types of reciprocity, obligational and observational reciprocity, and discusses their operation and limitations in both treaty and customary international law. It concludes by distinguishing reciprocity from reprisal. A. Reciprocity and Treaty Law Generally speaking, the international law of treaties governs law of war treaties. The law of treaties is a set of secondary rules—in other words, REV. 161 (1960) (citing HOWARD BECKER, MAN IN RECIPROCITY (1956); L.T. HOBHOUSE, MORALS EVOLUTION: A STUDY IN COMPARATIVE ETHICS (2d ed. 1951)). 16. Keohane, supra note 14, at 4. 17. Id. at 14. 18. Id. at 4. 19. Id. at 25. 20. Id. at 27.

IN

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 7

25-JUN-09

7:50

371

“rules about rules.”21 Secondary rules guide the application and interpretation of primary rules that prescribe or describe lawful conduct. For instance, the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations describes duties and obligations owed to states’ representatives by their foreign hosts.22 Primary rules of the Convention include the inviolability of embassy premises,23 exemption from taxes,24 and immunity from arrest for diplomatic agents.25 The Convention also includes secondary rules which condition the operation of primary rules. For example, the Convention prohibits parties from discriminating between states in their application of the Convention’s protections.26 Thus, like nearly all other primary international rules, the Convention’s primary rules operate subject to the secondary rules of international law. The principle of reciprocity has long been recognized as an important secondary rule under the law of treaties. Reciprocity places conditions on the binding force, interpretation, and operation of treaties. As a general matter, rules of treaty interpretation have evolved from custom into a formal “treaty on treaties.”27 Detailed, codified rules, often tailored to specific types of treaties and obligations, now guide states’ interpretation and implementation of their treaty obligations. Prior to examining this evolution, however, it will be useful to outline some generally applicable doctrines associated with reciprocity.28 Understood broadly, reciprocity operates in both an obligational sense and an observational sense. Reciprocity operates on an obligational level in that states are generally bound by treaties only in their relations with states that have consented to be bound by the same treaty.29 The binding effect of a treaty is thus contingent on other states’ reciprocating with indicia of in-

21. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (1961). Hart perceived that secondary rules alleviate uncertainty, inalterability, and inefficiency in primary rules. Id. Hart noted, however, a dearth of mature secondary rules in international law. Id. at 209. 22. Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations art. 22, opened for signature Apr. 18, 1961, 23 U.S.T. 3227, 500 U.N.T.S. 95, T.I.A.S. No. 7502 [hereinafter Diplomatic Relations Convention]. 23. Diplomatic Relations Convention, supra note 22, art. 22. 24. Id. art. 23. 25. Id. art. 29. 26. Id. art. 47. Article 47 conditions equal application of the Convention’s protections and immunities on reciprocity. Id. The article does not label as discriminatory situations “where the receiving State applies any of the provisions of the present Convention restrictively because of a restrictive application of that provision to its mission in a sending State . . . .” Id. art. 47, ¶ 2. 27. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties arts. 11, 26, opened for signature May 23, 1969, 1155 U.N.T.S. 331 (entered into force Jan. 27, 1980) [hereinafter Vienna Convention]. 28. See generally LORD MCNAIR, THE LAW OF TREATIES (1961) (discussing early to mid-twentieth century law of treaties). 29. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, arts. 11, 26. The Vienna Convention supports the legal maxim pacta sunt servanda (agreements must be kept) in this regard.

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

372

unknown

Seq: 8

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

tent to be bound.30 In this sense, the operation of treaties is contingent on obligational reciprocity.31 It is not surprising that legal scholars often analogize treaties to contracts.32 Indeed, many treaties refer to parties as “High Contracting Parties.”33 Lawyers and scholars trained in civil law systems occasionally cite the legal maxim inadimplenti non est adimplendum34 to describe the contractlike, reciprocity-based nature of treaty obligations.35 Similar to the law of 30. Most treaties require a minimum number of ratifications between any states parties prior to entering into force. See, e.g., U.N. Charter art. 110, para. 3; General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade art. 26, opened for signature Oct. 30, 1947, 61 Stat. A-11, 55 U.N.T.S. 194; Geneva Convention Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War art. 92, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3316, 75 U.N.T.S. 135; International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights art. 49, opened for signature Dec. 16, 1966, 933 U.N.T.S. 171; Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 84; Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court art. 126, July 17, 1998, 2187 U.N.T.S. 90, 37 I.L.M. 1002. 31. Derek Jinks has referred to required mutuality of obligations as “first-order reciprocity.” Derek Jinks, The Applicability of the Geneva Conventions to the “Global War on Terrorism,” 46 VA. J. INT’L L. 165, 192 (2004). Realist international relations scholars addressing bilateral or “specific” reciprocity minimize the concept of obligation. Thus, Robert Keohane and Robert Axelrod argue that reciprocity may be satisfied through real time reactions to actual behavior rather than prescriptive obligations. Keohane, supra note 14, at 19–20 (remarking that Axelrod declines to address obligation in his theory of reciprocity). In place of formal commitment and putatively binding agreements, Keohane and Axelrod envision a game of tit-for-tat on the basis of self-interest. Id. at 19. However, Keohane concedes a place for obligation in multilateral settings. As mentioned, he offers the term “diffuse reciprocity” to describe situations where one’s counterpart is a group rather than an individual actor. See supra text accompanying notes 18–20. Especially in sociological and anthropological literature, “the language of reciprocity is the language of obligation.” Id. at 20–21 (citing BARRINGTON MOORE, JR., INJUSTICE: THE SOCIAL BASES OF OBEDIENCE AND REVOLT 506 (1978); Alvin W. Gouldner, The Norm of Reciprocity: A Preliminary Statement, 25 AM. SOC. REV. 161, 169–71 (1960)). 32. MALCOLM N. SHAW, INTERNATIONAL LAW 88–89 (5th ed. 2003); SHABTAI ROSENNE, THE LAW OF TREATIES 46 (1970) (equating the law of treaties, the law of contract, and the civil law notion of “the law of obligations”); 1 HERSCH LAUTERPACHT, INTERNATIONAL LAW 351 (1970) (observing that “the contractual nature of all treaties is now no longer seriously challenged”). 33. See, e.g., Geneva Conventions, infra note 155; Hague Convention IV (pmbl.), infra note 179. Hague Convention IV also uses the term “Contracting Powers” in Article 1. The Vienna Convention may have altered the term’s legal significance. See Vienna Convention, supra note 27. The Vienna Convention defines “contracting state” as one that has consented to be bound prior to a treaty’s entry into force. Id. art. 2. The Convention uses the term “party” following entry into force. Id. Some later treaties employ “States Parties.” See also Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court art. 2, July 17, 1998, 2187 U.N.T.S. 90, 37 I.L.M. 1002; Convention on the Prohibition of the Development, Production, and Stockpiling of Bacteriological (Biological) and Toxin Weapons and Their Destruction art. 10, Apr. 10, 1972, 1015 U.N.T.S. 163, 11 I.L.M. 309. But see Protocal Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protection of Victims of Interntional Armed Conflicts (Protocol I) art. 1, Dec. 7, 1979, 1125 U.N.T.S. 3 (continuing to use the term “High Contracting Parties”). 34. If one party violates a treaty obligation, the other party can refuse to perform the corresponding obligation. Specifically, “[a] state’s compliance with the rules hinges on another state’s observance; inadimplenti non est adimplendum.” ZOLLER, supra note 9, at 15; see also John Norton Moore, Enhancing Compliance with International Law: A Neglected Remedy, 39 VA. J. INT’L L. 881, 957–62 (1999) (explaining the right to refuse reciprocal performance if a treaty obligation is violated by the other party); Oscar Schachter, In Defense of International Rules on the Use of Force, 53 U. CHI. L. REV. 113 (1986) (discussing the use of armed force as a reaction to the violation of international law). 35. See, e.g., Prosecutor v. Kupreskic, Case No. IT-95-16-T, Judgment, ¶ 520 (Jan. 14, 2000). The International Criminal Tribunal for Yugoslavia observed: [A] material breach of that treaty obligation by one of the parties would not entitle the other to invoke that breach in order to terminate or suspend the operation of the treaty. Article 60(5) provides that such reciprocity or in other words the principle inadimplenti non est adimplendum

R

R

R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 9

25-JUN-09

7:50

373

contracts, treaty law requires evidence of parties’ intent to be bound.36 Like contracts, treaties traditionally do not create obligations or rights for third parties.37 The decision of the International Court of Justice (“ICJ”) in the seminal North Sea Continental Shelf cases illustrates how the requirement of mutual consent limits treaty obligation.38 These cases arose from a dispute over a territorial boundary in the shallow waters between West Germany, on the one hand, and Denmark and the Netherlands on the other. Denmark and the Netherlands promoted a provision of the 1958 Geneva Convention on the Continental Shelf as the proper basis for the Court’s decision.39 They argued that West German public statements in support of the Convention were sufficient indicia of West Germany’s consent to be bound.40 The ICJ rejected application of the provision in question, and the treaty generally, because West Germany had not ratified the Convention.41 The Court insisted that treaty obligations do not arise casually, particularly when legal instruments specify formal means of manifesting intent to be bound.42 The Court found the dangers of applying conventional provisions absent clear manifestations of consent so obvious as to be “hardly worth stressing.”43

does not apply to the provision relating to the protection of the human person contained in treaties of humanitarian character, in particular the provisions prohibiting any form of reprisal against persons protected by such treaties. Id. 36. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 11. Article 11 includes signature, exchange of instruments, ratification, acceptance, approval, or accession as means for expressing a state’s intent to be bound by a treaty. Id. Additionally, Article 11 requires evidence of intent to be bound by a treaty, but it can sometimes be difficult to interpret expressions of intent. States will need to look at many factors in the treaty negotiation process. See Jerry Z. Li, The Legal Status of Three Sino-U.S. Joint Communiqu´es, 5 CHINESE J. INT’L L. 617, 624–25 (Nov. 2006). 37. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 34. The Convention outlines exceptions to the general rule, primarily where third parties express consent. Id. arts. 35–36. The similarities between contracts and treaties offer an opportunity to compare third-party rights and obligations. In both contracts and treaties, a third party does not have rights unless the parties intended to create rights for the third party. Just as courts interpreting contracts look outside the document itself to ascertain the parties’ intent, the interpretation of treaties can expand to include sources other than the treaty itself; for instance, previous drafts and preparatory works can indicate an intent to create third-party rights and obligations. See, e.g., Sital Kalantry, The Intent-to-Benefit: Individually Enforceable Rights Under International Treaties, 44 STAN. J. INT’L L. 63, 74–83 (2008). Nonetheless, third parties are quite often affected by treaties other states make. See, e.g., Gabriella Blum, Bilateralism, Multilateralism, and the Architecture of International Law, 49 HARV. INT’L L. J. 323, 361 (2008). 38. North Sea Continental Shelf Cases (F.R.G. v. Den., F.R.G. v. Neth.), Advisory Opinions and Orders, 1969 I.C.J. 3 (Feb. 20, 1969) [hereinafter North Sea Continental Shelf Cases]. 39. Id. ¶ 25. The parties did not call upon the Court to demarcate the border, but merely asked to identify the relevant international legal rule. Id. 40. Id. 41. Id. ¶ 27. 42. Id. ¶ 28. 43. Id. ¶ 33.

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

374

unknown

Seq: 10

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

The practice of submitting reservations to treaties also illustrates the operation of obligational reciprocity. As a general matter, states need not accept treaties wholesale.44 The law of treaties permits states to condition ratification on exclusion of particular treaty provisions.45 Once submitted, a state’s treaty reservation stands for acceptance or rejection by the treaty’s remaining states parties on an individual basis.46 If accepted by another state party, the reservation modifies the agreement between the reserving and accepting state to the extent of the reservation.47 If the reservation is rejected, the entire provision in question does not operate between the two states. Thus, the practice of reservations closely observes the principle of obligational reciprocity. It also illustrates the existence of bilateral interactions within multilateral treaty systems.48 Obligational reciprocity operates in emerging forms of international legal obligations as well as treaties. International law increasingly recognizes a role for quasi-contractual instruments that do not rise to the level of treaties. States and international law scholars have distinguished this so-called “soft law” from binding treaties and customs. It often takes the form of nonbind-

44. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 19. 45. Id. Reservations that operate contrary to the “object and purpose” of treaties are generally forbidden. Id. art. 19(b). Furthermore, some treaties expressly forbid reservations or limit the subject of permissible reservations. For instance, the 1993 Chemical Weapons Convention prohibits any reservations to the provisions of the Convention, permitting reservations only to the Convention’s Annex. Convention on the Prohibition of the Development, Production, Stockpiling and Use of Chemical Weapons and on Their Destruction art. 12, opened for signature Jan. 13, 1993, 1974 U.N.T.S. 45, S. Treaty Doc. No. 103–21 (1993). Other treaties appear to limit reservations through more subtle textual schemes. The Convention against Torture addresses reservations in three substantive articles, suggesting that states may not submit reservations to articles that do not include an explicit reservation provision. Convention against Torture and other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment arts. 28–30, opened for signature Dec. 10, 1984, 1465 U.N.T.S. 8. The U.N. Human Rights Committee has gone further with respect to human rights instruments. In its General Comment 24, the Committee observed, “Although treaties that are mere exchanges of obligations between States allow them to reserve inter se application of rules of general international law, it is otherwise in human rights treaties, which are for the benefit of persons within their jurisdiction.” Off. of High Comm’r for Hum. Rts. [OHCHR], General Comment No. 24: Issues relating to reservations made upon ratification or accession to the Covenant or the Optional Protocols thereto, or in relation to declarations under article 41 of the Covenant, CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.6 (Apr. 11, 1994), available at http://www.unhchr.ch/tbs/doc.nsf/0/69c55b086f72957ec12563ed004ecf7a?Open document. 46. Former practice had required unanimous state party acceptance of treaty reservations. D.W. Greig, Reciprocity, Proportionality, and the Law of Treaties, 34 VA. J. INT’L L. 295, 327 (1994). The individual system of accepting or rejecting reservations emerged after recognition of impracticalities of the former system in multilateral treaties. Id. (citing Reservations to the Convention on Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Advisory Opinion, 1951 I.C.J. 15, 21–22 (May 28)). 47. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 21. 48. The International Court of Justice confirmed the contractual nature of the treaty reservation system in the 1951 Advisory Opinion on Reservations to the Genocide Convention, supra note 46. The Court observed that “no reservation was valid unless it was accepted by all the contracting parties.” Id. at 6. Commentators have minimized the legal effect of the Court’s conclusion, noting that the Court merely addressed reservations to the Convention as positive law, leaving unaddressed the mitigating effect of treaty provisions that have attained customary status. See MARK VILLIGER, CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW AND TREATIES 260 (1985).

R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 11

25-JUN-09

7:50

375

ing resolutions issued by international organizations or governing bodies49 but may also arise from agreements between states.50 Although soft law is an increasingly prevalent and influential form of obligation,51 it falls short of international law in the formal sense. Furthermore, obligational reciprocity often conditions the binding force of states’ duties.52 Reciprocity doctrine traditionally operates at an observational level as well as an obligational level. Once the parties bind themselves, the continued force of a treaty is contingent on reciprocal observation by states parties.53 That is, states are bound by a treaty only to the extent that other states observe the treaty’s substantive provisions in practice. Material breach of a treaty is widely accepted as a sufficient cause for an affected party to terminate or suspend operation of the provision at issue or, in extreme cases, the entire treaty.54 In an effort to refine the doctrine of reciprocity, interna49. The U.N. General Assembly issues resolutions at nearly every session. See, e.g., G.A. Res. 50/1, U.N. Doc. A/RES/50/1 (Oct. 19, 1995); 1978 U.N.E.P. Draft Principles of Conduct in the Field of the Environment for the Guidance of States in the Conservation and Harmonious Utilization of Natural Resources Shared by Two or More States, reprinted in 17 I.L.M. 1094, 1097 (1978). 50. Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe: Final Act, Aug. 1, 1975, 14 I.L.M. 1292. 51. Soft law regulations are occurring with more frequency. Williamson observes: Diplomats and their governments sometimes prefer concluding soft law instruments because doing so can be easier than adopting treaties. Soft law instruments are advantageous because they avoid constitutional and other domestic legal requirements in most democracies for entry into force that apply to treaties. Another commonly cited advantage is the very fact that soft law is nonbinding, making it easier to induce a reluctant state to become a party, and overcoming a state’s fears that it might be committing itself to a course of conduct when future circumstances are hard to foresee. Richard L. Williamson, Jr., Hard Law, Soft Law, and Non-Law in Multilateral Arms Control: Some Compliance Hypotheses, 4 CHI. J. INT’L L. 59, 63 (2003); see also Christopher C. Joyner, Recommended Measures Under the Antarctic Treaty: Hardening Compliance with Soft International Law, 19 MICH. J. INT’L L. 401 (1998) (detailing the adoption of certain recommendations and behavior-regulating measures as soft law within the Antarctic Treaty System). 52. “As soft law, Antarctic Treaty recommendations carry a certain measure of legal authority. Consultative Parties hold strong expectations that norms contained in adopted recommendations will command respect by all ATCP governments, as well as by other Antarctic Treaty Parties, and that these norms will be adhered to over the long term.” Joyner, supra note 51, at 414. 53. LORD MCNAIR, THE LAW OF TREATIES 573 (1961). Lord McNair observes, “[I]t is not uncommon for the injured state, by way of sanction, to suspend the operation of a provision corresponding to, or analogous with, the provision broken.” Id. However, he further notes the uncertain and then-largely uncodified status of his rule. Id. The U.S. Supreme Court has confirmed the general rule of suspension in response to breach. Justice Iredell observed, “It is part of the law of nations, that if a treaty be violated by one party, it is at the option of the other party, if innocent, to declare, in consequence of the breach, that the treaty is void.” Ware v. Hylton, 3 U.S. 199, 261 (1796). In 1986, in response to New Zealand’s refusal to grant reciprocal access to ports and air strips, the United States suspended observance of its security obligations toward New Zealand under the 1951 ANZUS Pact. See OFFICE OF THE LEGAL ADVISER, DEP’T OF STATE, 1 CUMULATIVE DIGEST OF UNITED STATES PRACTICE IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 1981–88 (Marian Nash (Leich) ed., 1993) (citing Australia, New Zealand, United States Security Treaty (ANZUS Pact), Sep. 1, 1951, 3 U.S.T. 3420, T.I.A.S. 2493). 54. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60. The Convention describes a material breach as either repudiation of the treaty or “violation of a provision essential to the accomplishment of the object or purpose of the treaty.” Id. art. 60, ¶ 3(a) & (b). But see Herbert W. Briggs, Unilateral Denunciation of Treaties: The Vienna Convention and the International Court of Justice, 68 AM. J. INT’L L. 51 (1974). Commenting on the ICJ’s 1971 Namibia advisory opinion, Briggs laments what he considers Court dictum,

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

376

unknown

Seq: 12

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

tional lawyers have identified two strains of observational reciprocity in state practice and treaty law: “positive” and “negative” reciprocity. Negative reciprocity, perhaps the more intuitive strain, refers to state suspensions of legal obligations in response to breaches.55 The 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties codified much of the traditional law of treaties.56 It outlines a range of options for the exercise of negative reciprocity, drawing a clear distinction between bilateral and multilateral treaties. The Convention subjects bilateral treaties to less stringent limitations on the exercise of negative reciprocity by permitting suspension or termination at the discretion of the non-breaching party.57 In the case of material breach of a multilateral treaty, non-breaching parties have four options. First, with the unanimous agreement of the treaty parties, they may terminate the treaty in whole or in relevant part in their mutual relations with the breaching state.58 Second, subject again to unanimous agreement, the parties may terminate the treaty as between all the parties, essentially dissolving the agreement altogether.59 Third, states that have been specially affected by the breach may unilaterally suspend the treaty in their relations with the breaching state.60 Finally, any party other than the breaching state may suspend the treaty when the breach “radically changes” the parties’ positions with respect to future performance.61

recognizing a general right to terminate treaties in response to breach. Id. at 55. Briggs asserts, “The Court produces no evidence to support its allegation that a general principle of law establishes ‘a right of termination on account of breach.’ ” Id. Prior to the Vienna Convention, international tribunals addressed the general principle of reciprocity on at least two occasions. In the Diversion of Water from Meuse case at the Permanent Court of International Justice, Belgium claimed suspension of a provision of the Treaty of 1863 by virtue of Dutch breach. Diversion of Water from Meuse (Neth. v. Belg.), 1937 P.C.I.J. (ser. A/B) No. 70, at 7 (June 28). While the Court held that the Netherlands had not breached the treaty, a dissenting opinion observed that the principle of inadimplenti non est adimplentum was “so just, so equitable, so universally recognized that it must be applied in international relations also.” Id. (Judge Anzilotti dissenting). In the Tacna-Arica Arbitration, an arbitrator evaluated a Peruvian claim of discharge from obligations under the Treaty of Ancon because of Chilean breach. 2 REPORTS OF INTERNATIONAL ARBITRAL AWARDS 929, 943–44. The arbitrator confirmed the general remedy of termination of the treaty in the face of breach. Id. However, he limited the practice to occasions of “fundamental” breach. International Law Commission, Report on its 18th Sess. (1966), U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., U.N. Doc. A/6309/Rev. 1 (Jan. 3–28, 1966), reprinted in 61 AM. J. INT’L L. 248, 423 (1967). 55. See FRITS KALSHOVEN & LIESBETH ZEGVELD, CONSTRAINTS ON THE WAGING OF WAR 143 (3d ed. 2001); GEORG SCHWARZENBERGER, 2 INTERNATIONAL LAW AS APPLIED BY INTERNATIONAL COURTS AND TRIBUNALS: THE LAW OF ARMED CONFLICT 453 (1968) (noting that belligerents may use reprisals to “reverse the operation of the chief working principle behind the laws of war from positive, to negative, reciprocity”). 56. See Legal Consequences for States of the Continued Presence of South Africa in Namibia (South West Africa) notwithstanding Security Council Resolution 276, Advisory Opinion, 1971 I.C.J. 16, ¶ 94 (June 21) [hereinafter I.C.J. Namibia Advisory Opinion]. 57. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60, ¶ 1. 58. Id. art. 60, ¶ 2(a)(i). 59. Id. art. 60, ¶ 2(a)(ii). 60. Id. art. 60, ¶ 2(b). 61. Id. art. 60, ¶ 2(c).

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 13

25-JUN-09

7:50

377

The Vienna Convention enjoys wide ratification.62 In addition to binding states parties, the Convention’s reciprocity regime likely binds non-parties63 as a matter of customary international law.64 The Commentary to an earlier draft convention indicates that the majority of contemporary jurists regarded the statements on reciprocity contained in paragraphs one through three of Article 60 as reflective of customary rules.65 Preparatory works on negative reciprocity had attempted to divest states of unilateral authority to suspend treaty provisions in case of breach.66 A draft convention on treaty law devised a procedure whereby suspensions in response to breach would be provisional only, requiring confirmation by an international tribunal to have permanent effect.67 However, states—rejecting such limits—ultimately retained unilateral authority to exercise negative reciprocity under the Vienna Convention. Positive reciprocity is the second strain of obligational reciprocity. It refers to states’ efforts to induce reciprocal compliance from other actors through continued respect for an international norm or treaty provision, notwithstanding their legal right not to comply by virtue of breach or non62. Forty-five states are signatories to the Treaty, and 108 states are currently parties to it. United Nations Treaty Collection, http://treaties.un.org (last visited Mar. 10, 2009). 63. Although the United States is not a party to the Vienna Convention, U.S. courts have recognized the Vienna Convention as codification of customary international law. See Chubb & Son, Inc. v. Asiana Airlines, Inc., 214 F.3d 301, 308 (2d Cir. 2000). Additionally, the international legal community has recognized the customary status of the Vienna Convention: [A]ccording to a widespread opinio juris, legal conviction of the international community, the Vienna Convention represents a treaty which to a large degree is a restatement of customary rules, binding states regardless of whether they are parties to the Convention. Even before the Convention entered into force, its provisions had been invoked by states and by the International Court of Justice. Maria Frankowska, The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties Before United States Courts, 28 VA. J. INT’L L. 281, 286 (1988) (citing Fisheries Jurisdiction (U.K. v. Ice.), 1973 I.C.J. 3 (Feb. 2)); see also Appeal Relating to the Jurisdiction of the ICAO Council (India v. Pak.), 1972 I.C.J. 46 (Aug. 18)); I.C.J. Namibia Advisory Opinion, supra note 56. 64. See infra text accompanying notes 71–74 (outlining customary international law generally). 65. See International Law Commission, supra note 54. A later section of this article discusses the customary status of article 60, paragraph 5. See infra Part IV. The International Law Commission draft cited herein did not include the provision that became paragraph 5 in the final version of the Vienna Convention. 66. The Vienna Convention’s rules on reciprocity replicate to some extent preparatory work of the Harvard Research in International Law project. Conducted between 1932 and 1935, the project produced a Draft Convention on the Law of Treaties as part of its comprehensive, multi-volume survey of International Law. Draft Convention on the Law of Treaties, in 29 AM. J. INT’L L. SUPP. (1935), reprinted in 2 THE HARVARD RESEARCH IN INTERNATIONAL LAW: ORIGINAL MATERIALS 1077 (John P. Grant & J. Craig Barker eds., 2008) [hereinafter HARVARD RESEARCH COMMENTARY]. Article 27 of the Draft Convention recognizes suspension of a treaty obligation as a legitimate response to breach. Id. The Draft Convention, however, requires consultation or authority from “a competent international tribunal” prior to declaring that the treaty itself is no longer binding. Id. The researchers were concerned that states ought not “be the final judges in their own causes by permitting them unilaterally to terminate the treaty as between themselves and the party or parties alleged to have violated the treaty.” Id. Article 60 of the Vienna Convention reveals that states chose not to adopt the consultation requirement. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60. 67. HARVARD RESEARCH COMMENTARY, supra note 66, at 1077.

R R R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

378

unknown

Seq: 14

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

accession by other states.68 For example, a number of treaties include offers to non-state parties to comply on an ad hoc basis or to express their intent to observe the instrument’s primary rules.69 In exchange, state parties agree to reciprocate. Although positive reciprocity represents a more hopeful strain of the doctrine, it is not an obligation under general international law. Its operation is usually restricted to treaties bearing such express provisions or offers made as a matter of state policy rather than law.70 The previous discussion demonstrates that states have developed and even codified highly refined secondary rules for treaty interpretation and application. These rules account for both obligational and observational components of reciprocity in treaty practice. The following section discusses the extent to which these rules operate in the separate realm of customary international law. B. Reciprocity and Customary International Law While treaty law is often cited as the chief source of modern international legal obligations,71 it by no means represents the full extent of international constraints on states’ conduct. In fact, in a hierarchy of international law, some commentators would give primacy to custom.72 According to a widely accepted formula, customary international law is general and consistent state practice exercised out of a sense of legal obligation.73 As conflicting case law and scholarship attests, however, the formula is much more easily stated than applied.74 The ambiguous nature and content of customary international law complicates its relationship with the principle of reciprocity. This section demonstrates that reciprocity operates slightly differently in the 68. KALSHOVEN & ZEGVELD, supra note 55, at 143. Article 2 of the 1949 Geneva Conventions anticipates positive reciprocity. 69. Geneva Convention Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3316, 75 U.N.T.S. 135; European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, Nov. 4, 1950, E.T.S. No. 50, 213 U.N.T.S. 222; Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A, at 71, U.N. GAOR, 3d Sess., 1st plen. mtg., U.N. Doc. A/810 (Dec. 12, 1948). 70. The Vienna Convention reflects no agreement between states on positive reciprocity evidently reserving the issue for resolution on a treaty-by-treaty basis. See Vienna Convention, supra note 27. 71. Maria Frankowska, The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties Before United States Courts, 28 VA. J. INT’L L. 281, 285 (1988) (stating that “treaties, ‘the cement that holds the world community together’ are today the primary source of international obligations”). But see THEODOR MERON, THE HUMANIZATION OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 360 (2006) (noting that customary law has regained ground since 1970s); ANTHONY A. D’AMATO, THE CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 12 (1971) (arguing that custom enjoys a more responsive process of development and broader scope of application than treaty law). 72. DAVID J. BEDERMAN, INTERNATIONAL LAW FRAMEWORKS 15 (2001); D’AMATO, supra note 71, at 12. 73. RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW OF THE UNITED STATES § 102 (1987). Similarly, the Statute of the International Court of Justice defines customary law as “evidence of general practice accepted as law.” Statute of the International Court of Justice art. 38, ¶ 1(b), June 26, 1945, 59 Stat. 1055, 33 U.N.T.S. 993. 74. See BARRY E. CARTER & PHILLIP R. TRIMBLE, INTERNATIONAL LAW 134–35 (3d ed. 1999) (citing J. STARKE, INTRODUCTION TO INTERNATIONAL LAW 34–38 (9th ed. 1984) and other scholarship investigating formation of customary international law).

R

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 15

25-JUN-09

7:50

379

realm of customary international law than in treaty law because custom does not require the consent of the parties to be binding. As a result, observational reciprocity is much more salient in this area than obligational reciprocity. Customary law supplements and interacts with treaty law in a complex manner.75 International norms and rules often migrate between custom and treaty.76 Treaty conferences not only create new law but also codify existing customary rules into the less ambiguous form of treaties. Similarly, provisions of widely-ratified and effective treaties often mature into customary rules that bind all states regardless of their individual ratification status. For instance, custom played a decisive role in the North Sea Continental Shelf cases addressed above. While the ICJ summarily dismissed the contention that the Continental Shelf Convention bound West Germany as a nonparty, the Court entertained far more seriously the Danish and Dutch position that the Convention’s provisions reflected preexisting customary international law.77 Ultimately, the Court found the evidence inadequate to support the argument that the Convention had merely codified preexisting customary rules concerning the demarcation of international nautical boundaries.78 Instead, the Court determined that the rule supporting the Danish and Dutch stance was “a purely conventional rule.”79 The Court also rejected the assertion that the Convention had matured into customary law after its entry into force. However, it conceded the principle behind the Danish and Dutch argument by noting that treaties can create binding norms if their provisions mature into custom. But the Court established a high burden of proof on parties seeking to give treaty provisions the exceptional effect of binding states that had not ratified them.80 In a similar vein, 75. See MARK E. VILLIGER, CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW AND TREATIES 122–30, 255–78 (1985) (discussing and contrasting the jus scriptum and custom, as well as explaining their very complex interactions). 76. Id. at 156–67, 237–49. 77. North Sea Continental Shelf Cases, supra note 38, ¶¶ 47–56, 60–68 (surveying state practice, opinions of international law experts and commissions, and decisions for indicia of the inherency or customary status of the equidistance rule). 78. Id. ¶ 69. 79. Id. ¶ 74. 80. Id. ¶¶ 71–74. The U.S. Supreme Court announced a similarly high standard of proof for the existence of customary norms in Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain, 542 U.S. 692, 733–34 (2004). The Court resorted to its own longstanding standard for identifying customary international law, observing: [C]laim[s] must be gauged against the current state of international law, looking to those sources we have long, albeit cautiously, recognized. “Where there is no treaty, and no controlling executive or legislative act or judicial decision, resort must be had to the customs and usages of civilized nations; and, as evidence of these, to the works of jurists and commentators, who by years of labor, research and experience, have made themselves peculiarly well acquainted with the subjects of which they treat. Such works are resorted to by judicial tribunals, not for the speculations of their authors concerning what the law ought to be, but for trustworthy evidence of what the law really is.” Id. (quoting The Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. 677, 700 (1900)).

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

380

unknown

Seq: 16

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Theodor Meron has identified examples of custom operating as a legal backstop where failures of reciprocity prevented treaties from operating.81 Early twentieth century scholarship suggested that the doctrine of reciprocity applied with equal force to both customary and treaty law.82 Lack of reciprocal obligation or observance gave rise to rights of suspension of customary law.83 However, current scholarship suggests that reciprocity might operate differently in the realm of custom.84 At a minimum, this is likely true for obligational reciprocity. By definition, established customary norms bind states regardless of formal or express indicia of consent such as ratification.85 Customary law reaches all states by virtue of their claims to sovereign status. Thus observance of customary norms is not subject to the condition of express reciprocal commitment from other states. Yet in the long term, repeated and especially widespread disregard or suspension of a rule of customary law would certainly undermine the element of state practice required for the rule to sustain its binding force. Custom may not be an effective check on the operation of reciprocity in international law. Customary international law recognizes the status of persistent objector,86 which refers to states that consistently and expressly pur-

81. Theodor Meron, The Continuing Role of Custom in the Formation of International Humanitarian Law, 90 AM. J. INT’L L. 238, 239 (1996). Meron cites failure of the 1907 Hague Regulations and the 1929 Geneva Convention during the Second World War as the basis for the International Military Tribunal’s and the U.S. Nuremberg Military Tribunal’s resort to custom. Id. (citing TRIAL OF MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS, 1946, CMD. 6964, Misc. No. 12, at 65; 11 TRIALS OF WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE NUREMBERG MILITARY TRIBUNALS UNDER CONTROL COUNCIL LAW No. 10, at 462, 533–35 (1948)). Meron also notes the International Court of Justice’s resort to custom to decide the Paramilitary Case between the United States and Nicaragua. Id. (citing Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.), Merits, 1986 I.C.J. 14, 114, ¶¶ 218–20 (June 27)). 82. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 24 (citing LE FUR, supra note 9). Le Fur contended that the doctrine of reciprocity applied equally to conventional and customary law. He observed that “[r]eciprocity is fundamental to a system of conventions between equals.” Without reciprocity, concluded Le Fur, “international law would work toward its own destruction.” Id. at 24 (translated by Kalshoven). 83. ZOLLER, supra note 9, at 15. 84. MARK E. VILLIGER, CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW AND TREATIES 274–75 (1985). Villiger contends that Article 60(5) operates with respect to both conventional and customary norms. Id. The International Law Commission has observed that the maxim inadimplenti non est adimplendum “was not a principle that applied to international law in general and was apparently not applicable in the context of customary law.” Summary Records of the 2590th Meeting, [1999] 1 Y.B. Int’l L. Comm’n 165, U.N. Doc. A/CN.4/SER.A./1999. 85. Although the formation of custom requires “general” practice, unanimous or universal practice or accession is not required to establish general obligation. See 1 HERSCH LAUTERPACHT, INTERNATIONAL LAW: COLLECTED PAPERS 68 (Elihu Lauterpacht ed., 1970). Lawyers in the U.S. Department of Justice Office of Legal Counsel expressed a skeptical view of the legal status of customary law, in part because it was not based on the express consent of states. Memorandum for William J. Haynes II, Gen. Counsel, Dep’t of Defense, Application of Treaties and Laws to al Qaeda and Taliban Detainees (Jan. 9, 2002) reprinted in THE TORTURE PAPERS, supra note 8, at 38, 72. 86. See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW OF THE UNITED STATES §102, cmt. d (1987) [hereinafter RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS]. Some writers express less enthusiastic support for the doctrine of persistent objection. See SHAW, supra note 32, at 86. Shaw limits the doctrine to states that have objected since the origin of the custom in question.

R

R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 17

25-JUN-09

7:50

381

port to opt out of particular customary norms.87 While some customary norms may not be subject to persistent objection, many can be avoided by rigorous exercise of objections.88 It is foreseeable that states bound by a customary norm would decline to apply that norm to persistent objectors on the basis of lack of reciprocal obligation. Thus persistent objection may be an exception to custom’s non-requirement of express obligational reciprocity. For instance, suppose that in the North Sea Continental Shelf cases Germany had conceded the customary status of the Continental Shelf Convention provision in question. Imagine that Denmark had persistently objected to the rule. Germany might then have argued effectively for an exercise of negative reciprocity with respect to this customary norm, at least vis-`a-vis Denmark. Germany could have claimed that though it was bound to respect non-objecting states’ boundaries with regard to the norm, Germany did not owe such respect to Denmark for its claim to exceptional excusal from the rule. No authoritative source resolves the scenario, yet the logic of obligational reciprocity appears apposite. Although the United States is not a party to the 1977 Additional Protocols to the Geneva Conventions, it has supported portions of the Protocols as reflective of customary international law.89 For instance, the United States has indicated that the Protocol I provisions on medical transportation of wounded, including the requirement that aircraft land for inspection when summoned in contested territory, reflect custom. Yet the United States makes clear that a summons to land need only be respected as a customary rule where “there is a reasonable basis to believe the party ordering the landing will respect the Geneva Conventions” or where the opposing force concludes an agreement to honor the rule in question itself.90 Thus reciprocal commitment to the law of war conditions the United States’ obligation to respect this customary norm. In the context of customary international law, states insist less on obligational reciprocity than observational reciprocity—that is, reciprocal practice. As demonstrated previously with respect to treaty-based norms,91 some cus87. Ted Stein, The Approach of the Different Drummer: The Principle of the Persistent Objector in International Law, 26 HARV. INT’L L.J. 457 (1985). 88. IAN BROWNLIE, PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 11 (5th ed. 1998); Jonathan I. Charney, The Persistent Objector Rule and the Development of Customary International Law, 56 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 1, 16 (1985). Other writers have offered criticism of the persistent objector doctrine. See Andrew T. Guzman, Saving Customary International Law, 27 MICH. J. INT’L L. 115, 166 (2005); Holning Lau, Rethinking the Persistent Objector Doctrine in International Human Rights Law, 6 CHI. J. INT’L L. 495 (2005). 89. See 1977 Protocols Additional to the Geneva Conventions: Memorandum for Mr. John H. McNeill, Assistant Gen. Counsel, Office of the Sec’y of Def., Customary International Law Implication (May 9, 1986) reprinted in THE JUDGE ADVOCATE GENERAL’S LEGAL CENTER & SCHOOL, LAW OF WAR DOCUMENTARY SUPPLEMENT 388, 389 (Sean Watts ed., 2006); Michael J. Matheson, Remarks in Session One: The United States Position on the Relation of Customary International Law to the 1977 Protocols Additional to the 1949 Geneva Convention, 2 AM. U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 419, 425 (1987). 90. Id. 91. See supra text accompanying notes 66–68.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

382

unknown

Seq: 18

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

tomary norms enjoy a degree of insulation from negative reciprocity. Peremptory norms, or so-called jus cogens, describe a body of law widely accepted as binding all states in all situations.92 Like custom, jus cogens does not require express consent. Jus cogens is not susceptible to derogation or preemption by treaty.93 Even adherents to the doctrine of persistent objection usually concede that states may not opt out of jus cogens norms.94 In fact, exemption from persistent objection may be a hallmark of jus cogens, distinguishing it from ordinary customary international law. That distinction itself, however, lends a degree of credibility to claims that negative reciprocity remains available to states with respect to ordinary customary norms. C. Reprisal Distinguished The practice of reprisal has also evolved from a fundamental and nearly universally recognized aspect of international law into a complex and contentious sanction. While reprisal’s application in the evolving international legal system is disputed, there is consensus on some limiting principles. First, reprisals are reactive sanctions. Defined simply, reprisals are violations of international law undertaken in response to unauthorized violations by another subject of international law.95 Breach of a binding rule is an absolute prerequisite to legitimate reprisal under nearly all conceptions of the practice.96 Reprisal also requires a degree of privity between parties. Generally, legitimate reprisals must be in response to breaches which have adversely affected the state in question.97 Accordingly, no authority recognizes a right to anticipatory reprisal. A second prerequisite for the exercise of reprisals is international legal personality.98 Only entities authorized to act within the international legal 92. See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS, supra note 86, cmt. k; United States v. MattaBallesteros, 71 F.3d 754, 764 (9th Cir. 1995). 93. See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF FOREIGN RELATIONS, supra note 86, cmt. k. Widely recognized jus cogens norms include rules against piracy, slavery, torture, and genocide. Id; see also Andrea Bianchi, Human Rights and the Magic of Jus Cogens, 19 EUR. J. INT’L L. 491 (2008). 94. Brad R. Roth, Abusive Treatment and the Limits of International Criminal Justice, 6 J. INT’L CRIM. JUST. 215, 224 (2008) (characterizing jus cogens norms as “all-purpose trumps” immune to persistent objection). 95. Naulilaa Case, 2 R.I.A.A., 1011 (1928), reprinted in WHITEMAN, DIGEST OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 148–49 (1963). The case, heard by an international arbitration tribunal established by the Versailles Treaty, addressed a German raid on Portuguese South-West Africa in retaliation for the death of three German citizens. “The sine qua non of a legitimate resort to reprisals is that there should have been a previous violation of international law by the other party . . . .” Id. The tribunal rejected Germany’s claim to a legitimate right of reprisal, finding that Portugal had not engaged in any prior breach of international law but had rather killed the German citizens by accident. Id. 96. Id.; Shane Darcy, The Evolution of the Law of Belligerent Reprisals, 175 MIL. L. REV. 184, 189 (2003). 97. See Michael J. Kelly, Time Warp to 1945—Resurrection of the Reprisal and Anticipatory Self-Defense Doctrines in International Law, 13 J. TRANSNAT’L L. & POL. 1, 7–8 (2003). 98. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 36–37. Kalshoven notes that reprisals, though aimed at the offending state, “almost certainly will have their direct impact on individuals who, as likely as not, are innocent of the wrong provoking the reprisal.” Id. at 42.

R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 19

25-JUN-09

7:50

383

system may carry out reprisals.99 Classic international legal theory conceives of the state as the primary, if not sole, legal actor.100 Although modern theories increasingly support a role for individuals in international law,101 no existing theory permits individuals to carry out reprisals in their personal capacities. As a matter of policy, power to approve reprisals is usually reserved to the highest national authority available.102 99. OPPENHEIM’S INTERNATIONAL LAW 138 (Hersch Lauterpacht ed., 6th ed. 1948) [hereinafter OPPENHEIM 2]. 100. See HENRY WHEATON, ELEMENTS OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 32 (Coleman Phillipson ed., 5th ed. 1916); CHARLES H. STOCKTON, OUTLINES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 61–63 (1914). Though generally adhering to the traditional model of international legal personality, Ian Brownlie observes that international organizations as well as states may satisfy conditions precedent to international personhood. BROWNLIE, supra note 88, at 58–59. International organizations such as the United Nations and regional human rights bodies are increasingly recognized as powerful actors in international relations and law. The exercise of reprisal rights by international organizations is not, however, well developed in practice or theory. Kalshoven concludes that international organizations should be included as possible participants in the practice of reprisal. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 28–29. International humanitarian organizations, including the International Committee of the Red Cross, are not parties to the Geneva Conventions. However, in the event that a Protecting Power is unable to fulfill its duties, “the following ‘substitutes’ are available to fulfill their duties: ‘an organization which offers all guarantees of impartiality and efficacy,’ ‘a neutral State or such an organization,’ or ‘a humanitarian organization, such as the International Committee of the Red Cross.’ ” Christiane Bourloyannis, The Security Council of the United Nations and the Implementation of International Humanitarian Law, 20 DENV. J. INT’L L. & POL’Y 335, 337 (1992) (quoting Common Article 8, ¶ 1 of the First, Second and Third Geneva Conventions and Article 9 of the Fourth Geneva Convention). This common article does not explicitly state that the right to reprisal is included in this delegation of responsibilities. See also Brian D. Tittemore, Belligerents in Blue Helmets: Applying International Humanitarian Law to United Nations Peace Operations, 33 STAN. J. INT’L L. 61 (1997) (discussing whether U.N. Peacekeeping troops should be subject to the rights and duties associated with International Humanitarian Law). Notwithstanding instances where non-governmental or supra-national organizations take on the duties of states, it is difficult to imagine them engaging in reprisal. 101. Thus, international human rights law envisions individuals as both beneficiaries and agents of enforcement. Twentieth century conceptions of human rights posit that individuals benefit from rights directly and merely by virtue of the inherent qualities of being a person. By comparison, traditional concepts of international law recognized individual protections only in a derivative sense. Benefits enjoyed by individuals under international law flow indirectly from the person’s status as an agent or as chattel of the state. Modern human rights law also provides for an individual role in enforcement. A number of human rights bodies have adopted complaint systems, permitting vindication of rights by individuals directly against member states. In this regard, individual enforcement in human rights law departs from the classic, sovereign-centric system of state self-help. 102. See U.S. DEP’T OF THE ARMY, FIELD MANUAL 27–10: THE LAW OF LAND WARFARE, ¶ 497 (1956): [Reprisals] should never be employed by individual soldiers except by direct orders of a commander, and the latter should give such orders only after careful inquiry into the alleged offense. The highest accessible military authority should be consulted unless immediate action is demanded, in which event a subordinate commander may order appropriate reprisals upon his own initiative. Id. The Canadian Armed Forces manual provides, “The decision to take reprisal action must therefore be authorized at the highest political level. Operational commanders on their own initiative are not authorized to carry out reprisals.” OFFICE OF THE JUDGE ADVOCATE GENERAL OF CANADA, LAW OF ARMED CONFLICT AT THE OPERATIONAL AND TACTICAL LEVELS, 15–3 (2004). The British Manual of Military Law includes a similar reservation of authority. MINISTRY OF DEFENCE, BRITISH MANUAL OF MILITARY LAW, pt. III ¶ 645 (1958). Even the earliest codifications of reprisal doctrine reserved their authorization to the highest level of command. Accordingly, the Oxford Manual for Military Law of 1880 reserved reprisals to authorization by “the commander in chief.” Institute of International Law, Oxford Manual

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

384

unknown

Seq: 20

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Most importantly, reprisals can only be undertaken to induce or compel renewed compliance with the rule breached. The overarching purpose of reprisal “is to coerce the addressee to change its policy and bring it into line with the requirements of international law.”103 Two important restraints on reprisal flow directly from its purpose. First, reprisals are subsidiary.104 Subsidiarity requires that states exhaust less drastic means of enforcement, such as diplomatic protest, prior to resorting to reprisal. It performs the important function of reducing miscommunication of motives through breaches of international law. Threats or warnings of reprisals are considered prerequisites to actual reprisals.105 Second, reprisals must be proportionate to the violations that provoke them.106 Though it is an ambiguous standard, proportionality ensures that the scale of reprisals does not become unmoored from its purpose of preventing repeat violations.107 Reprisals include retaliatory, punitive, and rehabilitative elements, all directed at inducing renewed compliance. Rather than resurrecting compliance, disproportionate reprisals have the effect of provoking further retaliation. Proportionality purports to restrain such cycles of escalating breaches. There are tempting connections to be drawn between the principal of reciprocity and the practice of reprisal. At the most basic level, each constitutes a state response to a counterpart’s breach. Reciprocity and reprisal are thus closely related as means of state self-help in the international legal system. Each is also a product of states’ peculiar status as both subjects and authorities in the international legal system.108 Early attempts to codify authority and limits concerning reprisal and reciprocity often conflated the two or grounded the former in the latter.109 Yet important distinctions differentiate reciprocity from reprisal and illustrate the theoretical foundations of each form of sanction. 1880: The Laws of War on Land, in THE LAWS OF ARMED CONFLICTS 29, art. 86 (D. Schindler & J. Toman eds., Martinus Nihjoff 1988) (1880) [hereinafter Oxford Manual]. 103. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 33. 104. Id. The International Arbitrators in the Naulilaa Case noted that German reprisals should have been preceded by a demand for reparations. Naulilaa Case, supra note 95. 105. Darcy, supra note 96, at 193. 106. Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, 1996 I.C.J. 226, 246, ¶ 46 (July 8); Naulilaa Case, supra note 95; KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 33. 107. MYERS S. MCDOUGAL & FLORENTINO P. FELICIANO, LAW AND MINIMUM WORLD PUBLIC ORDER 682 (1961). 108. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 21–22 (“International society is characterized by the ambiguous position of States as member-subjects and authorities at the same time.”). 109. See Oxford Manual, supra note 102, art. 84. “Reprisals are an exception to the general rule of equity, that an innocent person ought not to suffer for the guilty. They are also at variance with the rule that each belligerent should conform to the rules of war, without reciprocity on the part of the enemy.” Id. While the Manual formed the basis for negotiations that produced the Hague Regulations of 1899, its observations on reprisals and reciprocity were not reproduced. Uncharacteristically, Lauterpacht adds some confusion in his description of reciprocity as an element of reprisal. Lauterpacht describes “negative reprisal” as “refusal to perform such acts as are under ordinary circumstances obligatory, such as the fulfilment of a treaty obligation or the payment of a debt.” OPPENHEIM 2, supra note 99, at 140.

R R R R R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 21

25-JUN-09

7:50

385

Negative reciprocity and reprisal differ most significantly in their respective effects on the underlying legal rule.110 Reprisal assumes, and seeks to compel, continued operation of the law in question. In this sense, reprisal affirms international law, reflecting the importance and value that states place on compliance.111 The temporal component of reprisal is illustrative: international law authorizes reprisals only while the offending state persists in breach.112 The offending state extinguishes the legal basis for reprisal when it realigns itself with the norm in question. Negative reciprocity, by contrast, suspends or terminates the legal obligation altogether. Actions justified by failure of reciprocal observance regard the law in question as extinguishable or entirely inapplicable in the event of breach. Unlike reprisal, reciprocity is not formally subject to the requirements of subsidiarity and proportionality.113 To exercise negative reciprocity, states need not necessarily exhaust other means of sanction. Material breach is sufficient. Furthermore, negative reciprocity can be exercised in an anticipatory sense. Faced with persistent evidence that a counterpart intends not to honor a legal rule, a state might reasonably regard the norm as inapplicable in its relations with that counterpart. Obligational reciprocity permits states to suspend or withhold operation of a legal rule without waiting for a material breach. Recurring objections to a norm in question, formal treaty reservations, and consistent patterns of state practice would indicate future intent to disregard an international norm. In this sense, obligational reciprocity operates less like a sanction than a mere determination of applicability—in other words, as a secondary rule of international law. The principle of negative reciprocity operates under other restraints that do not limit the practice of reprisal. Negative reciprocity operates with respect to particular provisions of international law. As a general matter, the reach of reciprocity is limited to the rule breached or repudiated. Legal doctrine limits suspension of entire legal covenants or regimes in favor of suspension of the particular provision breached by a counterpart.114 Negative reciprocity does not authorize suspension or termination of unrelated or even collateral legal norms. Reprisal is not similarly restricted. Reprisal may take the form of breach of an entirely separate or unrelated legal provision.115 For instance, in response to a breach of diplomatic immunity, a state may violate the protected economic interests of the state concerned, so long as it observes the principles of subsidiarity and proportionality. In this regard, the 110. Maurice Greenspan notes, “Reprisals are illegitimate acts of warfare, not for the purpose of indicating abandonment of the laws of war, but, on the contrary, to force compliance to those laws.” MAURICE GREENSPAN, THE MODERN LAW OF LAND WARFARE 407–08 (1959). 111. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 43. 112. Christopher Greenwood, The Twilight of the Law of Belligerent Reprisals, 20 NETH. Y.B. INT’L L. 45–46 (1989). 113. KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 363. 114. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60, ¶¶ 1–3. 115. Kalshoven observes that “reprisals need not affect the same norm as has been violated by the original offender.” KALSHOVEN, supra note 9, at 25.

R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

386

unknown

Seq: 22

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

means selected for reprisal are a function of anticipated effect on compliance rather than an effort to match or reciprocate the addressee’s breach.116 By contrast, reciprocity is an effort to reestablish a position of equality—a leveling of comparative legal obligations and conduct. III. RECIPROCITY

AND THE

DEVELOPMENT

OF THE

LAW

OF

WAR

The law of war has always included its own system of secondary rules that supplement the rules that apply to all international law.117 This section argues that the history of the law of war and its relationship with reciprocity reveals a trajectory of development, refinement, and obscuration of reciprocity doctrine. The law of war has long included strong evidence of conditions of reciprocity in both its specific and diffuse forms.118 The earliest laws of war relied on professional custom and ensured reciprocal observance by restricting application to elite classes of combatants. Later positive provisions included express conditions on application that vindicated similar concerns over combatants’ capacity and willingness to observe constraints. While some of these provisions were enforced only sporadically and ultimately vanished, they were often replaced by veiled conditions on the application of the law of war that had much the same effect as explicit conditions of reciprocity. At times, state reservations reinforced restrictive provisions on application. Even after the most important and humanitarian-focused revision of the law of war in 1949, reciprocity was never entirely eliminated in a positivist sense. Rather, conditions of reciprocity merely changed form. A. Early History Just as warfare has always included restraints on conduct,119 the law of war has nearly always limited the application of its rules to specified circumstances and persons. Although prohibitions on inhuman or unnecessary killing and destruction are nearly universal, they are also nearly universally qualified. Numerous exceptions have succeeded the seemingly categorical injunction, “Thou shalt not kill.”120 Jean-Jacques Fr´esard observes that “[r]eligions themselves are the first to specify, more or less explicitly, that the injunction concerns above all our people. The others, the ‘unbelievers,’ infidels and apostates, may be run through by the swords of men when they are not simply delivered up to the sword of God.”121 For example, ancient 116. According to Kalshoven, “[I]n selecting a reprisal action the decision-makers in the State will be guided by considerations of estimated effect rather than reciprocity . . . .” Id. 117. See supra discussion accompanying notes 21–26, discussing secondary rules in international law. 118. See supra discussion accompanying notes 16–20. 119. See PERCY BORDWELL, LAW OF WAR 8–9 (1908) (noting “incidents of humanity” in conflict in ancient Hindu and Aryan civilizations). ´ 120. JEAN-JACQUES FRESARD , THE ROOTS OF BEHAVIOR IN WAR 22 (2004) (quoting Exodus 20:13). 121. Id.

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 23

25-JUN-09

7:50

387

Hebrews distinguished protections for civilians belonging to immediate enemies from civilians belonging to remote enemies. Drawn from the Bible, such customs permitted a free hand in dealing with the former, even permitting genocide, while protecting the latter and their property from arbitrary violence.122 Although strong evidence supports the law of war’s religious foundations,123 a second wellspring for many early restraints on conduct in war was the sense of fraternity between belligerents.124 The military class developed a sense of respect and honor that called for restraint among its members. Combatants began to appreciate the long-term benefits of such restraints as honoring surrenders and respecting the wounded comrades and enemies alike.125 Only the warrior class observed these rules.126 The preterit law of war always operated most reliably between the professional military classes of homogeneous cultures.127 Some have argued that its restrictive application resulted from the conclusion that only members of the professional military class could guarantee compliance with battlefield proscriptions.128 A common thought was that only those schooled in the customs and traditions of organized combat would observe its elaborate constraints—undoubtedly, an early manifestation of reciprocity. Furthermore, the relatively limited and conjunct class of combatants ensured accountability for atrocities. Acts of treachery ignited costly and prolonged blood feuds.129 Restraint tended to diminish in conflicts between elites and lower social orders where such vengeance-based sanctions were unlikely.130 122. 1 THE LAW OF WAR: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY 4 (Leon Friedman ed., 1972) (citing Deuteronomy 20:10–17). 123. See STEPHEN C. NEFF, WAR AND THE LAW OF NATIONS 45 (2005) (describing the evolution of just war doctrine from Christian theology). 124. Michael Howard observes, “Restraint on war grew out of the cultures of the war-making societies, rather than being imposed on them by some transcendent moral order.” Michael Howard, Constraints on Warfare, in THE LAWS OF WAR 2 (Michael Howard et al. eds., 1994). 125. Id. at 3. 126. The terms bellum romanum and guerre mortelle often refer to early European conflicts fought against barbarians or infidels without restraint or discrimination. Id. Bellum romanum was waged against three categories of enemy: “rebels, infidels, and ‘savages.’ ” Id. at 5. 127. Id. at 3 (explaining that earliest norms of combat applied as matters of professional respect between elite classes of warriors and were generally not extended to “barbarians” or “infidels”). Geoffrey Best observes, “[E]veryone with strong experience of the active conduct of war understood two things very well: first, that its laws and customs could only be observed in relation to circumstances and, second, that in any ordinary tussle between law and military necessity, law would have to be accommodating.” GEOFFREY BEST, LAW AND WAR SINCE 1945, at 22 (1997). 128. For example, Robert Stacey observes, “The laws of war governing pitched battles were quite detailed, but they applied only to knights and squires, in the later Middle Ages the only two groups capable of bearing heraldic insignia.” Robert C. Stacy, The Age of Chivalry, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 36. 129. See Geoffrey Parker, Early Modern Europe, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 54. 130. See id.; Harold Selesky, Colonial America, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 59 (observing that controls over the use of force “slip . . . away on the margins”). Selesky notes a high level of barbarity in engagements between English and French forces where the latter extensively employed Native American forces. Id. at 57–58. Confronted with an unfamiliar enemy, English soldiers did not observe the restraints associated with conflicts between professional armies. Id. at 85.

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

388

unknown

Seq: 24

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Geoffrey Parker suggests that durability of relations was the essential condition for restraint in war in pre-Enlightenment Europe, because it provided “some certainty that the two sides will meet again.”131 In the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, professional fraternity and shared cultural identity receded as the foundations for restraint in war. Law of war historians note the development of relatively less exclusive behavioral customs in later periods of Western warfare. Their works suggest a convergence of natural law, military law, ecclesiastical precept and self interest.132 However, restraints of the period had more to do with improving discipline and preventing distractions associated with looting and pillaging than with vindicating humanitarian concerns or universal rules of combat.133 Thus while combatants began to recognize practical advantages to mutual restraint, the code that emerged remained in most respects “a contractual etiquette of belligerence” conditioned on opponents having both the capacity and resolve to respect its terms.134 B. The Early Positive Law of War Until the late eighteenth century, custom was nearly the sole source of international regulation of warfare. But by the mid-nineteenth century, custom had become sufficiently refined to be regarded as a “common law of war.”135 Custom had the advantage of widespread applicability but lacked 131. Parker, supra note 129, at 57. Surveying the Napoleonic Wars of the early nineteenth century, Gunther Rothenberg observes that self interest of combatants played an important role in the operation of restraints on warfare. Gunther Rothenberg, The Age of Napoleon, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 97. Rothenberg argues that the traditional accounts of hostilities devolving from highly regulated encounters into total chaos are greatly exaggerated. Id. Accounting for exceptions, Rothenberg notes that combatants largely observed the laws and customs of warfare out of self interest with significant collateral humanitarian impact. Id. Robert Axelrod offers similar observations concerning the importance of repeat encounters to the development of cooperation between parties. ROBERT AXELROD, THE EVOLUTION OF COOPERATION 129 (1984). He explains that during World War I, the immobile and static nature of trench warfare ensured prolonged interaction between small military units. Prolonged interaction permitted patterns of cooperation based on reciprocity to develop between enemies. Id. Specifically, Axelrod notes a system of “liveand-let-live” wherein each side declined to engage or kill the other. Id. at 74. 132. Parker, supra note 129, at 42; see also Howard, supra note 124, at 4 (“[T]here were beginning to creep into the conduct of war not only prudential but ethical constraints on their treatment.”). 133. BEST, supra note 127, at 34 . 134. Parker, supra note 129, at 41. Geoffrey Best observes, “Humanitarian commentators in our own time too easily fall into the good-natured error of transferring their universalist principles on to ages and peoples whose views of their own species were strictly discriminatory.” BEST, supra note 127, at 24–25. 135. Emer de Vattel mentions the customary status of the law of war in his early nineteenth century work on the law of nations: The war being reputed equal between two enemies, whatever is permitted to one, in virtue of the state of war, is also permitted to the other. Accordingly no nation under pretence of justice being on its side, ever complains of the hostilities of the enemy, while they observe the terms prescribed by the common laws of war. EMER DE VATTEL, THE LAW OF NATIONS, OR, PRINCIPLES OF THE LAW OF NATURE, APPLIED TO THE CONDUCT AND AFFAIRS OF NATIONS AND SOVEREIGNS: A WORK TENDING TO DISPLAY THE TRUE INTEREST OF POWERS 447 (Nicklin & Johnson eds., 1829).

R R

R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 25

25-JUN-09

7:50

389

clarity. Although states could not mandate universal consent, they eventually clarified the law of war through international legal instruments. 1. Early Law of War Treaty Provisions Reciprocity figured prominently in the earliest treaty-based law of war provisions. The first international legal instruments to regulate warfare were bilateral treaties. These instruments were not aimed at regulating warfare per se but were rather broad efforts to maintain peaceful and productive relations between states.136 The articles that addressed the law of war were brief and subsidiary to the purpose of the treaties. Scholars credit the U.S.Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce as one of the earliest positive international formulations of restraint on the conduct of land warfare.137 The treaty established rules of neutrality in case either state engaged in war with a third state,138 guaranteed safe return to civilians in the event of war between the parties139, and provided for the safe and open detention of prisoners of war.140 Upon first inspection, the Treaty of Amity appears to be conditioned on obligational and observational reciprocity. Indeed, the Treaty preamble recites reciprocity as a basis for the agreement.141 However, the Treaty’s provisions on the law of war were insulated from at least one general justification for suspension, termination in the event of war. The Treaty explicitly stated 136. See DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR 4–5 (Adam Roberts & Richard Guelff eds., 3d ed. 2000) (noting bilateral treaties also used to fix obligations of neutrality since the early seventeenth century) (citing W.E. HALL, THE RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF NEUTRALS 27–46 (1874)). 137. Treaty of Amity and Commerce Between his Majesty the King of Prussia and the United States of America, U.S.-Prussia, Sept. 10, 1785 [hereinafter U.S.-Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce], reprinted in DIETRICH SCHINDLER & JIRI TOMAN, THE LAWS OF ARMED CONFLICT (4th ed. 2004). Two bilateral treaties that preceded the U.S.-Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce dealt primarily with maritime legal customs. See THE LAW OF WAR: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY, supra note 122, at 149 (citing Treaty of Amity and Commerce Between the United States of American and his Most Christian Majesty, U.S.-Fr., Feb. 6., 1778, 8 Stat. 12 [hereinafter U.S.-Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce]; Treaty of Amity and Commerce between their High Mightinesses the United Netherlands, and the United States of America, U.S.-Neth., Oct. 8, 1782, 8 Stat. 32). 138. U.S.-Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce, supra note 137, art. 12. 139. Id. art. 23. Article 23 took its form from a nearly identical clause proposed for the peace treaty concluding the American Revolutionary War. BORDWELL, supra note 119, at 69–70. Benjamin Franklin drafted the original proposal to the U.S.-Great Britain Treaty of Peace and saw that it was included in the U.S.-Prussian Treaty. Id. at 70. 140. U.S.-Prussia Treaty of Amity and Commerce, supra note 137, art. 24. Protections for prisoners of war included freedom from confinement in dungeons, prisons or ships; a prohibition on shackling; rations comparable to those provided to forces of the detaining power; and receipt of comfort items and supplies. Id. 141. Id. pmbl. The Treaty’s preamble states: His majesty the King of Prussia, & the United States of America, desiring to fix, in a permanent and equitable manner, the rules to be observed in the intercourse and commerce they desire to establish between their respective countries, his majesty & the United States have judged that the said end cannot be better obtained than by taking the most perfect equality and reciprocity for the basis of their agreement. Id. (emphasis added).

R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

390

unknown

Seq: 26

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

that it would persist in case of war between the parties, eliminating the option to exercise negative reciprocity.142 States continued to enact bilateral treaties to regulate conduct in war continued through the mid-nineteenth century.143 However, records of state practice concerning these treaties are scant. Beyond the language of the treaties themselves, there is little evidence to show how the principle of reciprocity bore on observance, suspension, or termination of treaty obligations. The conclusion of such treaties certainly suggests some reciprocal commitment to the principles included therein. Perceptions about which other states would likely reciprocate may have contributed to the limited and bilateral nature of these treaties. Limits on termination and suspension of these instruments usually precluded the option of resorting to arms in retaliation for breach. On the other hand, resort to negative reciprocity, particularly suspension of a breached provision, does not seem entirely foreclosed by their text. 2. The U.S. Lieber Code Despite the formative role of bilateral treaties in the effort to codify customary restraints on warfare, the most influential nineteenth century codification of the law of war was not itself an international instrument. Just as 142. Id. The preamble goes on to state: & it is declared, that neither the pretence that war dissolves all treaties, nor any other whatever, shall be declared as annulling or suspending this & the next preceding article, but on the contrary, that the state of war is precisely that for which they are provided, & during which they are to be as sacredly observed as the most acknowledged articles in the law of nature or nations. Id. The last clause suggests a persistence or immunity from conditions of reciprocity, recognizing a nearly peremptory status for the norms of Articles 23 and 24. It is uncertain how the parties envisioned this provision would interact with the preamble’s stated commitment to the principle of reciprocity. 143. See, e.g., Treaty of Peace and Amity, concluded between the United States of America and the Dey and Regency of Algiers, Feb. 11, 1822, reprinted in 2 TREATIES AND OTHER INTERNATIONAL ACTS OF THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA (Hunter Miller ed., 1931). The Treaty guaranteed safe passage to diplomats and civilians in case of war between the parties. The parties disclaimed resort to war as a response to breach prior to a three-month period of notice and redress. Id. art. 16. The Treaty did not address retaliation or reciprocity more explicitly. See also Chilean-American Diplomacy Convention of Peace, Amity, Commerce, and Navigation, U.S.-Chile, May 16, 1832, available at http://avalon.law.yale. edu/19th_century/chile01.asp. The Treaty guaranteed the safe return of civilians from occupied territory in the event of war. Id. art. 23. Article 31 relegated retaliation for breach, including either negative reciprocity or reprisal, to a subsidiary status. Id. art. 31. In the event of breach, both states agreed to serve notice and provide an opportunity for redress prior to exercising traditional forms of state self-help. Id. Reciprocity assumes a central place in the Treaty by virtue of the following opening passage from the preamble: [D]esiring to make firm and lasting the friendship and good understanding which happily prevail between both nations, have resolved to fix, in a manner clear, distinct and positive, the rules which shall in future be religiously observed between the one and the other, by means of a treaty . . . .” Id. pmbl. (emphasis added). In 1872, the United States and the Netherlands agreed, in the event of hostilities, to allow a nine-month evacuation period for the citizens of each state, “in all freedom and without hindrance.” THE LAW OF WAR: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY, supra note 122, at xiv.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 27

25-JUN-09

7:50

391

surprising, the instrument in question arose in the context of a domestic conflict. U.S. General Order No.100 of 1863—commonly called the Lieber Code after its author and promoter, Dr. Francis Lieber—is widely credited with kicking off the late nineteenth century trend of codifying the customs and usages of war into multilateral treaties.144 In addition to codifying preexisting norms of respect for wounded combatants and prisoners, the Lieber Code added significantly to prevailing military custom.145 The Code dealt

144. UNITED STATES WAR DEPARTMENT, INSTRUCTIONS FOR THE GOVERNMENT OF ARMIES IN THE FIELD (General Orders No. 100, prepared by Francis Lieber, L.L.D.) (1863) [hereinafter Lieber Code]. Roberts and Guelff affirm the influence the Lieber Code had on future national and international law of war instruments. DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 12–13. The Lieber Code was a starting point for many international treaty conventions in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. “Perhaps the landmark international breakthough came at the Hague in 1899 with the signing by twenty-four nations of the ‘Convention with Respect to the Laws and Customs of War on Land.’ This document ‘leaned heavily’ on the Lieber code established in the U.S. . . . . ” Ron Sievert, A New Perspective on the International Criminal Court: Why the Right Should Embrace the ICC and How America Can Use It, 68 U. PITT. L. REV. 77, 89 (2006); see Corrine Brenner, Cultural Property Law: Reflecting the Bamiyan Buddhas’ Destruction, 29 SUFFOLK TRANSNAT’L L. REV. 237, 240 (2006) (citing the Lieber code as the basis for protecting cultural property during war-time); Mary Deutsch Schneider, About Women, War and Darfur: The Continuing Quest for Gender Violence Justice, 83 N.D. L. REV. 915, 923 (2007) (citing the Lieber code as codifing sexual violence as a war crime). To be sure, the Lieber Code was not the first articles of war issued to an army. Barbara Donagan notes that several early articles of war and even permanent legislation governed sixteenth and seventeenth century armies. Barbara Donagan, Codes of Conduct in the English Civil War, in 118 PAST AND PRESENT 65, 74–76 (1988). Such codes typically prescribed conduct of loyalty, but also included restraints on conduct toward civilians. Id. at 82. Examining legal limitations on seventeenth century European armies, Donagan identifies three primary sources of restraint: the law of nature and nations, the law of war, and military law. Id. at 74–75. The pre-Lieber Code 1856 Paris Declaration Respecting Maritime Law is widely acknowledged to be the first multilateral law of war instrument. Paris Declaration Respecting Maritime Law, Apr. 16, 1856, 46 BFSP 26, reprinted in DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 47–49. The Declaration did not address humanitarian concerns beyond respect for property and duties of neutral powers. Parties to the Declaration agreed to limit the use of privateers and the seizure of neutral property at sea. Id. at 49. As evidence that its rules were based on obligational reciprocity, the Declaration’s penultimate clause limits the parties’ obligations to states that have acceded to the Declaration. Id. 145. During the American Civil War, Lieber wrote: How far rules which have formed themselves in the course of time between belligerents might be relaxed with safety toward the evildoers in our civil war; or how far such relaxation or mitigation would be likely to produce a beneficial effect upon an enemy who, in committing a great and bewildering wrong, seems to have withdrawn himself from the common influences of fairness, sympathy, truth and logic-how far this ought to be done at the present moment must be decided by the executive power, civil and military, or possibly by the legislative power. It is not for me in [this] place to make the inquiry. So much is certain, that no army, no society engaged in war, any more than a society at peace, can allow unpunished assassination, robbery, and devastation without the deepest injury to itself and disastrous consequences which might change the very issue of the war. RICHARD SHELLY HARTIGAN, LIEBER’S CODE AND THE LAW OF WAR 12, 13, 19–20 (1983); see Stephen W. Simpson, Shoot First, Ask Questions Later: Double Tapping Under the Laws of War, 108 W. VA. L. REV. 751, 759–60 (2006) (noting the importance of the Lieber Code as the precursor to the modern laws of war).

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

392

unknown

Seq: 28

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

explicitly with regulation of occupied territory,146 guerrilla tactics,147 and even protections for civilians and their property.148 Despite its encouraging humanitarian provisions, the Lieber Code took a harsh view of reciprocity. The Code provided, “The law of war can no more wholly dispense with retaliation than can the law of nations, of which it is a branch. Yet civilized nations acknowledge retaliation as the sternest feature of war.”149 Subsequent articles reinforce the Lieber Code’s tolerance for retaliation by permitting the suspension of the Code’s protections in the event of enemy abuses.150 It is unclear whether the Code’s references to retaliation meant to reserve a right to exercise negative reciprocity, belligerent reprisals, or both.151 Explaining the conditions for resort to retaliation, the Code notes only retributive goals.152 Reciprocity and retaliation share “the idea of doing the same thing in response to something.”153 Like negative reciprocity, retributive retaliation suggests an intent to balance accounts between forces rather than to inspire future compliance, the hallmark of belligerent reprisal. In its final section, the Code addresses the law of war’s scope of application. The Code regarded the application of the laws and customs of war to internal conflicts as a matter of state discretion.154 Presaging later qualifications on rules applicable to internal conflicts, the Code denied that a state’s decision to apply the law of war had any legal effect on the legitimacy of 146. Lieber Code, supra note 144, arts. 1–7. 147. Id. arts. 81–85. 148. Id. art. 23. 149. Id. art. 27. 150. Id. arts. 61–62. Stone offers support for associating retaliation with reciprocity. JULIUS STONE, LEGAL CONTROLS OF INTERNATIONAL CONFLICT 354 (2d ed. 1959) (“The premise on which retaliation in war proceeds is, indeed, that a belligerent’s duty to observe the laws of war is not absolute, but conditional on the enemy’s reciprocation.”). 151. The first edition of Colonel William Winthrop’s highly influential treatise on Military Law does not address reciprocity. WILLIAM WINTHROP, MILITARY LAW AND PRECEDENTS (1886). His omission may not be surprising given that the positive law of war was still primarily restricted to national codes and instructions to armed forces. The major efforts to develop multilateral treaties on the law of war were still in nascent stages when Winthrop wrote. The omission of conditions of reciprocity from the second edition of Winthrop’s work in 1920 is less easily explained. WILLIAM WINTHROP, MILITARY LAW AND PRECEDENTS (2d ed. 1920). The preface to the second edition advertises a material supplement to the previous edition’s law of war section. Id. at 7. Yet the section draws exclusively on pre-twentieth century sources for support, despite major multilateral codifications of the law of war at the 1899 and 1907 Hague Conferences. See infra Part III.C. It may be best to understand Winthrop’s work on the law of war, including the 1920 update, as a limited survey of nineteenth century custom. 152. Lieber Code, supra note 144, art. 28. Article 28 reads:

R

R

Retaliation will, therefore, never be resorted to as a measure of mere revenge, but only as a means of protective retribution, and moreover, cautiously and unavoidably; that is to say, retaliation shall only be resorted to after careful inquiry into the real occurrence, and the character of the misdeeds that may demand retribution. Id. 153. ZOLLER, supra note 9, at 14. Zoller notes that the Latin root of retaliation, “talio,” developed from “talis” meaning “of the same quality.” Id. 154. Lieber Code, supra note 144, art. 152.

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 29

25-JUN-09

7:50

393

insurrection or rebellion.155 The Code does not indicate whether a rebel force’s compliance could compel reciprocal state observance. Humanitarian concerns are the only cited justification for applying the regular law of war to rebels.156 Although technically not binding on Confederate forces, the Code’s retaliation provisions clearly anticipated reciprocal observance by the armed forces of the South. With the exception of its use of guerilla warfare, the Confederate Army was in most respects a peer of the Union Army.157 In fact, a significant portion of the United States’ pre-Civil War professional military class had defected to the South.158 The Code granted belligerent— and consequently prisoner of war—status to a broad range of Confederate participants, including partisans,159 sutlers,160 reporters,161 and scouts. Only spies, traitors, and brigands not formally incorporated into the Confederacy’s forces were categorically excluded from protection.162 The Code thus expressed a strong preference for protecting conventional forces similar to those of the state in organization and conduct. 155. Id. See generally DONALD A. WELLS, THE LAWS OF LAND WARFARE: A GUIDE TO U.S. ARMY MANUALS 3 (1992). States have included similar caveats in modern international conventions regulating internal armed conflicts. Common Article 3 of the four 1949 Geneva Conventions provides, “The application of the preceding provisions shall not affect the legal status of the Parties to the conflict.” Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces in the Field art. 3, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3114, 75 U.N.T.S. 31 [hereinafter 1949 Geneva Convention I]; Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded, Sick, and Shipwrecked Members of Armed Forces at Sea art. 3, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3217, 75 U.N.T.S. 85 [hereinafter 1949 Geneva Convention II]; Convention Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War art.3, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3316, 75 U.N.T.S. 135 [hereinafter 1949 Geneva Convention III]; Convention Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War art. 3, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3516, 75 U.N.T.S. 287 [hereinafter 1949 Geneva Convention IV]. 156. Lieber Code, supra note 144, art. 152. 157. Although the Confederate Army only mobilized one million troops to the Union Army’s 2.6 million, the composition of the two armies was similar. Both consisted of relatively small classes of officers and enlisted men with overwhelming numbers of new recruits. Since the Confederate Army was led by West Point graduates, its organization scheme was almost identical to the regular U.S. Army, and ´ by extension the Union Army. The methods employed by the Confederate Army mirrored French Ecole Polytechnique and the Napoleonic model. See Robert M. Epstein, The Creation and Evolution of the Army Corps in the American Civil War, 55 J. MILITARY HIST. 21, 22 (1991); see also HERMAN HATTAWAY & ARCHER JONES, HOW THE NORTH WON: A MILITARY HISTORY OF THE CIVIL WAR 10 (1983). 158. See HATTAWAY & JONES, supra note 157. Many officers from Southern states were either dismissed or allowed to resign from the Army at the beginning of the Civil War. Prior to resignations or dismissals, 1,105 officers were in the regular army. Id. Of this group, 809 officers remained with the Union army and 270 officers joined the confederacy. Id. The officers were almost all professionally trained at West Point. Id. “West Point graduates on the active list numbered 824; of these, 184 became Confederate officers. Of the approximately 900 military academy graduates then in civilian life, 114 returned to the Union army and ninety-nine others acquired southern commissions.” Id. Incidentally, Henry Heth, the West Point graduate who translated the French tactical guide used by both armies in the Civil War, later defected to serve in the Confederate Army. Epstein, supra note 157 at 23. Geoffrey Best posits that the Lieber Code may have been a response to the character of the United States’ new enemy. Led by gentlemen and former members of its own armed forces, the Union Army could not have employed practices used against “Red Indians and Mexicans.” BEST, supra note 127, at 41. 159. Lieber Code, supra note 144, art. 81. 160. Id. art. 50. 161. Id. 162. Id. arts. 82–84, 90–91, 103.

R

R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

394

unknown

Seq: 30

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

The Lieber Code was a great textual advance for positive humanitarian concerns in war.163 The Code is well-understood as a codification of the general common law of war applied as a matter of policy to a civil war.164 Despite its humanitarian attentions, the Code was conditioned on observational reciprocity. A series of efforts inspired by the Code demonstrated the continued role of reciprocity in international codifications of the common law of war. 3. Early Multilateral Law of War Treaties Enthusiasm for codifying the law of war spread through Europe at the end of the nineteenth century. Pursuing diverse objectives, multiple efforts continued Lieber’s work. A Swiss businessman who observed the intense suffering of wounded and sick combatants at the Battle of Solferino led the movement that produced the 1864 Geneva Convention and its iterative incarnations.165 A scant ten articles, the Convention focused exclusively on humanitarian concerns for the wounded and contained no explicit limits on application or conditions of reciprocity. However, other contemporaneous treaties placed far more emphasis on reciprocity. In 1868, Czar Alexander II of Russia invited the world’s major powers to St. Petersburg, a gathering which resulted in a declaration that renounced the use of exploding or inflammable substances in light projectiles.166 But the binding force of the Declaration was conditioned on the strictest obligational reciprocity. By its terms, the Declaration applied only to conflicts comprised exclusively of states parties to the treaty.167 The Declaration did not address consequences of breach between parties, presumably leaving questions of negative reciprocity to international law. 163. Deplorable conditions of confinement for some prisoners of war and instances of indiscriminate campaigns caution against championing the Lieber Code as a practical success at humanizing the American Civil War. See ROBERT KNOX SNEDEN, EYE OF THE STORM : A CIVIL WAR ODYSSEY (2000); EARL SCHENCK MIERS, THE GENERAL WHO MARCHED TO HELL: WILLIAM TECUMSEH SHERMAN AND HIS MARCH TO FAME AND INFAMY (1951). 164. The United States reissued General Order 100 to its armed forces during the Spanish-American War. WELLS, supra note 155, at 4–5. 165. HENRY DUNANT, A MEMORY OF SOLFERINO (Am. Red Cross trans., 1986) (1862); see ANGELA BENNETT, THE GENEVA CONVENTION (2005) (reciting a detailed personal history of Dunant’s efforts to bring about the first Geneva Convention). 166. Id. at 54. 167. The Declaration provided in relevant part: This engagement is obligatory only upon the Contracting or Acceding Parties thereto, in case of war between two or more of themselves: it is not applicable with regard to non-Contracting Parties, or Parties who shall not have acceded to it. It will also cease to be obligatory from the moment when, in a war between Contracting or Acceding Parties, a non-Contracting Party or a non-Acceding Party shall join one of the belligerents. Id.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 31

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

25-JUN-09

7:50

395

In 1874, again on the initiative of the Russian Czar, European states convened in Brussels to draft an agreement on the laws and customs of war.168 The Brussels Conference undertook a much broader codification than its predecessor, addressing authority over occupied territory, means and methods of warfare, combatant status, and prisoners of war.169 It also incorporated the 1864 Geneva Convention by reference.170 However, the Brussels Declaration lacked support and suffered from substantive disagreements between less powerful states and Europe’s perennial military powers. Attempting a similarly broad codification of the law of war, the International Law Institute produced the 1880 Laws of War on Land.171 Perhaps mindful of state reluctance encountered at Brussels, its authors issued the Oxford Manual, intended for distribution by states to their armed forces. Like the Brussels Declaration, the Oxford Manual appears to have been merely a draft proposal rather than an authoritative or binding progression in the law of war. Unlike their immediate predecessors and successors, neither the Brussels Declaration nor the Oxford Manual addressed reciprocity in either the obligational or observational sense. The limited effect of each instrument was doubtless the product of politics, diplomacy, and timing. Yet with the exception of the omission of reciprocity, their similarity in substance to contemporaneous instruments is striking. C. Reciprocity and the Hague Tradition172 Although they were innovative in many respects, the conventions produced at the Hague Peace Conferences of 1899 and 1907 resembled their predecessors in their insistence on reciprocity as a condition of application. 1. The Origins of the Hague Conventions Still hopeful of achieving peace and limiting the effects of war through international law, as well as perhaps vindicating political and security concerns, Czar Nicholas II initiated the First Hague Peace Conference in 168. See PROJECT OF AN INTERNATIONAL DECLARATION CONCERNING THE LAWS AND CUSTOMS OF WAR (Aug. 27, 1874), available at http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf/INTRO/135?OpenDocument. 169. Id. Actually called a “project,” the Brussels Conference was not formally authorized to conclude a treaty but had hoped to produce a agreement on principles that states might endorse. See THE LAW OF WAR: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY, supra note 122, at 152. 170. Project of an International Declaration concerning the Laws and Customs of War, supra note 168. 171. Oxford Manual, supra note 102. 172. Law of war scholars have noted a bifurcation of the modern jus in bello between rules derived from the Hague Regulations of 1899 and 1907 and rules usually appearing in the various iterations of the Geneva Conventions. The former rules are typically said to be of the Hague Tradition and concern primarily regulation of the means and methods used in warfare. Rules derived from the so-called Geneva Tradition typically focus on protections for the victims of warfare, including the wounded, sick, shipwrecked, and civilians. The bifurcation has always been slightly artificial as each tradition has consistently overlapped with the other. For instance, both the Hague and Geneva Traditions address protections for prisoners of war.

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

396

unknown

Seq: 32

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

1899.173 The Conference produced highly contentious discussions on arms limitations, the use of international arbitration and mediation to avoid war, and naval operations. By comparison, the Conference’s effort at codifying regulations of land warfare proved easy.174 The U.S. delegation reported strong similarities between the proposed regulations for land warfare and the still-operative Lieber Code.175 The influence of the 1874 Brussels Declaration was clear in the Conference’s organization and agenda. Ultimately, the Conference produced the 1899 Convention with Respect to Laws and Customs of War on Land.176 The Conference placed the bulk of the Convention’s substantive provisions in an annex of regulations containing 60 articles.177 Shortly after the 1899 Conference concluded, there were calls for a second Conference.178 In 1907, the Second Peace Conference met at the Hague and produced thirteen conventions.179 Again, agreement on laws of land warfare proved relatively easy to conclude. Conference delegates seemed content to 173. One author offers competing motives for the Czar’s initiation of the Conference. James L. Tryon, The Hague Conferences, 20 YALE L. J. 470, 471 (1911). The Czar’s father, who had initiated both the St. Petersburg and Brussels Conferences is said while on his deathbed to have charged his son to promote the peace of the world. Id. An alternative, and more pragmatic motivation, may have been the Czar’s desire to mitigate the costly arms races of the period. Id. at 471–72. 174. Id. at 473. 175. Report of Captain Crozier to the Commission of the United States of America to the International Conference at the Hague, Regarding the Work of the Second Sub-committee of the Second Committee of the Conference, in 2 JAMES B. SCOTT, THE HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES OF 1899 AND 1907, at 45–46 (1909) [hereinafter RECORD HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES]. 176. 1899 Hague Convention (II) Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land with Annex of Regulations, July 29, 1899, 32 Stat. 1803, 1 Bevans 247 [hereinafter 1899 Hague Convention II]. 177. Id. 178. Tryon, supra note 173, at 478. Although President Theodore Roosevelt took the first steps to initiate the Second Conference, he left the formalities of invitation again to Czar Nicholas II of Russia. Id. 179. Convention for the Pacific Settlement of International Disputes, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2199, 1 Bevans 577 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention I]; Convention Respecting the Limitation of the Employment of Force for the Recovery of Contract Debts, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2241, 1 Bevans 607 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention II]; Convention Relative to the Opening of Hostilities, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2259, 1 Bevans 619 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention III]; Convention Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2277, 1 Bevans 631 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention IV]; Convention Respecting the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers and Persons in Case of War on Land, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2310, 1 Bevans 654 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention V]; Convention Relating to the Status of Enemy Merchant Ships at the Outbreak of Hostilities, Oct. 18, 1907, 205 Consol. T.S. 305, 3 Martens Nouveau Recueil (ser. 3) [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention VI]; Convention Relating to the Conversion of Merchant Ships into War-Ships, Oct. 18, 1907, 205 Consol. T.S. 319, 3 Martens Nouveau Recueil (ser. 3) 557 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention VII]; Convention Relative to the Laying of Automatic Submarine Contact Mines, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2332, 1 Bevans 669 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention VIII]; Convention Concerning Bombardment by Naval Forces in Time of War, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2351, 1 Bevans 681 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention IX]; Convention for the Adaption to Maritime War of the Principles of the Geneva Convention, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2371, 3 Martens Nouveau Recueil (ser. 3) 360 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention X]; Convention Relative to Certain Restrictions with Regard to the Exercise of the Right of Capture in Naval War, Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2396, 1 Bevans 711 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention XI]; Convention Relative to the Creation of an International Prize Court, Oct. 18, 1907, 205 Consol. T.S. 381; Convention Concerning the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers in Naval War, Oct. 18, 1907, 205 Consol. T.S. 395, 1 Bevans 723 [hereinafter 1907 Hague Convention XIII].

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 33

25-JUN-09

7:50

397

reproduce in large part the work of the drafting efforts at Brussels and Oxford. The Fourth Hague Convention of 1907180 reproduced, with only slight variations, the work of the 1899 Conference’s Second Convention, including the regulations contained in the appendix.181 Like its successful predecessors the Lieber Code and the St. Petersburg Declaration, the Fourth Hague Convention included an explicit reference to reciprocity. Article 2 of the Convention provided the clearest possible condition of obligational reciprocity, stating, “The provisions contained in the Regulations referred to in Article 1, as well as in the present Convention, do not apply except between Contracting powers, and then only if all the belligerents are parties to the Convention.”182 The clausula si omnes, or general participation clause, thus ensured that the Convention would operate exclusively between Treaty parties. In the plenary session that reviewed the provision, Louis Renault, a law professor attached to the French delegation to the 1899 Conference, remarked that article 2 “merely sanctions the common law in the matter of the binding effect of the Regulations.”183 He also noted the appearance of the clause in the earlier St. Petersburg Declaration.184 At a later review, Russian delegate Fyodor de Martens, who would lend his name to the Convention’s famous preamble,185 strongly defended the si omnes clause as evidence of “a ‘mutual insurance association against the abuse done of force in time of war,’ an association which states should be free to enter or not, but which must have its own by-laws obligatory upon the members among themselves.” 186 The nature of the other twelve conventions produced at the 1907 Hague Conference is consistent with the parties’ inclusion of the si omnes clause. Even the effort to extend the 1864 Geneva Convention to maritime settings, a treaty of an essentially humanitarian nature, was made subject to a si omnes clause.187 Most of the thirteen 1907 Hague Conventions reflected innovations in international law.188 Without customary status, states subjected many of the Hague Conventions to harsh conditions of obligational reciproc-

180. 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 179. 181. Tryon, supra note 173, at 481. Schindler & Toman provide a useful side-by-side printing of the 1899 and 1907 Hague Conventions. SCHINDLER & TOMAN, supra note 137, at 64–98. 182. 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 187, art. 2. Recall that the St. Petersburg Declaration included a nearly identical general participation clause. See supra text accompanying note 176. 183. RECORD OF HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES, supra note 175, at 209. 184. Id. 185. See infra text accompanying notes 201–05. 186. RECORD OF HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES, supra note 175, at 417 (emphasis in original). 187. See id. at 210. Article 18 of the Hague Convention X states, “The provisions of the present Convention do not apply except between Contracting Powers, and only if all the belligerents are parties to the Convention.” 1907 Hague Convention X, supra note 179, art. 18. States adopted Article 18 without discussion at the Plenary Conference of 1899. See id. at 210–11. 188. Report of the Swedish International Humanitarian Law Committee Stockholm 1984, reprinted in HOW DOES LAW PROTECT IN WAR? 599 (Marco Sassoli ` & Antoine Bouvier eds., 1999).

R R R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

398

unknown

Seq: 34

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

ity. In fact, First World War belligerents rejected operation of a number of these instruments because their enemies had failed to ratify them.189 2. The Status of the Conventions: Custom or Innovation? Uncertainty about whether the Conventions reflected custom when they were signed led parties to object to their application on the grounds of both obligational and observational reciprocity. The Convention’s preamble indicates an effort at innovation, stating an intention “to revise the general laws and customs of war, either with a view to defining them with greater precision or to confining them within such limits as would mitigate their severity as far as possible . . . .”190 Yet, because so many of the Regulations drew their provisions from existing sources, some authorities have concluded that they reflected preexisting custom.191 Further, the relatively widespread ratification of the Fourth Conventions and its regulations may suggest customary status.192 If the Regulations merely reflected custom, the parties’ insistence on the si omnes clause would be curious. The clause would be largely superfluous if states intended to condition duties arising under the Convention on obligational reciprocity when those same provisions were already universally applicable as a matter of custom. It is of course possible that the Convention and its Regulations matured into custom in the few years between 1907 and the First World War.193 However, there is insufficient state practice to support such a claim.194 It is more plausible that some portions of the Regulations 189. COLEMAN PHILLIPSON, INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE GREAT WAR 175 (1915) (noting German rejection of binding force of Hague Convention IX because not all belligerents ratified the Convention). Similarly, Dr. Phillipson dismissed the legal effect of British and Belgian agreement to prohibit launching explosives and projectiles from aircraft, because other major powers, including Germany, had not ratified the declaration. Id. at 176. 190. 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 179, pmbl. (emphasis added). 191. PHILLIPSON, supra note 189, at 158; W. Hays Parks, Air War and the Law of War, 32 AIR FORCE L. REV. 1, 14 (1990) (citing 1 J. SCOTT, THE HAGUE PEACE CONFERENCES OF 1899 AND 1907, at 537 (1939) for the proposition that Articles 25 and 27 of the Hague Regulations reflected custom at the time of drafting) [hereinafter Parks, Air War]. 192. A contemporary source noted that “44 of the 47 states now commonly recognized as belonging to the family of civilized nations” met at the Second Conference. Tryon, supra note 173, at 478. Fortyone states signed the Hague Convention IV. See DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 84–85. By 1914, twenty-seven states had ratified the Convention. Id. 193. Ian Brownlie notes that no formal duration of practice is required for the formation of custom. BROWNLIE, supra note 88, at 5. It seems that a notable intensity of practice might compensate for a short duration. 194. Although Article 1 of the Convention required parties to issue instructions to their armed forces in conformity with the Regulations, few states complied. Hersch Lauterpacht offers a survey of the Regulations’ status under the municipal law of a number of states between the world wars. Hersch Lauterpacht, The Law of Nations and Punishment of War Crimes, 21 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 58, 64 (1944) [hereinafter Lauterpacht, War Crimes]. Lauterpacht relates the interesting story of a German Major charged with preparing a 1901 Army Manual entitled “Customs of War on Land.” Id. at 64 n.1. The Manual contained no reference to the Hague Regulations. Id. When questioned on the omission by a Reichstag Commission on War Crimes, the Major replied that he “had no detailed knowledge of the ¨ IM WELTKRIEG 27). Hague Regulations at the time.” Id. (citing 1 VOLKERRECHT

R R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 35

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

399

reflected custom, whereas others had not garnered sufficient state practice and acceptance to attain customary status prior to or during the War. The Hague Regulations had a mixed record in the First World War. States applied the Regulations inconsistently, often claiming that other parties failed to respect both obligational and observational reciprocity. For instance, German newspapers cited the si omnes clause to justify Germany’s non-application of the Hague Regulations.195 German authorities invoked negative reciprocity in response to allegations of atrocities in Belgium and France.196 French authorities claimed that Germany’s breach had terminated application of the Hague Regulations to their mutual relations.197 Assessing the Regulations’ bombardment provisions, Geoffrey Best argues that the Hague Regulations may have been far more effective as opportunities for states to vilify their enemies rather than as limits on states’ conduct in war.198 Best maintains that citations to the Hague Regulations often merely showcased how the enemy had treacherously reneged on its very recent legal commitments.199 W. Hays Parks, a U.S. Department of Defense expert on the law of war, notes that the reciprocal nature of Hague protections for civilians marginalizes targeting restraints.200 Whether or not the Hague Regulations reflected custom at the time they were signed, the Fourth Hague Convention acknowledged the role of custom as a fixture in law of war treaties. The Martens Clause appears in the Convention’s preamble, stating: Until a more complete code of the laws of war has been issued, the high contracting Parties deem it expedient to declare that, in cases not included in the Regulations adopted by them, the inhabitants and the belligerents remain under the protection and the rule of the principles of the law of nations, as they result from

195. PHILLIPSON, supra note 189, at 158 (citing reports in the COLOGNE GAZETTE). Phillipson rejects the assertion that entry of non-Parties Serbia, Montenegro, and Turkey negated application of the Hague Regulations. Id. Phillipson concedes that had the Regulations been novel or concerned minor details, the “technical defence” offered by the general participation clause might have been acceptable. Id. at 158, 176. However, he maintains that the Hague Regulations codified the preexisting custom, denying effect to the general participation clause. Id. Later, Phillipson renews his argument concerning the customary status of the Hague Conventions with respect to the prohibition on bombardment of undefended places in the Article 25. Id. at 175–76. As observed earlier, Phillipson’s observation on the customary status of the Hague Conventions appears restricted to the Hague Convention IV. See supra text accompanying note 189. 196. PHILLIPSON, supra note 189, at 177. 197. RENE´ PROVOST, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS AND HUMANITARIAN LAW 172 n.73 (2000) (citing Conseil de guerre de Paris (4e), Jun. 18 1919, 46 J. DU DROIT INT’L (CLUNET) 737, 740 (1919)). 198. BEST, LAW AND WAR, supra note 127, at 47. 199. Id. at 47. 200. Parks, Air War, supra note 191, at 15. Parks notes that Article 27 of the Annexed Regulations to the Hague Conventions requires protection of hospitals, museums, and schools so long as they are not used for military purposes. Id.

R

R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

400

unknown

Seq: 36

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50 the usages established among civilized peoples, from the laws of humanity, and the dictates of public conscience.201

The Martens Clause emerged from unresolved debate over the rights of inhabitants of occupied territory to resist their occupiers.202 Small states, who would be forced to rely on “unconventional” means of resistance in case of invasion, objected to limits on rights of popular resistance proposed by more powerful states. The Martens Clause resolved the impasse over treatment of resistance fighters by referring to the common law of war and to more general norms of humane treatment. Several conclusions flow from the Clause. First, the Martens Clause concedes the incomplete nature of the Hague Regulations. The drafters were aware of the limitations their political interests placed on any agreement codifying war rules. The Clause denies that the new, positive law of war would operate in an exclusive fashion, clearly anticipating that customary norms would supplement the Hague Regulations during war. Second, the Martens Clause evidences the broad applicability of some customary norms. The Clause explicitly acknowledges the Regulations’ limits on applicability, specifically mentioning the si omnes clause.203 However, the Clause also reminds parties that failure to achieve conditions for treaty application does not give rise to lawlessness. While certainly advancing humanitarian considerations, the Martens Clause reiterates the shortcomings of custom. That the Clause arose as a compromise to intractable debate over substantive provisions of the law of war reveals the unsettled nature of the customary constraints on war.204 The Clause suggests that many constraints could only be expressed in the broadest and most general terms—as principles rather than detailed provisions. Furthermore, although identification of universally applicable customs would go a long way toward overcoming the requirement of obligational reciprocity, one wonders whether states at the time would in practice have adhered to such norms in the face of persistent objection or violation by an enemy.205

201. 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 179, pmbl.; 1899 Hague Convention II, supra note 176, pmbl. 202. See DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 9 (citing Minist`ere des Affaires Etrang`eres, Report of the Second Subcommission in the official report, Conf´erence Internationale de la Paix, La Haye, 18 Mai–29 Juillet 1899, Imprimerie Nationale, The Hague, 1899, 49–51; WILLIAM I. HULL, THE TWO HAGUE CONFERENCES AND THEIR CONTRIBUTIONS TO INTERNATIONAL LAW 215–20 (1908)). 203. The passage immediately following the Clause reads, “They declare that it is in this sense especially that Articles 1 and 2 of the Regulations adopted must be understood.” 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 179, pmbl.; 1899 Hague Convention II, supra note 176, pmbl. 204. See supra text accompanying note 202. 205. See infra discussion accompanying note 210 (discussing retaliatory attacks on civilian population centers in the Second World War).

R R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 37

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

25-JUN-09

7:50

401

3. The Hague Conventions in Practice, 1907 to 1949 State practice from the First World War through the Second World War reveals the practical limitations of the Hague Conventions. Indeed, the atrocities committed during this era cast doubt on whether the Conventions had any impact on state behavior. Failure to convene meaningful post-conflict war crimes tribunals likely retarded authoritative, neutral, or independent interpretation of the Martens Clause and the Hague Regulations generally. Although the otherwise draconian Versailles Treaty provided for the transfer and international trial of war criminals, these provisions were never enforced.206 Only a handful of German domestic trials were ever conducted.207 The Leipzig Trials, conducted by the German government against its own soldiers, did not include significant analysis of the Hague Regulations’ applicability, the state of customary laws of war, or of the legitimacy of exercising negative reciprocity.208 The inter-war period also shed little light on the status of the Hague Convention.209 Only two states acceded to the Convention between 1919 and 1939—Poland, in 1925, and Ethiopia in 1935, the latter on the eve of being invaded by Italy for the second time in less than fifty years.210 Italy had signed but had not ratified the Fourth Hague Convention. The Second Italo-Ethiopian (or Abyssinian) War involved infamous atrocities, including maltreatment of prisoners, attacks on Red Cross facilities and hospitals, and the use of poisonous gas. The states were entreated to observe the 1864 206. Treaty of Versailles arts. 228–30, June 28, 1919, 13 A.J.I.L. Supp. 151, 385, 2 Bevans 235. German international law scholars objected strongly to the Treaty’s transfer and prosecution provisions. See Lauterpacht, War Crimes, supra note 194, at 61. A German Privy Councillor, responding to a request for legal review from the German Reichstag, observed, “The Allies [have] imposed upon Germany a breach of most elementary legal principles and a forced departure from entire German legal history.” Id. ¨ IM WELTKRIEG 57). (quoting 3 VOLKERRECHT Lauterpacht also considers the interesting reciprocity-based question of whether absence of mutuality concerning prosecution of war crimes between victors and defeated powers undermines the legitimacy of the former. Lauterpacht, War Crimes, supra note 194, at 68. He concedes the apparent inequity and offers aspirations, yet little more, for a more equitable post-war system of prosecutions, including the possibility of an International Criminal Court. Id. at 68, 82. 207. See generally CLAUD MULLINS, THE LEIPZIG TRIALS (1921). 208. Id. 209. Some regard the inter-war period as a dark age of sorts for development of the law of war. See J.W. Garner, The Outlook for the Law of War and of Neutrality, in 22 TRANSACTIONS OF THE GROTIUS SOCIETY 1 (1937). Professor Garner observes of the period, “Many persons spoke of [the law of war] more or less contemptuously as the ‘so-called’ law of war. . . . University professors dropped the subject from their course, and even text writers omitted it from their books . . . .” Id. 210. Italy was not party to the Hague Conventions, and the tactics it employed in the 1935 to 1936 conflict repulsed countries around the world. “The employment of gas in Ethiopia was roundly condemned and the world recoiled with horror when reports of systematic attacks on Red Cross units by Italian aircraft began to reach Europe.” A.J. BARKER, THE CIVILIZING MISSION: A HISTORY OF THE ITALO-ETHIOPIAN WAR OF 1935–1936, at 243 (1968). Italy had ratified the 1925 Protocol for the Prohibition of the Use in War of Asphyxiating, Poisonous or other Gases, and of Bacteriological Methods of Warfare, and 750 Italians were charged with war crimes as a result of the atrocities committed in the war. M. Cherif Bassiouni, From Versailles to Rwanda in Seventy-Five Years: The Need to Establish a Permanent International Criminal Court, 10 HARV. HUM. RTS. J. 11, 30 (1997).

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

402

unknown

Seq: 38

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Geneva Convention, to which they were both parties,211 but research reveals little discussion of the Hague Regulations as having binding force as custom or as the foundation for establishing war crimes. Indeed, the law of war appears to have existed within an especially “chaotic state” during this period, prompting commentators to speculate that future war would be conducted under very uncertain rules.212 The Second World War resurrected questions about the effect of the Hague Conventions’ si omnes clause and obligational reciprocity generally. A number of parties to the conflict, including Bulgaria, Greece, Italy, and Yugoslavia, had not acceded to the Hague Conventions. However, war crimes tribunals in the post-war era, including the Nuremberg International Military Tribunal (“IMT”), rejected the clause as a defense to crimes based on violations of the Regulations.213 The IMT’s conclusions regarding the Convention and Regulations’ status as customary law essentially rendered the si omnes clause a dead letter. The IMT’s recognition of the Hague Regulations’ provisions as customary obligations ran contrary to states’ insistence that various conditions restricted their application. Accepting the IMT’s conclusions requires a fragmentation of the Convention. That is, the IMT’s assignment of customary status divorced the substantive Regulations from their clear textual conditions on application. Until the Second World War, states had not evinced any willingness to accept the Regulations’ constraints independent of formal obligational reciprocity. As late as 1994, governments resorted to the si omnes clause in their analyses of the applicability of the Hague Regulations. For instance, the German Federal Government replied to inquiries submitted by a member of its Lower House of Parliament concerning application of the Hague Regulations to the armed conflict between

211. See Bernard Bridel, Les ambulances a` croix rouge du CICR sous les gaz en Ethiopie, LE TEMPS (Aug. 13, 2003), translated and reproduced at http://www.icrc.org/Web/eng/siteeng0.nsf/iwpList96/DEB07F09BE30 F4B8C1256DB000479398> (describing ICRC reports of atrocities committed by both parties to the conflict). 212. Garner, supra note 209, at 5. 213. George H. Aldrich & Christine M. Chinkin, The Hague Peace Conferences: A Century Of Achievement And Unfinished Work, 94 AM. J. INT’L L. 90, 93 (2000) (“For example, the relevant provisions of the 1899 and 1907 Hague Conventions on the Laws and Customs of War on Land became accepted in practice so that, by 1945, the international tribunal trying Germans accused of war crimes was able to hold that Hague Convention No. IV and its annexed Regulations had become part of customary international law binding on Germany, even though the Convention as such was not applicable to the Second World War.”) (citing United States v. Von Leeb [High Command Case], in 11 TRIALS OF WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE NUREMBERG MILITARY TRIBUNAL UNDER CONTROL COUNCIL LAW NO. 10, at 462 (1950)); see also OPPENHEIM’S INTERNATIONAL LAW 234–36 (Hersch Lauterpacht ed., 7th ed. 1952). The Nuremberg Military Tribunal declared the Hague Regulations to be customary law: “The rules of land warfare expressed in the Convention undoubtedly represented an advance over existing international law at the time of their adoption. But the Convention expressly stated that it was an attempt ‘to revise the general laws and customs of war,’ which it thus recognized to be then existing, but by 1939 these rules laid down in the Convention were recognized by all civilized nations, and were regarded as being declaratory of the laws and customs of war which are referred to in Article 6(b) of the Charter.” Id. at 51 (quoting Trial of German Major War Criminals, 22:467).

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 39

25-JUN-09

7:50

403

the Government of Turkey and the PKK by noting that Turkey had not ratified the Fourth Hague Convention.214 The vitality of observational reciprocity under the Convention and Regulations during the Second World War is similarly uncertain. The scope and scale of violations of purportedly settled restraints on war were truly shocking. Widespread, indiscriminate bombing and deplorable treatment of prisoners of war on both sides of the conflict flouted the spirit of prohibitions contained in the Hague Regulations. In the first edition of his update to Oppenheim’s international law treatise after the Second World War, Hersch Lauterpacht observed that the law of war “never before in history was so widely and so ruthlessly disregarded as in the Second World War.”215 The historian Michael Howard concluded that the War marked the “beginning of the end of what we have called the Grotian era,” wherein it had been thought that “an assumption of common values . . . would govern the conduct of . . . wars, whether or not these values were codified.”216 In fact, during the war, neutral governmental pleas for restraint in the conduct of hostilities provoked reiteration of the condition of observational reciprocity from both sides of the conflict.217 State claims and reservations notwithstanding, the IMT weighed in strongly against rights of negative reciprocity, as illustrated by its rejection of the tu quoque defense.218 Charged with, inter alia, violating rules for the use of submarines against merchant shipping,219 the former German Chief of Naval Operations, Admiral Karl Donitz ¨ argued that mutual breach had sus-

214. BTDrucks 12/8458, translated in Sassoli ` & Bouvier, supra note 188, at 1384–85. Ultimately, the response determined that Common Article 3 of the 1949 Geneva Conventions set the minimum legal standards applicable to the conflict. Id. at 1385. The response noted that the parties might augment Article 3 by agreeing to undertake further legal obligations through Article 96(3) of Additional Protocol I. Id. 215. OPPENHEIM 2, supra note 99, at iii. 216. Michael Howard, Constraints on Warfare, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 7–8. 217. See Tami Davis Biddle, Air Power, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 151. Biddle notes that “[r]esponding in 1939 to a plea by President Roosevelt, Germany, England, and France agreed to limit bombing to strictly military objectives at the outset of the war. But all three powers reserved the right to take appropriate action in the event that their enemies reneged.” Id. 218. Tu quoque, translated as “you also,” offers a defense in situations of mutual breach. Sienho Yee, The Tu Quoque Argument as a Defence to International Crimes, Prosecution or Punishment, 3 CHINESE J. INT’L L. 87, 87 (2004). Albin Eser describes tu quoque as an argument allowing “the commission of an international crime simply because of the fact that the adversary is behaving in the same (reprehensible) way.” Albin Eser, Defences in War Crimes Trials, in WAR CRIMES IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 251, 269 (Yoram Dinstein ed., 1996); see also Brad R. Roth, Just Short of Torture: Abusive Treatment and the Limits of International Criminal Justice, 6 J. INT’L CRIM. JUST. 215, 232 (2008) (detailing the implications of tu quoque as a defense to international criminal behavior). 219. See Proc`es-Verbal Relating to the Rules of Submarine Warfare Set Forth in Part IV of the Treaty of London of 22 April 1930, Nov. 6, 1936, 173 L.N.T.S. 353, reprinted in SCHINDLER & TOMAN, supra note 137, at 1145. The charges against Donitz ¨ are available in the trial records of the Nuremberg International Military Tribunals. See 22 TRIAL OF THE MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL 557 (1949).

R

R R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

404

unknown

Seq: 40

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

¨ defense offered responses to an interrogatory pended the rules.220 Donitz’s from U.S. Fleet Admiral Chester Nimitz, who confirmed that U.S. submarine forces had also disregarded the submarine rules in the Pacific theater.221 The IMT rejected Donitz’s ¨ defense, concluding that, despite mutual breach, the rules remained in effect. Although the IMT convicted Donitz, ¨ it denied taking account of the submarine violations during sentencing.222 As with obligational reciprocity, the IMT proved willing to read conditions of observational reciprocity out of the law of war in the face of compelling evidence of state practice to the contrary.223 The IMT Prosecutor, however, declined to prepare indictments based on the targeting provisions of the 1907 Hague Regulations. Telford Taylor, the Chief Counsel for the IMT, related after the trial: Many of the provisions of the Hague Conventions regarding unlawful means of combat . . . were antiquarian. Others had been observed only partially during the First World War and almost completely disregarded during the Second World War . . . . The indictment of the first Nuremberg trial, accordingly, contained 220. See 17 TRIAL OF THE MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL 378–81 (1949); see also 40 TRIAL OF THE MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL 108–11. 221. 13 TRIAL OF THE MAJOR WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE INTERNATIONAL MILITARY TRIBUNAL 347. 222. 22 Nuremberg IMT, supra note 219, at 559. The Tribunal sentenced Admiral Donitz ¨ to ten years’ imprisonment. Id. at 588. For his part, Donitz ¨ expressed no regret over his conduct of the submarine campaign. In his final statement to the Tribunal, Donitz ¨ stated, “I consider this form of warfare justified and have acted according to my conscience. I would have to do exactly the same all over again.” Id. at 390. 223. War crimes trials conducted by national military tribunals mirrored some conclusions of the Nuremberg International Military Tribunal. See United States v.Von Leeb, in 12 TRIALS OF WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE NUREMBERG MILITARY TRIBUNALS UNDER CONTROL COUNCIL LAW 532–33 (1951) [hereinafter The High Command Trial]; United States v. Ernst von Weizsaecker, in 14 TRIALS OF WAR CRIMINALS BEFORE THE NUREMBERG MILITARY TRIBUNALS UNDER CONTROL COUNCIL LAW 323 (1951) [hereinafter The Ministries Case]. In the High Command Trial, Field Marshal von Leeb’s final statement recounted a failure of reciprocal observance of the law of war on the Eastern Front. Von Leeb stated: In the East the grim aspect of the war was determined by Russia. Stalin’s appeal for the slaughter of all Germans induced the partisans to pervert the conduct of the war. We, as German soldiers, had up to that moment refrained from such conduct, and we had not desired and sought such extremes; neither in Russia nor in other theaters. We were forced to seek effective protection against this degeneration in warfare. We acted in self-defense. The High Command Trial, supra at 459–60. In The Ministries Case, the Nuremberg International Military Tribunal addressed charges stemming from the murder upon recapture of fifty escaped British Prisoners of War from Stalag Luft III, an event dramatized in the Steve McQueen film The Great Escape and a number of memoirs. See generally WILLIAM ASH, UNDER THE WIRE (2005); PAUL BRICKHILL, THE GREAT ESCAPE (1950); ALAN BURGESS, THE LONGEST TUNNEL (1991); ALBERT P. CLARK, 33 MONTHS AS A POW IN STALAG LUFT III (2005). The Nuremberg International Military Tribunal noted a German Foreign Office response to Swiss inquiries on behalf of the British prisoners wherein the German Foreign Office asserted that because of its bombing of the German civilian population the British “must be denied the moral right to take a stand in the matter of the escapees or to raise complaints against others.” The Ministries Case, supra at 456–57. The Nuremberg International Military Tribunal dismissed the defendants’ assertion of suspension of the Geneva Conventions or the Hague Regulations. Id. at 461.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 41

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

405

no charges against the defendants arising out of their conduct of the war in the air.224 States continued the work of the Hague tradition at a number of treaty conferences throughout the interwar years.225 The 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol illustrates prevailing state views on reciprocity and issues associated with the Hague Tradition.226 The Protocol opens with an aspirational preamble urging universal acceptance and practice of its ban on the use of asphyxiating gases.227 The goal of universal observance seemed reasonable given that the Protocol built off the work of the First Hague Conference’s Declaration II, which prohibited the use of projectiles to deploy “deleterious gases.”228 The fact that Declaration II was thought to have merely codified preexisting custom against the use of poison and treacherous weapons may also have bolstered optimism about widespread observance.229 Putative customary status notwithstanding, states’ delegates to the drafting convention attempted to condition treaty obligations on reciprocity by inserting a si omnes clause.230 While other delegates fended off the inclusion of reciprocity in the treaty text, major powers ratified the Protocol only with reservations to that effect. For instance, the Government of France submitted the following reservations: The said Protocol is only binding on the Government of the French Republic as regards States which have signed or ratified it or which may accede to it. The said Protocol shall ipso facto cease to be binding on the Government of the French Republic in regard to any enemy State

224. See Parks, supra note 191, at 37–38 (quoting TELFORD TAYLOR, FINAL REPORT TO THE SECREARMY ON THE NUERENBERG WAR CRIMES TRIALS UNDER CONTROL COUNCIL LAW NO. 10, at 65 (1949)). 225. See, e.g., Treaty for the Limitation and Reduction of Naval Armaments, Dec. 31, 1930, 112 L.N.T.S. 65; Commision of Jurists to Consider and Report upon the Revision of the Rulse of Warfare, Rules of Aerial Warfare, opened for signature Feb. 26 1923, 32 A.J.I.L. Supp. 1, 12, 34. 226. Geneva Protocol for the Prohibition on the Use in War of Asphyxiating Poisonous or Other Gases, and of Bacteriological Methods in Warfare, June 17, 1925, 26 U.S.T. 571, T.I.A.S. No. 8061, 94 L.N.T.S. 65 [hereinafter 1925 Gas Protocol]. The 1925 Gas Protocol remains in force and has 135 states parties. See International Committee of the Red Cross, State Parties to the Following International Humanitarian Law and Other Related Treaties as of 6-MAR-2009, http://www.icrc.org/IHL.nsf/(SPF)/ party_main_treaties/$File/IHL_and_other_related_Treaties.pdf (last visited Mar. 13, 2009). However, the 1925 Gas Protocol has been supplemented and amended by the 1993 Chemical Weapons Convention. See Convention on the Prohibition of the Development, Production, Stockpiling and Use of Chemical Weapons and on their Destruction, Jan. 13, 1993, 1974 U.N.T.S. 45, S. Treaty Doc. No. 103–21 [hereinafter CWC]. 227. 1925 Gas Protocol, supra note 226, pmbl. 228. Hague Convention IV, Declaration II Concerning the Prohibition of the Use of Projectiles Diffusing Asphyxiating Gases, July 29, 1899, 187 Consol. T.S. 453, 26 Martens Nouveau Recueil (ser. 2) 998, reprinted in DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 60–61. 229. See DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 59, 155. 230. Proceedings of the Conference for the Supervision of the International Trade in Arms and Ammunition and in Implements of War, League of Nations Doc. A13.1925.IX (1925).

R

TARY OF THE

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

406

unknown

Seq: 42

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50 whose armed forces or whose Allies fail to respect the prohibitions laid down in the Protocol.231

The Soviet Union, Czechoslovakia, Great Britain, and the Netherlands replicated France’s reservations.232 Germany similarly declared that it would observe the 1925 Protocol subject to reciprocity.233 The reservations managed to address both obligational and observational reciprocity. In the first clause of the reservation, states parties to the Gas Protocol resurrected the reciprocity-based conditions that appeared in the Hague Regulations’ si omnes clause.234 In the second, they reserved the right to exercise negative reciprocity in response to the use of chemical weapons. Again, the states’ reservations are curious considering that the prohibition on the use of asphyxiating gases was thought to be a customary norm. The most likely explanation is that the form and content of whatever customary rule existed did not, in the opinion of states, match the Protocol in scope or content. Additionally, the 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol reservations may indicate that such customary norms were also subject to conditions of at least observational reciprocity.235 More generally, however, the Protocol’s reservations evince that states regarded customary norms as fully subject to both obligational and observational reciprocity. Law of war historian Geoffrey Best has characterized most inter-war legal developments as window dressing.236 In these fledgling efforts to forge international agreements on the law of war, obligational reciprocity cabined the limits on the conduct of hostilities. Although judicial bodies rejected defendants’ arguments that legal norms were suspended under negative reciprocity, states were unwilling to codify limits on negative reciprocity, pre231. See DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 165 (emphasis added). 232. Reservations withdrawn in later years. See infra discussion accompanying note 234. The United States did not ratify the 1925 Gas Protocol until 1975. Though transmitted to the U.S. Senate for advice and consent in 1926, Senator William Borah, Chairman of the Foreign Relations Committee unexpectedly withheld the Protocol from a vote. R.R. Baxter & Thomas Buergenthal, Legal Aspects of the Geneva Protocol of 1925, 64 AM. J. INT’L L. 853, 855 n.11 (1970). In 1947, President Truman withdrew the treaty from consideration. Id. 233. DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 156. 234. By the mid 1990s, many states, including France, withdrew their reciprocity-based reservations to the 1925 Gas Protocol. For a complete catalog of reservations and withdrawals to the 1925 Gas Protocol, see DOCUMENTS ON THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 136, at 164–67. The CWC supplements the 1925 Protocol’s regulation of the use of gas. The CWC includes no readily apparent conditions on application; for instance, the treaty makes no distinction between international and non-international armed conflict. Parties to the CWC pledge in Article 1 “never under any circumstances” to develop, use, prepare to use or encourage others to use chemical weapons.” Id. art. 1. Furthermore, Article 22 of the CWC prohibits reservations to the treaty’s main body. Id. art. 22. Yet, the treaty’s withdrawal provisions include what might be characterized as a nod to conditions of reciprocal observance under extreme conditions. Article 16 permits a state to withdraw with ninety days notice in the case of “extraordinary events it regards as having jeopardized its supreme interests.” Id. art. 16. 235. See supra discussion accompanying note 231. Japan, though it never ratified the treaty, was prosecuted for using gas against China. 236. BEST, supra note 127, at 46, 59. Best questions even his own earlier work’s conclusions regarding the practical influence of the Hague Regulations. Id. at 46.

R R

R

R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 43

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

25-JUN-09

7:50

407

ferring to leave the doctrine to treaty reservations and the general customs of treaty law. Indeed, there are few state commitments to unreciprocated observance of the law of war from that period. D. The 1949 Geneva Conventions The 1949 Geneva Conventions237 represented one of the most significant legal advances for humanitarian protections during war. Universally ratified and almost universally recognized, they have become synonymous with the law of war in the popular understanding. Although they continued the preexisting Geneva Tradition of regulating the law of war,238 the 1949 Conventions were nothing less than revolutionary. First, although they built on previous Geneva guarantees of protection for recognized classes of war victims (the wounded and sick, the shipwrecked, and prisoners of war), the 1949 Conventions originated a system of enforcement that none of their predecessors, including treaties of the Hague Tradition, had managed.239 Second, the 1949 Conventions explicitly addressed the treatment of victims of armed conflict beyond the limited context of war between sovereigns.240 Finally, in recognition of their horrendous suffering in the Second World War, the 1949 Conventions added civilians to the Geneva Tradition’s classes of protected persons.241 The Geneva revolution was not entirely successful. Although states proved willing to expand protections and strengthen enforcement regimes, the Conventions were almost as conditional as previous instruments of the Geneva Tradition. Evidence of these conditions was subtle and often veiled. To be sure, the 1949 Conventions did not include a si omnes clause. The Conventions explicitly rejected non-parties’ entry into conflicts between states parties as a basis for withholding application of the Conventions among parties.242 However, restrictions on the types of conflict to which 237. 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155; Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155. 238. See sources cited supra note 172 (describing the Geneva and Hague Traditions as well as the limits of these characterizations). 239. The Conventions are to be enforced primarily through a system identifying grave breaches: each of the four Geneva Conventions includes two articles describing offenses punishable as grave breaches and delineating a system of universal and compulsory jurisdiction for states parties. See, e.g., 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, arts. 146, 147. 240. See 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 3. 241. The Fourth Geneva Convention’s provisions in Part II offer broad protections for civilians. See 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, Part II. The Fourth Convention’s Article 4 protects the nationals of parties who are in the enemies’ hands. Id. art. 4. Each of the Conventions protects civilians in non-international armed conflict through Common Article 3. See, e.g., 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 3. 242. See, e.g., 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 2(3); 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 2(3); 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 2(3); 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 2(3).

R R R

R R R R R R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

408

unknown

Seq: 44

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

most of the Conventions applied and restrictions on the persons to whom the Conventions gave their most elaborate protection qualified their coverage in a manner similar to traditional reciprocity provisions. A number of common misconceptions and exaggerations have grown around the Conventions.243 The gravest of these misconceptions may be that the Geneva Conventions apply in their entirety to all cases of hostilities. States’ rejection of this notion at the diplomatic convention could not have been clearer. Since promulgating the 1864 Geneva Convention, the International Committee of the Red Cross (“ICRC”) has been the de facto convening authority for diplomatic conferences to revise instruments of the Geneva Tradition. As at earlier conferences, the ICRC submitted a draft convention to the states assembled in 1949.244 The most ambitious passage of the draft would have applied the Conventions to all conflicts. Article 2 of the Stockholm Draft would have made the Conventions applicable in their entirety not only to armed conflict and belligerent occupation between states parties, but also to “armed conflict not of an international character which may occur in the territory of one or more of the High Contracting Parties.”245 Perhaps as an enticement to adopt this radical alteration of the scope of the law of war, the draft included an explicit and remarkable guarantee of negative reciprocity. Draft Article 2, Section 4 read: “[E]ach of the Parties to the conflict shall be bound to implement the provisions of the present Convention, subject to the adverse party likewise acting in obedience thereto.”246 The clause would have done for observational reciprocity what the si omnes 243. One of the most common misconceptions is that the Geneva Conventions still constitute a single convention. Strictly speaking, the term “the Geneva Convention” accurately describes only the 1864 Geneva Convention. Each incarnation from the Geneva Tradition since 1864 has either supplemented that Convention or taken the form of multiple Conventions emanating from the same Diplomatic Conference. 244. The draft convention submitted to states’ representatives in Geneva in 1949 was known to the Conference as the Stockholm Draft. The Stockholm Draft emerged from work on an earlier draft submitted to states at the 1948 17th International Red Cross Conference in Stockholm, Sweden. COMMENTARY, IV GENEVA CONVENTION RELATIVE TO THE PROTECTION OF CIVILIAN PERSONS IN TIME OF WAR 6–7 (Jean S. Pictet ed., 1958) [hereinafter COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVENTION IV]. 245. Draft Convention for the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War, 1949, reprinted in 1 FINAL RECORD OF THE DIPLOMATIC CONFERENCE OF GENEVA OF 1949, at 113 (William S. Hein & Co. 2004) (1950) [hereinafter 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD]. The 1949 Diplomatic Record’s use of the term “in the territory of one or more of the High Contracting Parties” is in contrast to the phrase adopted to describe the geographic reach of Common Article 3. Ultimately, states used the term “in the territory of one of the High Contracting Parties.” In 2002, that adopted formulation led the U.S. Department of Justice Office of Legal Counsel (“OLC”) to conclude that Common Article 3 did not apply to international conflicts with non-state actors, such as the Global War on Terror. See infra note 252 (describing in greater detail OLC’s analysis of Common Article 3). Though not cited by OLC, the change cited above from the 1949 Diplomatic Record supports OLC’s otherwise controversial conclusion. 246. 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 245. Norway objected early to the condition of reciprocity in general and as running counter to the Conventions’ ban on reprisals against prisoners of war. 2B FINAL RECORD OF THE DIPLOMATIC CONFERENCE OF GENEVA OF 1949, at 41, 44 (William S. Hein & Co. 2004) (1950) [hereinafter 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD]. Likewise, the United States objected to the condition of observational reciprocity in civil wars. See id. at 48. Italy preferred that reciprocity not be “dealt with specifically in the case of conflicts which were not dealt with of an international character.”

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 45

25-JUN-09

7:50

409

clause did for obligational reciprocity. Concessions to reciprocity notwithstanding, states rejected the proposal.247 Citing practical and legal concerns, states significantly narrowed the Draft Article’s scope of coverage in the final Convention.248 In their final version, only one of the Conventions’ nearly four hundred separate articles applies to all cases of armed conflict—Common Article 3.249 Common Article 3 is “common” only in the sense that it appears in each of the four Conventions. Called a “Convention in miniature” by one of the delegates to the 1949 Geneva Conventions Diplomatic Conference, Common Article 3 outlines a minimum level of humanitarian protections in situations of armed conflict to which other conventional protections do not apply. Though textually committed to regulating “armed conflict not of an international character,” Common Article 3 is best understood in contradistinction to armed conflicts covered by the rest of the Conventions. As the U.S. Supreme Court recently affirmed, Common Article 3 is a minimum threshold for armed conflicts and persons not qualifying for protection under the full Conventions.250 The revolutionary nature of Common Article 3 lay neither in its selfcontained format nor in the character of the protections it afforded. The Article eschews elaborate schemes of regulation, confining itself to the broadest humanitarian principles. Common Article 3 was truly novel in its focus on states’ internal affairs and its application of international law to the conduct of civil wars. Common Article 3 constrains states’ treatment of their own citizens who rebel or conduct organized hostilities251 within their own Id. at 49. The Soviet Union remained committed to the original draft, including its condition of de facto reciprocal compliance with the Conventions as a precondition to application. Id. at 50. 247. A record of states’ discussions and ultimate rejection of the draft universal application provision is available in 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 246, at 41–43. Among other conceptual concerns, the delegates noted that applying the Civilians Convention to insurgents would be problematic, because the Convention relied on the enemy’s nationality to define the protected person class. Id. at 41. The Delegation of the Soviet Union was the exception, championing the draft article’s expansion to cover non-international armed conflicts. See id. at 43. The Soviet Delegation’s apparently magnanimous and confusingly liberal approach to revising the Conventions confounded and frustrated the delegations of Western powers during the Conference. See id. at 318–20, 380, 448–55. 248. A Soviet delegate remarked on debate concerning the scope of application of the Conventions, “No other issue has given rise to such a long discussion and to such a detailed and exhaustive study as the question of the extension of the Convention to war victims of conflicts not of an international character.” Id. at 325. 249. See, e.g., 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 3. 250. Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, 548 U.S. 557, 629–31 (2006); see also ARMY JUDGE ADVOC. GEN. LEGAL CENTER AND SCH., DEP’T OF THE ARMY, LAW OF WAR HANDBOOK 149 (Keith E. Puls ed., 2004) (stating that Common Article 3 “serves as a ‘minimum yardstick of protection in all conflicts, not just internal armed conflicts’ ” (quoting Military and Paramilitary Activities (Nicar. v. U.S., 1986 I.C.J. 14, ¶ 218 (June 27)))); Prosecutor v. Tadi´c, Case No. IT-94-1-I, Decision on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction, ¶ 102 (Oct. 2, 1995) (stating that “the character of the conflict is irrelevant” in deciding whether Common Article 3 applies). 251. Jean Pictet’s Commentary to the 1949 Conventions discusses the requirement that rebel movements be organized to qualify for protection under Common Article 3. COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVEN-

R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

410

unknown

Seq: 46

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

territories.252 As in the case of the Lieber Code’s application to the American Civil War, states had previously applied humanitarian legal restraints to civil war, yet Common Article 3 is remarkable as an international legal commitment to such restraint.253 The implications of Common Article 3 for the traditional principle of reciprocity are potentially profound. As non-international armed conflicts do not entail interactions between states, the operation of Article 3 might be entirely free from conditions of mutual obligation. For example, a state party could not avoid Article 3 restrictions regarding its conduct in a civil war merely by failing to ratify the Conventions. In this sense, Common Article 3 could be a truly unilateral international norm, rather than a bilateral or multilateral obligation subject to traditional privity of commitment. Common Article 3 may further limit traditional obligational reciprocity because parties to the conflict may lack international legal character. Though a rebel force may express commitment to Article 3 and its principles, it cannot ratify the Conventions. Common Article 3 does not grant international legal personality to individuals or rebel groups.254 Rather, it binds rebel forces when ratified by their sovereign opponents.255 Thus, formal, obligational reciprocity between belligerents in a non-international armed conflict is not a precondition to the operation of Article 3. Obligational reciprocity may persist in at least one regard with respect to Common Article 3. As an international legal commitment rather than a domestically guaranteed right, Common Article 3 relies on the international legal system for enforcement.256 Although Article 3 encapsulates a number TION IV, supra note 244, at 35–36. Jean Pictet served as a delegate of the ICRC at the 1949 Geneva Conventions Diplomatic Conference. Following the Conference and signature of the Conventions, Pictet, along with several distinguished ICRC delegates, produced the Commentaries in four volumes. See id. Although published under the auspices of the ICRC, the foreword to the Commentaries disclaims them as the personal work of Pictet and his co-authors. Id. at 1. The disclaimer notes that only participant states are qualified to render official and authentic interpretations of the Conventions. Id. Nonetheless, the Commentaries have commanded a seemingly authoritative force on interpretation of the Conventions. See Hamdan, 548 U.S. at 630–31 (referring to Pictet’s work as the “official commentaries” on the Geneva Conventions). As Pictet’s work cautions, citation to the Records of the Geneva Convention Diplomatic Conference or state commentary on the Conventions would be more appropriately deemed “official.” Id. 252. In 2002, the U.S. Department of Justice Office of Legal Counsel (“OLC’) offered to the Counsel to the President an interpretation of Common Article 3 that restricted its application to the territory of each state party. Bybee Memorandum, supra note 8. The OLC surmised that Article 3 did not apply to non-international conflicts that transcended a state’s borders but did not involve more than one state party to the Conventions. Id. Scholars increasingly refer to such conflicts as transnational armed conflicts. The U.S. Supreme Court rejected the OLC interpretation in 2006. See Hamdan, 548 U.S. at 630–31. 253. See supra discussion accompanying notes 154–72. 254. Common Article 3 states, “The application of the preceding provisions shall not affect the legal status of the Parties to the conflict.” 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 3; see also 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 3; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 3. 255. COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVENTION IV, supra note 244, at 37. 256. See supra discussion accompanying notes 249–55 (analyzing Common Article 3 strictly as a positive legal provision). Most (if not all) of the substantive provisions of Common Article 3 reflect customary international law. See H.P. Gesser, A Measure of Humanity in Internal Disturbances and Tension: Proposal for a Code of Conduct, 262 INT’L REV. OF THE RED CROSS 44 (1988). Enforcement of such provisions as

R

R

R R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 47

25-JUN-09

7:50

411

of principles and norms expressed in both international human rights law and domestic law, it lacks the individual complaint and enforcement provisions emblematic of the domestic legal regimes. Common Article 3 thus remains subject to inter-state means of enforcement: politics, diplomacy, international courts, and the use of force. A state engaged in a non-international armed conflict could, in theory, refuse to entertain complaints from states not reciprocally committed to the Conventions as states parties. Under such an understanding, only states that had ratified the 1949 Conventions would have standing to enforce Common Article 3 through the international legal system.257 Common Article 3 maintains an element of observational reciprocity as well. The question of what constitutes an “armed conflict” for purposes of Article 3 arose repeatedly at the Diplomatic Conference.258 States were adamant that Article 3 could not cover every conceivable act of violence committed within their territories, but rather would be restricted to cases of insurgency.259 Although they did not incorporate such provisions into the text of the Article,260 states enumerated criteria to identify conditions under which the Article would apply and to distinguish rebels and insurrectionists from mere bandits and rioters.261 Among the distinguishing characteristics of an insurgency triggering application of Common Article 3 is that the movement is “prepared to observe the ordinary laws of war” or “agrees to be bound by the provisions of the Convention.”262 Although the condition of de facto reciprocity that had appeared in earlier iterations was dropped from the final version of Common Article 3,263 states created implicit criteria for qualifying insurgencies to retain reciprocity in practice. Thus even while states consented to a revolutionary expansion of the reach of international law into their internal affairs, they included a veiled requirement of observational reciprocity.

customary law would operate quite differently and only under conditions of reciprocity identified earlier in the section on reciprocity and customary international law. See supra discussion accompanying notes 71–102. 257. The example is purely theoretical as currently every state has ratified the 1949 Geneva Conventions. See States Party to the Main Treaties, International Committee of the Red Cross, http://www.icrc. org/eng (search for “IHL and other treaties” then follow the first link to the PDF) (last visited Mar. 7, 2009). 258. COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVENTION IV, supra note 244, at 35. 259. Id. at 31. 260. A draft of what would become Common Article 3 enumerated criteria of insurgencies that would obligate a state party to apply Common Article 3. See 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 246, at 46–47. Among the criteria was one requiring that the organization “declares itself bound by the present Convention, and . . . by the laws and customs of war (and that it complies with the above conditions in actual fact).” Id. at 47 (parenthetical in original). 261. At signature, citing concern for the ambiguity of the phrase “conflict not of an international character” and the parties to which the provision would apply, Portugal submitted a reservation to Common Article 3. See 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 245, at 351. 262. COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVENTION IV, supra note 244, at 36. 263. See 1949 Diplomatic Record, supra note 261 (noting explicit reciprocity clause in working draft).

R

R R

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

412

unknown

Seq: 48

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

Article 1 directly addressed states parties’ exercise of negative reciprocity. It states simply, “The High Contracting Parties undertake to respect and to ensure respect for the present Convention in all circumstances.” 264 Jean Pictet’s Commentaries to the Conventions point to Common Article 1 as evidence that the Conventions are not engagements “concluded on the basis of reciprocity.”265 Pictet’s Commentaries conceive the Conventions as a binding testimonial, “a series of unilateral engagements solemnly contracted before the world . . . .”266 Compared to other provisions common to the four Conventions, Article 1 received scant attention from the drafting committees.267 A member of the joint discussion committee suggested a narrower meaning than that given by Pictet’s Commentary.268 The Norwegian delegation believed “that the object of this Article was to ensure respect of the Conventions by the population as a whole.”269 That is, states should ensure not only that their armed forces were trained under the Conventions, but that their populations were as well. Claude Pilloud, a delegate of the ICRC who later assisted in the preparation of Pictet’s Commentaries, responded that Article 1 was included in the Stockholm Draft to remind states not only to apply the Conventions themselves but also to see that the “humanitarian principles of the Conventions were universally applied.”270 Neither comment suggests that the Conventions apply either universally or unconditionally. When notions of reciprocity were so thoroughly debated in the context of other Articles,271 states would not have simply waved through Article 1 with the understanding that it would spell the end of reciprocity. Along with the thin record of state commentary on Article 1 generally, these comments suggest a more modest meaning for Article 1 than that offered by Pictet.

264. 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 1 (emphasis added); see also 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 1; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 1; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 1. Article 1 carried over in the preparation of the Stockholm Draft from the 1929 Prisoner of War Convention’s Article 83 and the 1929 Wounded and Sick Convention’s Article 25. Only the phrase “in the name of their peoples” was removed. See 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 246, at 26. 265. COMMENTARY GENEVA CONVENTION IV, supra note 244, at 15. Kalshoven and Zegveld also assert that Article 1 precludes the operation of negative reciprocity under the 1949 Geneva Conventions. KALSHOVEN & ZEGVELD, supra note 55, at 75. They state, “For the 1949 Geneva Conventions the operation of this crude principle is excluded by the provision in common Article 1 [sic] that the contracting states are bound to respect the Conventions ‘in all circumstances.’ ” Id. Kalshoven and Zegveld concede that negative reciprocity may persist as a legitimate state sanction in the Hague Tradition, including bans on the use of certain weapons. Id. However, they limit this observation on reciprocity and means and methods rules to pre-1977 Protocol provisions. Id. 266. COMMENTARY, GENEVA CONVENTION IV, supra note 244, at 25. 267. See 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 246, at 27. 268. Id. at 53. 269. Id. 270. Id. (emphasis added). 271. See supra notes 253–61 (noting discussion of reciprocity as a condition to applying what would become Common Article 3 to non-international armed conflicts).

R R R

R R R

R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 49

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

413

A full appreciation of Article 1 and reciprocity under the 1949 Conventions requires examination of the Conventions’ inner workings. Scholars and writers have begun to appreciate that the Conventions’ conditions on applicability with respect to situations and persons operate in much the same way as the traditional principle of reciprocity.272 Common Article 2 is the provision most responsible for guaranteeing obligational reciprocity within the Conventions. Article 2 interacts with the principle of obligational reciprocity in two ways. The opening clause of Article 2 limits states’ obligations to co-parties to the Conventions, stating in relevant part, “[T]he present Convention shall apply to cases of declared war or any other armed conflict which may arise between two or more of the High Contracting Parties . . . .”273 It is hard to imagine a clearer statement of intent to limit the operation of the Conventions to conflicts between sovereign, peer competitors. For a significant portion of the Conventions’ history, war between a state party and non-party state remained possible and in at least one case occurred.274 In such a situation, the Conventions would not have operated in a formal, de jure sense. Article 2 insulated states parties from de jure operation of the Conventions in armed conflicts with non-state actors. The final clause of Common Article 2 also addresses obligational reciprocity, stating: Although one of the Powers in conflict may not be a party to the present Convention, the Powers who are parties thereto shall remain bound by it in their mutual relations. They shall furthermore be bound by the Convention in relation to the said Power, if the latter accepts and applies the provision thereof.275 Although it does not operate with the severity of the 1907 Hague Conventions’ si omnes clause or the reservations submitted to the 1925 Gas Protocol, 272. See PROVOST, supra note 197, at 153–56; see also INGRID DETTER, THE LAW OF WAR 411 (2d ed. 2000) (noting a degree of reciprocity in the 1977 Protocols to the Geneva Conventions); Derek Jinks, The Applicability of the Geneva Conventions to the “Global War on Terrorism,” 46 VA. J. INT’L L. 165, 192–93 (2004); Robert Sloane, Prologue to a Voluntarist War Convention, 106 MICH. L. REV. 480 (2008). 273. 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 2. 274. By 1955, only forty-five states had ratified or acceded to the Geneva Conventions, but by 1960 seventy-four states had done so. By 1968, forty-four additional states joined the Conventions (bringing the total number to 118). Another spike in ratifications or accessions occurred in the early 1990s, with twenty-six countries ratifying the Conventions from 1990 to 1996 (bringing the total number to 187). See States Party to the Main Treaties, International Committee of the Red Cross, http://www.icrc.org/eng (search for “IHL and other treaties” then follow the first link to the PDF) (last visited Mar. 7, 2009). The civil war in Angola began in the 1960s and “escalated into an increasingly internationalized conflict” by 1975. Angola did not become party to the Conventions until 1984. However, different factions within Angola received military and diplomatic aid from many countries that were already parties to the Conventions, including Cuba, South Africa, and China. STOCKHOLM INT’L PEACE RESEARCH INST. (“SIPRI”), SIPRI YEARBOOK: WORLD ARMAMENTS AND DISARMAMENT 53 (1976). 275. 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 2; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 2 (emphasis added).

R

R R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

414

unknown

Seq: 50

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

the final clause of Common Article 2 confirms that obligational reciprocity is a precondition to application of the vast majority of the 1949 Geneva Conventions. Only non-parties that commit to the Conventions in a de jure sense and abide by them in a de facto sense may resort to them for protection vis-`a-vis a state party. The condition of de facto application also reflects a condition of observational reciprocity in Common Article 2. The Special Committee that adopted the text made clear that provisional application of the Conventions to non-parties would cease “when it is admitted that a nonsignatory State is not applying the Convention.”276 Once a conflict activates the full body of the Conventions through Common Article 2, reciprocity operates in the criteria required for victims of war to benefit from their protections. As their titles suggest, each of the four Conventions identifies a class of so-called “protected persons” that is the primary focus of its safeguards. The criteria for groups277 to benefit from the protections of the first three Conventions are nearly identical.278 Article 4 of the Third Convention includes at least two conditions that guarantee reciprocal acceptance and application of the law of war. The first condition requires militias, volunteer corps and resistance movements to satisfy four criteria to qualify for prisoner of war (“POW”) status. Only groups that conduct “their operations in accordance with the laws and customs of war” are accorded POW status.279 Commitment to and compliance with the law of war first appeared as a condition for irregular fighters to claim POW status in the Brussels Declaration of 1874.280 The Conventions’ law of war condition simultaneously satisfies states’ desire for observational reciprocity and provides a positive incentive for states to comply with the law of war generally. In addition to state observation of the law of war, the Geneva Conventions address individual compliance. Article 85 of the Third Convention covers POWs who had not individually complied with the law of war. The article states that “[p]risoners of war prosecuted under the laws of the Detaining Power for acts committed prior to capture shall retain, even if convicted, the benefits of the present Convention.”281 Thus, POWs who violate the law of war prior to their capture do not lose their POW status. Instead, 276. 2B 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 246, at 128. 277. I have commented elsewhere, with co-authors, on the group-level focus of the first three Conventions’ criteria for protected person status. See Geoff Corn, Eric Talbot Jensen & Sean Watts, Understanding the Distinct Function of the Combatant Status Review Tribunals: A Response to Blocher, 116 YALE L.J. POCKET PART 327 (2007), available at http://yalelawjournal.org/2007/04/11/corn_jensen_watts.html. 278. See 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 13; 1949 Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 13; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 4. 279. 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 4. 280. Project of an International Declaration concerning the Laws and Customs of War, Brussels, supra note 169, art. 9. The criterion was also present in POW qualification criteria of the Hague Regulations and the 1929 Geneva Conventions. See 1899 Hague Convention II, supra note 176, Annexed Regulations, art. 1; 1907 Hague Convention IV, supra note 179, Annexed Regulations, art. 1. 281. 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 85.

R

R R R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 51

25-JUN-09

7:50

415

the Detaining Power may prosecute POWs under the same domestic legal regime as its own armed forces.282 Article 85 denies the operation of negative reciprocity at the individual level. Denying states the opportunity to regard POW protections as inapplicable to war criminals drew strong objections from the Soviet Bloc delegations. General Slavin of the Soviet delegation remarked: “[T]hose who violated the common laws of humanity automatically forfeited their rights under the Convention,” and that “none of the provisions of the Convention should be applied to war criminals.”283 After failing to amend or remove the provision from the Convention, these states filed reservations insisting on a loose version of negative reciprocity at the individual POW level.284 The Warsaw Pact objections and reservations reflect clear insistence on observational reciprocity not only as a matter of general state practice but on an individual level as well. Under the Soviet reservations only militants’ personal observation of the Conventions guarantees their reciprocal application. The second condition of reciprocity required for groups to receive POW status is less obvious. Where the requirement to accept and apply the law of war is clearly enumerated in itemized format, the requirement that such groups claiming POW status belong to a state party is easy to miss. Under Article 4, only militias, volunteer corps, and resistance movements “belonging to a Party to the conflict” qualify for POW status. In other words, state imprimatur is a precondition to any group qualifying for POW status. Armed groups taking part in international armed conflicts must trace their authority to do so back to a state party to the Conventions. This requirement ensures that an actor with international legal personality assumes responsibility for the group’s conduct. Furthermore, the requirement limits obligational reciprocity because only states can ratify the Conventions. Even non-state actors that fastidiously satisfy each of the four itemized criteria in Article 4 do not merit Geneva POW status without state imprimatur. Like the first three Conventions, the Fourth Geneva Convention, which protects civilians, includes a provision outlining preconditions to the majority of its protections. Article 4 of the Fourth Convention is the gateway to the most extensive and elaborate protections for civilians.285 Essentially, any 282. See id. art. 102. 283. 2A FINAL RECORD OF THE DIPLOMATIC CONFERENCE OF GENEVA OF 1949, at 321 (William S. Hein & Co. 2004) (1950). 284. Their reservations operated to deny the law of war to persons who had not observed it. Thus, Hungary submitted a reservation to Article 85 stating, “prisoners of war convicted of war crimes . . . must be subject to the same treatment as criminals convicted of other crimes.” 1949 DIPLOMATIC RECORD, supra note 245, at 347. Albania, Bulgaria, Poland, Romania, Czechoslovakia, and the Soviet Union. Id. at 342–55. 285. 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 4. Article 4 reads in relevant part: Persons protected by the Convention are those who, at any given moment and in any manner whatsoever, find themselves, in case of a conflict or occupation, in the hands of a Party to the conflict or Occupying Power of which they are not nationals. Nationals of a State which is not bound by the Convention are not protected by it.

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

416

unknown

Seq: 52

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

person finding herself in the hands of her nation’s enemy qualifies as a “protected person” under the Fourth Convention.286 During international armed conflict, nationals of states parties that are either in enemy territory or find their own territory occupied by an enemy state party must be accorded protected status. The Convention leaves nationals of non-party states largely unprotected.287 Thus Article 4 sustains the condition of obligational reciprocity by denying protected person status to nationals of states not party to the Conventions. It provides further evidence that, while states were eager to rectify the humanitarian shortcomings of the preexisting law of war, they would only do so on the basis of reciprocal commitment.288 Like most international agreements and treaties, the Geneva Conventions include withdrawal provisions. Article 158 of the Fourth Convention is representative of the Conventions’ approach to withdrawal.289 Article 158 permits states to withdraw from the legal effect of ratification upon one year’s notice.290 However, denunciation does not take effect in ongoing conflicts involving the denouncing state party. Furthermore, Article 158 makes clear that withdrawal from the Conventions does not create a legal void. States exercising withdrawal under Article 158 remain subject to “the principles of the law of nations” and specifically to norms traditionally preserved by the Martens Clause.291 Not surprisingly, the Article limits the effect of denunciation to the denouncing party, preserving operation of the Conventions between remaining states parties. Commentators have cited Article 158 as evidence of a renunciation of negative reciprocity.292 While in a sense accurate, such claims overstate the effect of Article 158 and fail to appreciate how the Conventions’ conditions on application, outlined previously, operate as conditions of reciprocity. First, where Article 158 would deny legal effect to a state’s denunciation of the Conventions that was precipitated by failure of observational reciprocity during an ongoing armed conflict with the breaching state, the effect would Id.; see COMMENTARY, IV GENEVA CONVENTION, supra note 244, at 4–5 (noting the unprecedented scope and scale of protections provided by the Fourth Convention); see also Knut Dormann, ¨ The Legal Situation of Unlawful/Unprivileged Combatant, 85 INT’L REV. RED CROSS 45, 60–61 (2003) (summarizing and classifying the Fourth convention’s extensive and detailed protective regime for civilians). 286. Civilians who do not meet the nationality criteria of the Article 4 are limited to protections of Part II of the Fourth Convention. See 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 4. 287. Nationals of states not parties to the Conventions qualify only for protection under Common Article 3 and Part II of the Fourth Geneva Convention. 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, arts. 4, 13. 288. The universal ratification of the Conventions overcame this category. See supra note 274. 289. Article 158 is common to the four of the 1949 Geneva Conventions. It appears as articles 63, 62, and 142, respectively, in the first three Conventions. See Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 63; Geneva Convention II, supra note 155, art. 62; Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 142. 290. Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 158. 291. Article 158 reads in relevant part: “[Denunciations] shall in no way impair the obligations which the Parties to the conflict shall remain bound to fulfil by virtue of the principles of the law of nations, as they result from the usages established among civilized peoples, from the laws of humanity and the dictates of the public conscience.” Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 158. 292. BOUCHET-SAULNIER, supra note 7, at 137.

R

R R R R R R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 53

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

417

be merely to delay termination of the Conventions rather than to deny withdrawal entirely. Following denunciation, the Conventions would not operate in a subsequent armed conflict between the breaching and victim states. Further, the option of declining to apply the Conventions to groups of persons not meeting the Conventions’ protected person criteria would remain available to the victim state and vindicate most of the concerns that have traditionally informed the principle of reciprocity. It remains unclear whether Article 158 would entirely foreclose suspension of an individual provision of the Conventions under the traditional law of treaties. The arc of late-nineteenth and early to mid-twentieth century efforts to codify the law of war reflected a growing trend away from blunt expressions of reciprocity. States gradually abandoned formal conditions on obligational reciprocity, including the si omnes clause and reservations to its effect, and limited their resort to negative reciprocity as a means of self-help in response to failures of observational reciprocity. Yet states simultaneously preserved the function of former conditions on reciprocity through restrictive secondary rules. This preservation limits the application of the law of war to conflicts with peer competitors and groups similarly committed to honoring the customs and usages of the traditional law of war. Subsequent developments in both the law of war and the law of treaties would introduce new considerations into the debate concerning the continued vitality and propriety of the principle of reciprocity. IV. MODERN DEVELOPMENTS

OF THE

PRINCIPLE

OF

RECIPROCITY

The traditional principle of reciprocity both reflects and reinforces an international legal system dominated by sovereigns. Negative reciprocity, a measure of state self-help, follows easily from a system that sees the state as the true and perhaps exclusive beneficiary of international legal norms. As illustrated above, the law of war has historically adhered to such traditional notions of reciprocity. Even while states shed coarse conditions of reciprocal obligation and observance like the si omnes clause, they preserved the contingency of their international legal obligations by reserving application of the vast majority of the law to peer competitors. Thus, like the traditional principle of reciprocity, the established law of war has reinforced the sovereign focus of the international legal system. In the late twentieth century, academic and judicial circles questioned the vitality of that system, warranting an examination of how such developments impact reciprocity.293 The evolution in the law of treaties mentioned 293. See generally MERON, THE HUMANIZATION OF INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 71 (compiling a series of the authors’ earlier articles emphasizing individuals’ growing roles in international law); George Abi-Saab, The Specificities of Humanitarian Law, in STUDIES AND ESSAYS ON INTERNATIONAL HUMANITARIAN LAW AND RED CROSS PRINCIPLES IN HONOUR OF JEAN PICTET (Christophe Swinarski ed., 1984).

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

418

unknown

Seq: 54

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

previously294 includes a reconceptualization of the contractual nature of treaties. While conceding the synallagmatic nature of most treaties, international scholars have characterized some treaties as non-contractual. Sometimes called “law-making treaties,” these instruments are argued to evince obligations of a general or even ubiquitous nature.295 These are usually multilateral treaties, stating broad, normative rules of conduct applicable across the spectrum of states parties’ international conduct. Some commentators cite such treaties as evidence of a relative decline in the importance of sovereignty to evaluating and applying international legal rules.296 More importantly, “law-making treaties” are frequently said to regard individuals rather than states as their primary beneficiaries. As modern conflicts have proved that existing law of war instruments inadequately protect the full range of humanitarian interests in the welfare of civilians and victims of war, a less sovereign-focused outlook on protections has emerged. It is not uncommon to hear states’ obligations under the law of war referred to as “rights” that vest in individuals.297 Such reconceptions coincide with a broader recognition of transnational relationships and individuals as proper subjects of international law.298 This evolution is not only apparent from human rights instruments and scholarship but has found its way into the secondary rules governing international law, including the treatment of reciprocity by the law of treaties. A number of sources have leveraged the emerging non-sovereigntist conception of international law to reduce reciprocity’s role in the law of war. Recognizing the interaction between such emerging secondary rules and the law of war is critical to a complete understanding of the modern doctrine of reciprocity. A. The 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties299 is integral to the argument that reciprocity no longer conditions law of war obligations. The Con294. See supra discussion accompanying note 27. 295. SHAW, supra note 32, at 89–90 (citing the Genocide Convention and the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations of 1961 as examples of “law-making” treaties); see also C. Wilfred Jenks, The Conflict of Law-Making Treaties, 30 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 401 (1953); Molly C. Quinn, Life Without Parole for Juvenile Offenders: A Violation of Customary International Law, 52 ST. LOUIS U. L.J. 283, 291 (2007) (quoting Ian Brownlie, PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 6 (6th ed. 2003)). 296. Harold Koh, Why Do Nations Obey International Law?, 106 YALE L.J. 2599 (1997). 297. Aya Gruber, Who’s Afraid of Geneva Law?, 39 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 1017 (2007) (discussing the trend in U.S. Supreme Court decisions to accept the Geneva Conventions and international law as domestically binding); Jason W. Hobbes, To Boldly Go Where No Signatory Has Gone Before: How the Military Commissions Act of 2006 Has Rewritten the United States’ Obligations Under the Geneva Conventions, 26 PENN. ST. INT’L L. REV. 489 (2007) (commenting that the Military Commissions Act of 2006 shifted the United States’ interpretation of its responsibilities under the Geneva Conventions). The Conventions themselves often use the term “rights” within the text of the Articles. 1949 Geneva Convention I, supra note 155, art. 6; 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 105; 1949 Geneva Convention IV, supra note 155, art. 27. 298. Koh, supra note 296, at 2599. 299. Vienna Convention, supra note 27.

R R

R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 55

25-JUN-09

7:50

419

vention purports to regulate the most important aspects of the international treaty system.300 A number of sources, including U.S. government administrations301 and U.S. federal courts,302 regard the Vienna Convention as generally reflective of customary international law.303 However, it may be more accurate to regard the Convention as it was viewed when drafted, as a mixture of codified pre-existing practice and “progressive development” on subjects not fully realized in international law.304 The Convention codified a significant portion of the pre-existing customary law of treaties.305 Article 60 of the Convention addresses states’ exercise of negative reciprocity in response to breaches of treaty obligations.306 The Article’s provisions on suspension of treaty obligations reflected accepted customary limits and conditions on state practice with respect to negative reciprocity.307 Article 60 sustains states’ freedom to suspend performance of a broad range of positive legal obligations when confronted with breach. Despite this codifying effect, Article 60 also challenged traditional state prerogatives. In particular, paragraph 5 supports the emerging non-sovereigntist view of international legal obligations, stating, “Paragraphs 1 to 3 do not apply to provisions relating to the protection of the human person contained in treaties of a humanitarian character, in particular to provisions prohibiting any form of reprisals against persons protected by such treaties.”308 As borne out by its drafting history, paragraph 5 reads almost as an afterthought to Article 60. Whereas the first three paragraphs of Article 60 were the product of extensive debate and decades of scholarly and committee 300. See IAN SINCLAIR, THE VIENNA CONVENTION ON THE LAW OF TREATIES 5 (1973). 301. See John Norton Moore, Enhancing Compliance with International Law: A Neglected Remedy, 39 VA. J. INT’L L. 881, 891–92 (1999) (citing Letter of Submittal from Secretary of State William P. Rogers to the President, Transmitting the Vienna Convention (Oct. 18, 1971) at 1 and Written Statement by Deputy Legal Adviser Mary V. Mochary Before the Senate Foreign Relations Comm. (June 11, 1986) at 1). Each letter characterizes the majority of the Vienna Convention as reflective of the customary international law of treaties. Id. 302. Fujitsu Ltd. v. Fed. Exp. Corp., 247 F.3d 423, 433 (2d Cir. 2001). Applying the Convention, the court observed, “we rely upon the Vienna Convention here ‘as an authoritative guide to the customary international law of treaties.’ ” Id. (quoting Chubb & Son, Inc. v. Asiana Airlines, 214 F.3d 301, 309 (2d Cir. 2000)). 303. See I.C.J. Namibia Advisory Opinion, supra note 56, ¶ 94. The Court observed, “The rules laid down by the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties concerning termination of a treaty relationship on account of breach (adopted without a dissenting vote) may in many respects be considered as a codification of existing customary law on the subject.” Id.; see also Frankowska, supra note 63, at 298 (addressing U.S. courts’ treatment of the Convention as reflective of customary law). 304. SINCLAIR, supra note 300, at 11–12. The Convention’s preamble acknowledges a developmental aspect noting a “progressive development of the law of treaties achieved in the present Convention . . . .” Vienna Convention, supra note 27, pmbl. 305. See I.C.J. Namibia Advisory Opinion, supra note 56, ¶ 94. 306. See supra discussion accompanying notes 56–61. 307. Frankowska notes that although the United States has not ratified the Convention, it has resorted to Article 60 in its treaty relations with other states. Frankowska, supra note 63, at 300. In response to Vietnamese suspension of the 1973 Paris Peace Treaty on claims of the breach by the United States, the United States cited Article 60, specifically the topics covered in paragraphs 1 through 3, as reflective of custom. Id. at 300, n.85. 308. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60, ¶ 5.

R R R R R R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

420

unknown

Seq: 56

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

work,309 paragraph 5 appeared in a plenary committee session as an oral amendment offered by the Swiss delegation.310 Mohammed Gomaa characterized paragraph 5 as “an innovation of the Conference.”311 When introducing the written amendment, a Swiss delegate described the 1949 Geneva Conventions, as well as conventions on refugees, genocide, and “human rights in general,” as instruments that should not be subject to traditional notions of reciprocal suspension or termination.312 Records of discussion of the Swiss amendment are sparse.313 While several states commented on the desirability of the rule, none referred to any pre-existing custom to the same effect. Nor did the proposal replicate any provision in existing law of war treaties. Ultimately, the plenary Committee adopted the Swiss amendment by a vote of 87 votes to none, with nine abstentions.314 Despite its humble origins, the doctrinal consequences of paragraph 5 for conflict regulation are potentially enormous. Paragraph 5 might represent a major shift in both the theoretical and doctrinal underpinnings of the principle of reciprocity. On the theoretical level, paragraph 5 signifies a major coup for jurists and interests dissatisfied with the persistence of reciprocity in the law of war. It clearly characterizes humanitarian obligations as duties owed erga omnes rather than inter partes.315 From this transformation, according international legal personality to individuals under humanitarian treaties is an attractive and understandable next step. Paragraph 5 thus signifies a major shift away from the sovereigntist view of the law of war and other humanitarian legal disciplines.

309. See ROSENNE, supra note 32, at 33–34. Shabtai Rosenne attended the Vienna Convention Diplomatic Conference as a delegate for the State of Israel. Rosenne contributed to committee’s discussions on the Article 60 of the Vienna Convention. See U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, 2d Sess., 21st plen. mtg. ¶¶ 34–37, U.N. Doc A/CONF.39/11.Add.1 (May 13, 1969). 310. Mohammed M. Gomaa reports that Sir Gerald Fitzmaurice, a Special Rapporteur of the ILC, proposed to exempt human rights treaties, labor conventions, and maritime safety conventions from termination or suspension upon breach. MOHAMMED M. GOMAA, SUSPENSION OR TERMINATION OF TREATIES ON GROUNDS OF BREACH 106–07 (1996). Later, Special Rapporteurs declined to include the exemption in drafts of the ILC’s work. Id. Review of the diplomatic record of the Convention indicates that Switzerland first proposed the concept captured in paragraph 5 in a plenary meeting at the 1968 Session of the Conference. See U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, 1st Sess., 61st plen. mtg. ¶ 12, U.N. Doc A/CONF.39/11 (May 9, 1968). The Swiss renewed their proposal the next year at another plenary session. U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, 2d Sess., 21st plen. mtg. ¶ 22, U.N. Doc A/CONF.39/ 11.Add.1 (May 13, 1969). 311. GOMAA, supra note 310, at 107. 312. U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, 2d Sess., 21st plen. mtg. ¶ 21, U.N. Doc A/CONF.39/ 11.Add.1 (May 13, 1969). 313. Sir Humphrey Waldock, an unaligned expert consultant to the Conference, noted concern that paragraph 5 would conflict with many existing termination provisions contained in existing treaties. Waldock observed that the persistence of rules that had matured into custom and jus cogens would serve the same interests addressed by the Swiss delegation’s amendment. U.N. Conference on the Law of Treaties, 1st Sess., 61st plen. mtg. ¶ 76, U.N. Doc A/CONF.39/11 (May 9, 1968). 314. ROSENNE, supra note 32, at 319. 315. For an exhaustive analysis of erga omnes in the international obligations, see generally MAURIZIO RAGAZZI, THE CONCEPT OF INTERNATIONAL OBLIGATIONS ERGA OMNES (1997).

R

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 57

25-JUN-09

7:50

421

The potential doctrinal byproducts of paragraph 5 are no less significant. In its broadest interpretation, paragraph 5 would insulate the law of war entirely from the reciprocity-based remedies of the first three paragraphs of Article 60.316 A maximalist reading of paragraph 5 accords with a movement toward conflating human rights and international humanitarian law into a general and truly universal international law of humanitarian concerns.317 The extent to which human rights law and the law of war merge, coexist, overlap, or even conflict is the subject of extensive academic debate and literature.318 A complete survey of the field, much less an effective defense of a viewpoint in this debate, is well beyond the scope of this Article.319 For purposes of this Article, however, it is sufficient to note that paragraph 5 of the Vienna Convention arguably supports a viewpoint that regards human rights law and the law of war as at least equivalent in terms of their purported rejection of negative reciprocity as a means of state selfhelp.320 Paragraph 5 might be read to acknowledge no distinction between human rights law and the law of war in terms of suspension or termination of legal norms as responses to failures of obligational or observational reciprocity.

316. GOMAA, supra note 310, at 109. 317. Paragraph 5 might express a human rights-like theory of the obligation to protect victims of war—a monumental development when one considers the history of the law of war illustrated earlier. As demonstrated above, early thought on war conflated the person and state. Combatants and even civilians were conceived as extensions of the state. One of the theoretical developments in armed conflict critical to the modern law of war was Rousseau’s contention that war should not be conceived as a conflict between persons. “War then, is not a relation between man and man, but a relation between State and State, in which individuals are enemies only by accident, not as men, nor even as citizens, but as soldiers; not as members of their fatherland, but as its defenders. In short, each State can have as enemies only other States and not individual men; inasmuch as it is impossible to fix any true relation between things of different natures.” JEAN JACQUES ROUSSEAU, 1 SOCIAL CONTRACT OR PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL RIGHT, ch. 4 (Charles M. Stover trans., The New American Library 2d ed. 1974) (1762). The rights-based conception of the law of war carries this evolution further, characterizing rights that persist in the context of armed conflict and restrain states’ efforts. 318. See YORAM DINSTEIN, THE CONDUCT OF HOSTILITIES UNDER THE LAW OF INTERNATIONAL ARMED CONFLICT 20–25 (2004); see also Michael J. Dennis, Application of Human Rights Treaties Extraterritorially to Detention of Combatants and Security Internees: Fuzzy Thinking All Around?, 12 ILSA J. INT’L & COMP. L. 459 (2006); Aaron Xavier Fellmeth, Questioning Civilian Immunity, 43 TEX. INT’L L.J. 453 (2008) (detailing the interplay between the law of war and human rights law in terms of civilian casualties); Monica Hakimi, International Standards for Detaining Terrorism Suspects: Moving Beyond the Armed Conflict-Criminal Divide, 33 YALE J. INT’L L. 369 (2008) (discussing the difference between detaining an individual within the laws of war or within the peacetime laws of human rights); Francisco Forrest Martin, Establishing a Unified Use of Force Rule, 64 SASK. L. REV. 347 (2001); Dietrich Schindler, Human Rights and Humanitarian Law: Interrelationships of the Laws, 31 AM. U. L. REV. 935, 941–42 (1982); Kenneth Watkin, Controlling the Use of Force: A Role for Human Rights Norms in Contemporary Armed Conflict, 98 AM. J. INT’L. L. 1, 2–6 (2004). 319. Ren´e Provost provides the most thorough exploration of the interaction between human rights law and the law of war. See generally supra note 197. Provost offers a nuanced exploration of how the two legal systems differ, overlap, and may in some cases be reconciled, including an excellent comparison on how reciprocity may operate differently within the two disciplines. Id. 320. The Swiss delegation, in its discussion proposing paragraph 5, mentioned the Geneva Conventions and major human rights instruments all at once. See supra discussion accompanying note 310, ¶ 21.

R

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

422

unknown

Seq: 58

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

In fact, the nature of the treaty-based norm in question may limit negative reciprocity. If classic international law conceived of treaties as contracts, it regarded states as the parties in privity.321 To continue the contractual analogy, causes of action for breach accrued to states, not to individual persons whom they may incidentally have affected. However, modern human rights treaties present an exception and illustrate the growing “humanization” of international law in some circles.322 Rather than recognize states as their primary beneficiaries, human rights treaties are frequently thought to benefit individuals. While treaties predating the mid-twentieth century international human rights movement often benefitted individuals,323 such benefits were incidental and usually owing to the person’s status as de facto chattel, or at least interests, of the sovereign. Most modern human rights treaties operate differently. They elevate interactions between the state and individuals to concerns of international law. Persons may thus be said to gain a limited degree of international personality from human rights treaties.324 In this sense that human rights treaties are said to be obligations owed erga omnes as opposed to inter partes.325 Negative reciprocity loses much of its logical and legal relevance under this conception of human rights treaties. When an obligation is owed primarily to individuals, a breach occurring between State A and such individuals would not occasion suspension between State B and other, or even the same, individuals.326 The effects of any reciprocal suspension or termination of the norm in question by State B would miss their mark almost entirely. For this reason, international human right treaties are said to operate largely free from conditions of observational reciprocity and the sanction of negative reciprocity. Extrapolating human rights treaties’ conception of the legal status of individuals to the law of war is an attractive step. If the law of war protects individuals from states rather than states’ interests in individuals and military goals, the logic of negative reciprocity quickly evaporates. State A’s failure to observe the law of war with respect to nationals of State B would not warrant suspension of the relevant norms by B. The nationals of State A, having had no part in the earlier breach by their state, would continue to enjoy protection throughout the armed conflict.

321. See supra discussion accompanying notes 32–37. 322. See generally MERON, THE HUMANIZATION OF INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 71. 323. See, e.g., Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded in Armies in the Field, Aug. 22, 1864, 129 Consol. T.S. 361. 324. A number of human rights treaties included provisions for individual complaints against states parties. See, e.g., Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, opened for signature Dec. 19, 1966, 999 U.N.T.S. 302 (entered into force Mar. 23, 1976). 325. PROVOST, supra note 197, at 167. 326. Noah Feldman, Ugly Americans, in THE TORTURE DEBATE IN AMERICA 267, 275–76 (Karen Greenberg ed., 2006).

R R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 59

25-JUN-09

7:50

423

Yet textual limits within paragraph 5 of the Vienna Convention and temporal limits on application of the Convention generally caution against such a drastic reconceptualization of the law of war. First, paragraph 5’s restriction on negative reciprocity addresses only “provisions relating to the protection of the human person.”327 While the law of war has long made such efforts a priority, humanitarian provisions have not been its exclusive focus.328 The law of war includes important affirmative authority to use armed force against persons; to destroy, confiscate or requisition property; and to detain persons. Indeed, an ICRC instructor reputedly regarded the right to kill as “the first principle of the law of war.”329 A number of treaties from the Hague Tradition, including the 1925 Geneva Protocol and the 1980 Convention on Conventional Weapons and its Protocols, defy the categorical label “humanitarian treaty.” Such provisions or treaties might be outside the scope of the paragraph 5 “provisions relating to the protection of the human person” and thus still subject to traditional conditions of reciprocal obligation and observance. The Vienna Convention’s general rule of non-retroactivity may be a second limit on the effect of paragraph 5. Article 4 states, “[T]he Convention applies only to treaties which are concluded by States after the entry into force of the present Convention with regard to such States.”330 At a minimum, treaties concluded prior to January 27, 1980 would not be subject as a matter of conventional law to the reciprocity regime outlined in Article 60.331 Even today, most law of war treaties predate the Vienna Convention’s entry into force.332 The same temporal restriction holds true for a number of the human rights instruments specifically mentioned in the discussions that led to the adoption of paragraph 5. Thus Article 60, Paragraph 5 could only operate on earlier treaties such as the 1899/1907 Hague Regulations, the 1949 Geneva Conventions, and the 1977 Additional Protocols to the Geneva Conventions under a theory that its rejection of negative reciprocity reflected custom. To be more precise, at least one of two possibilities must be true for paragraph 5 to operate on the majority of major law of war treaties. First, paragraph 5 could have reflected or codified a pre-existing customary rule at the time it was drafted.333 Alter-

327. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 60, ¶ 5. 328. See DINSTEIN, supra note 318, at 1. ´ 329. FRESARD , supra note 120, at 22. Fr´esard declines to name the instructor and merely calls him or her “a pioneer among ICRC military instructors.” Id. 330. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 4. 331. The Vienna Convention entered into force on January 27, 1980, supra note 27, art. 4. 332. For instance, the 1899 Hague Conventions and its annexed Regulations entered into force on September 4, 1900. SCHINDLER & TOMAN, supra note 137, at 56. The 1907 Hague Regulations entered force on January 26, 1910. Id. The 1949 Geneva Conventions entered force on October 21, 1950. Id. at 459. The 1977 Additional Protocols I & II to the Geneva Conventions entered force on December 7, 1978. Id. at 711. 333. Article 3 of the Vienna Convention states:

R R R R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

424

unknown

Seq: 60

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

natively, paragraph 5 may have matured since its development in 1969 into a customary rule with retroactive effect on treaties of a humanitarian nature. At least one commentator has attributed customary status to paragraph 5 at the time of its drafting.334 The ICJ has also stated in dictum that paragraph 5 reflected custom.335 The International Criminal Tribunal for Yugoslavia applied paragraph 5 to the 1949 Geneva Conventions, strongly suggesting that the Tribunal attributes customary status to paragraph as well.336 A recent study of the customary law of war captures the modern position on the effect of paragraph 5 and the state of reciprocity in the law of war generally. Rule 140 of the study states, “[T]he obligation to respect and ensure respect for international humanitarian law does not depend on reciprocity.”337 Commentary on rule 140 cites paragraph 5 to support the claim that respect for treaties of a “humanitarian nature” is independent of other states’ respect for those instruments.338 Yet the customary status of paragraph 5 is dubious.339 For instance, the circumstances leading to the inclusion of paragraph 5 in the Vienna Convention do not suggest an intent to codify existing custom.340 None of the three major drafting efforts that led to the Convention explored a humanitarian exception to the reciprocity regime ultimately codified in Article 60.341 The fact that the present Convention does not apply to international agreements concluded between States and other subjects of international law or between such other subjects of international law, or to international agreements not in written form, shall not affect: (a) the legal force of such agreements; (b) the application to them of any of the rules set forth in the present Convention to which they would be subject under international law independently of the Convention; (c) the application of the Convention to the relations of States as between themselves under international agreements to which other subjects of international law are also parties. Vienna Convention, supra note 27, art. 3. Article 3(b) contemplates the operation of preexisting secondary rules on treaty interpretation and application drawn from custom. 334. Gomaa asserts that paragraph 5 reflected, at the time of its drafting, an existing rule of customary international law. GOMAA, supra note 310, at 113. 335. I.C.J. Namibia Advisory Opinion, supra note 56, ¶ 94. 336. The Tribunal stated:

R R R

Article 60(5) [of the Vienna Convention] provides that such reciprocity or in other words the principle inadimplenti non est adimplendum does not apply to provisions relating to the protection of the human person contained in treaties of a humanitarian character, in particular the provisions prohibiting any form of reprisals against persons protected by such treaties. Prosecutor v. Kupreˇski´c, Case No. IT-95-16-T, Judgment, ¶ 520 (Jan. 14, 2000). 337. 1 CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW: RULES 498 (Jean-Marie Henckaerts & Louise DoswaldBeck eds., 2005). 338. Id. at 499. 339. Elisabeth Zoller has expressed skepticism at the general applicability and reach of Article 60. She posits that attributing customary status to Article 60 “has so many distorting effects on international relations that it cannot purport to be an exact image of the international law in force.” ZOLLER, supra note 9, at 17–18. 340. See supra discussion accompanying note 311. 341. Legal historians have identified three major drafting efforts leading to the Vienna Convention. See ROSENNE, supra note 32, at 30–41; Richard D. Kearney & Robert E. Dalton, The Treaty on Treaties, 64 AM. J. INT’L L. 495, 496–502 (1970). The first was the 1925 Project 21 of the American Institute of International Law. Id. The Project produced the so-called Havana Convention on Treaties. Conventions

R R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 61

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

425

Neither the exhaustive survey of treaty law conducted by the Harvard Project nor the decades of preparatory work conducted by the International Law Commission noted an exception to general rules of negative reciprocity for humanitarian instruments or norms. Rather, the preparatory work for the Convention conveys the impression that the Swiss amendment was an innovation intended to remedy a normative oversight in existing law. The contemporaneous works of prominent commentators also fail to support the existence of a customary humanitarian law exception to the general reciprocity regime. Less than a decade prior to the Vienna Conference, Stone stated, “The premise on which retaliation in war proceeds is, indeed, that a belligerent’s duty to observe the laws of war is not absolute, but conditional on the enemy’s reciprocation.”342 Also, Schwarzenberger noted, “The laws of war constitute a typical illustration of the international law of reciprocity.”343 Just three years after the Vienna Convention was signed, he observed: [A] belligerent when confronted with large-scale breaches of the laws of war on the part of the adversary “may . . . prefer to take . . . immediate action and, by his reprisals, reverse the operation of the chief working principle behind the laws of war from positive, to negative, reciprocity.”344 Other contemporaneous developments in the law of war further clarify the extent to which paragraph 5 either reflected or had matured into custom. B. The 1977 Additional Protocols to the Geneva Conventions Commentary on and development of the law of war following the Vienna Convention was not limited to experts. After the Vienna Conference conon Public International Law Adopted by the Sixth International American Conference, Convention on Treaties, Feb. 20, 1928, reprinted in 22 AM. J. INT’L L. SUPP. 138–42 (1928). The second major effort to codify the law of treaties was the Harvard Research in International Law. ROSENNE supra note 32, at 31. The Harvard draft convention on the Law of Treaties included thirty-six articles accompanied by over 500 pages of commentary. Article 27 of the draft treaty addressed responses to treaty violations, authorizing suspension of performance in response to breach. Harvard Research in International Law, reprinted in THE HARVARD RESEARCH IN INTERNATIONAL LAW: ORIGINAL MATERIALS 662–63 (John P. Grant & J. Craig Barker eds., 2008). Article 27 proposed a system of arbitration as the primary means to address breach of treaty obligations never adopted by states. Id. Neither the draft nor commentaries suggest an exception for humanitarian provisions or treaties. Id. at 1094–95. Finally, the U.N. International Law Commission, as part of its broader effort to codify “the whole field of international law,” began in 1949 a study on the law of treaties. See ROSENNE, supra note 32, at 32 (quoting Statute of the International Law Commission, G.A. Res. 174 (II), art. 18, U.N. Doc. A/519 (Nov. 21, 1947)). The ILC’s Draft Article 57 addresses termination or suspension as a consequence of breach. Id. Draft Article 57 differs substantially only from its final version at Article 60 of the Vienna Convention in its omission of a provision comparable to paragraph 5. Id. The commentary to Draft Article 57 reflects a focus on the nature of the breach rather than the nature of the obligation breached in determining the availability of negative reciprocity. Id. at 73–75. The commentary includes no discussion of special treatment for humanitarian treaties. Id. 342. STONE, supra note 150, at 354. 343. SCHWARZENBERGER, supra note 55, at 452. 344. Id. at 453.

R

R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

426

unknown

Seq: 62

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

cluded its effort to codify the law of treaties, states set out to update and further codify the law of war. Between 1974 and 1977, states met at Geneva to conclude what became the 1977 Additional Protocols to the 1949 Geneva Conventions.345 Even today, the 1977 Additional Protocols stand out as the most significant revision and update of the law of war since the 1949 Conventions. The Protocols not only purported to reform the application of the law of war to emerging forms of conflict such as wars of national liberation346 but also worked a revolutionary merger of the jus in bello’s previously bifurcated Hague and Geneva traditions.347 One might have expected the ambitious Protocols to address explicitly or even reform the relationship between the law of war and the principle of reciprocity. Like their predecessors, the Protocols entered force prior to the Vienna Convention, insulating them from the effect of Article 60, paragraph 5 as a matter of conventional law. The drafters could have made a deliberate effort to clarify the effect of paragraph 5 before that treaty took effect. If they believed that paragraph 5 merely reflected custom, they could have excluded reciprocity from the Protocols. Alternatively, they could have included paragraph 5 by reference. Yet the Protocols neither unequivocally rejected the doctrine of negative reciprocity nor extinguished the veiled and subtle vestiges of reciprocity found in earlier twentieth century law of war instruments. To be sure, Protocol I includes some indicia of intent to limit the operation of negative reciprocity. Article 1 restates the commitment to “ensure respect for the Conventions in all circumstances” found in Article 1 of the 1949 Conventions. Echoing the Commentary to the 1949 version, the Commentary to Protocol I, Article 1 advocates a universalist understanding of the Geneva Conventions and an aversion to conditions of formal reciprocity.348 In fact, the Commentary specifically cites Article 60, paragraph 5.349 Protocol I, Article 96(3) also provides non-parties the opportunity to effec345. See generally Protocol I, supra note 33. 346. Article 1, paragraph 4 is one of the most controversial provisions of Additional Protocol I. Article 1, paragraph 4 expands coverage to conflicts between states parties and national liberation movements or organizations fighting racist regimes. Id. art. 1, ¶ 4. 347. While the 1949 Geneva Conventions supplemented previous iterations of the Geneva Tradition following the Second World War, the treaties of the Hague Tradition, including the Fourth Hague Convention and its Regulations, remained essentially unchanged from 1899 through 1977. Only the 1954 Hague Cultural Property Convention managed to codify modern rules for the conduct of hostilities and use of weapons. See Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict, May 14, 1954, 249 U.N.T.S. 215. Despite monumental changes state’s conduct of hostilities, the Hague Tradition remained essentially dormant through the mid-twentieth century. Early in the development of the draft rules that would become the 1977 Additional Protocols, the International Committee of the Red Cross undertook a codification and update of rules concerning the conduct of hostilities formerly associated with the Hague Tradition. In particular, the 1977 Additional Protocols address protection of civilians from the effects of hostilities. See Protocol I, supra note 33, arts. 51–58. 348. COMMENTARY ON THE ADDITIONAL PROTOCOLS OF 8 JUNE 1977 TO THE GENEVA CONVENTIONS OF 12 AUGUST 1949, at 32, ¶ 49 (Yves Sandoz et al. eds., 1988) [hereinafter Commentary]. The Commentary notes with respect to Article 1 that treaties of humanitarian law do not operate on the basis of reciprocity—rather they are “unilateral engagements solemnly contracted in front of the world.” Id.

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 63

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

427

tively accede to the Protocol and induce reciprocal observance from de jure parties, thereby reducing the exclusionary effects of states’ insistence on formal obligational reciprocity. Yet no Article explicitly requires non-reciprocal application of obligations. Furthermore, states parties’ and signatories’ statements do not mirror the unofficial Commentaries’ enthusiasm for paragraph 5. Some states parties have interpreted Article 96 as preserving the principle of obligational reciprocity.350 And the United Kingdom submitted with its 1998 ratification a reservation to two important provisions on protections of civilians in targeting. The UK reservation provides: The obligations of Articles 51 and 55 are accepted on the basis that any adverse party against which the United Kingdom might be engaged will itself scrupulously observe those obligations. If an adverse party makes serious and deliberate attacks, in violation of Article 51 or Article 52 against the civilian population or civilians or against civilian objects, or, in violation of Articles 53, 54 and 55, on objects or items protected by those Articles, the United Kingdom will regard itself as entitled to take measures otherwise prohibited by the Articles in question to the extent that it considers such measures necessary for the sole purpose of compelling the adverse party to cease committing violations under those Articles, but only after formal warning to the adverse party requiring cessation of the violations has been disregarded and then only after a decision taken at the highest level of government. Any measures thus taken by the United Kingdom will not be disproportionate to the violations giving rise there to and will not involve any action prohibited by the Geneva Conventions of

349. Id. ¶ 51. Paragraph 51 includes the Commentary’s strongest rejection of conditions of reciprocity, stating: The prohibition against invoking reciprocity in order to shirk the obligations of humanitarian law is absolute. This applies irrespective of the violation allegedly committed by the adversary. It does not allow the suspension of the application of the law either in part or as a whole, even if this is aimed at obtaining reparations from the adversary or a return to a respect for the law from him. (19) This was confirmed quite unambiguously in Article 60 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, which lays down under what conditions a material breach of a treaty can permit its suspension or termination; that article specifically exempts treaties of a humanitarian character. Id. 350. Report of the Swedish International Humanitarian Law Committee Stockholm, supra note 188, at 601 (observing “Sweden shall not be required to abide by more comprehensive obligation than those applying to our adversary”). The report expresses a preference for offering non-party enemies the opportunity to assent to practical observation of the Protocol by agreement. The Committee, however, reserved the right to waive full application of the Protocol where an adversary fails to reciprocate. Id. at 602. Finally, the Committee observed that provisions of the Protocol that had achieved customary status would be respected even in the absence of reciprocal observance. Id.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

428

unknown

Seq: 64

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50 1949 nor will such measures be continued after the violations have ceased.351

The Vienna Convention’s nonretroactivity provision would prevent paragraph 5 from operating on the UK and states expressing similar reservations as a matter of conventional law with respect to Protocol I. The only remaining source for a prohibition on negative reciprocity and reprisal would be custom. Though framed as a question of reprisal rather than as one of negative reciprocity, the reservation casts significant doubt on the customary status of paragraph 5 from the perspective of the United Kingdom. Nevertheless, the Protocols’ expansion of the traditional scope of application of the Geneva Conventions demonstrates an intent to diminish the operation of negative reciprocity. Two provisions in particular mitigate the Geneva Conventions’ limits on application that preserved the effects of negative reciprocity. First, the revolutionary and highly controversial Article 1, paragraph 4 extends the protections of Protocol I to armed conflict between states parties and “peoples fighting against colonial domination and alien occupation and against racist regimes . . . .”352 It thus applies a major portion of the law of war to armed conflicts with non-state actors in addition to conflicts between sovereign peer competitors. It also eschews obligational reciprocity as the test for law of war applicability in favor of determining applicability on the basis of adversaries’ causus belli. Second, in qualifying conflicts, Protocol I amends the traditional criteria for Prisoner of War protection. Through a textually complex regime, Article 44 awards POW status to all “combatants” who fall under the power of an adverse Party.353 With only one exception, individual combatants qualify for POW status notwithstanding their failure to observe the law of war.354 Under Article 44, only failure to carry arms openly in the attack, or perfidy,355 disqualifies combatants from POW status.356 The extent to which Article 44 reflects a sea change in POW status and a repeal of the vestiges of reciprocity is a matter of debate. The 1949 Conven351. Reservation letter from Christopher Hulse, Ambassador of the United Kingdom to Switzerland, to the Swiss Government (Jan. 28, 1998), available at http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf/NORM/0A9E03F0F2 EE757CC1256402003FB6D2?OpenDocument. 352. Protocol I, supra note 33, art. 1, ¶ 4. 353. Protocol I, supra note 33, art. 44. 354. Article 44 states in relevant part, “While all combatants are obliged to comply with the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict, violations of these rules shall not deprive a combatant of his right to be a combatant, or if he falls into the power of an adverse Party, of his right to be a prisoner of war.” Id. 355. Protocol I defines perfidy as “[a]cts inviting the confidence of an adversary to lead him to believe that he is entitled to, or is obliged to accord, protection under the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict, with intent to betray that confidence.” Protocol I, supra note 33, art. 37. 356. Protocol I, supra note 33, art. 44, ¶ 4. While captured fighters who failed to carry arms openly forfeit POW status, Article 44 provides that they remain protected by “protections equivalent in all respects to those accorded to prisoners of war by the Third Convention and by this Protocol.” Id. Thus, combatant immunity appears to be the only forfeited protection.

R R

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 65

25-JUN-09

7:50

429

tions had required group adherence to the law of war as a criterion for POW status, at least for militias and volunteer corps. A cursory read of Article 44 suggests that it eliminates the requirement of observational reciprocity, except with respect to perfidy. Yet Article 44 cannot be read in isolation. Many fail to appreciate that the operative term for POW status under Article 44 is “combatant,” a term defined in the preceding Article.357 Article 43 offers a two-stage definition of combatant, curiously presented in reverse order. Article 43(2) defines combatants as “armed forces of a Party to a conflict (other than medical personnel and chaplains . . .).”358 Article 43(1), defines “armed forces” to include “all organized armed forces, groups and units which are under a command responsible to [a] Party . . . . [and] subject to an internal disciplinary system which inter alia, shall enforce compliance with the rules of international law applicable in armed conflict.”359 Were the term “combatant” loosely understood to mean “persons taking part in hostilities,” the consternation over Article 44 might be justified. Allowing anyone who took up arms openly to benefit from POW status would upend the law of war’s detention regime and would call into question whether states could still demand obligational and observational reciprocity given such permissive criteria. But as Article 43 reflects, “combatant” is a term of art in Protocol I. As feared by detractors of Protocol I, individual combatants retain POW status despite their personal law of war violations.360 Article 43 preserves both obligational and observational reciprocity where it counts: at the group level. It ensures that only combatants who belong to “armed forces, groups, and units” that actually commit to, apply, and enforce the laws of war are eligible for POW status. Thus while Protocol I amended the test for POW status, states retained the critical guarantee that only groups of adversaries committed to reciprocal obligation to and observance of the law of war would benefit from the status. Protocol I’s limitations and states’ reservations to provisions even suggesting unconditional application undermine the claim that Vienna Convention Article 60, Paragraph 5 reflected or matured into customary law. The Convention’s prohibition on retroactivity thus bars applying Paragraph 5 to earlier law of war treaties. Finally, the Protocols’ efforts to reform the law applicable to non-international armed conflicts demonstrate states’ commitment to preserving reciprocity in the late twentieth century. 1977 Additional Protocol II updates and supplements the protections prescribed in Common Article 3 of the 1949 Conventions. Protocol II adds to Common Article 3, inter alia, ex357. Article 44 explicitly refers to Article 43 for the definition of the term “combatant.” Id. art. 44. 358. Id. art. 43(1). 359. Id. art. 43(2). 360. Recall that the 1949 Third Geneva Convention operates similarly through Article 85, permitting POWs to retain the benefits of the Convention even while facing prosecution for war crimes. 1949 Geneva Convention III, supra note 155, art. 85.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

430

unknown

Seq: 66

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

panded process in criminal prosecutions,361 enhanced responsibilities with respect to the wounded and sick,362 and added details to protections from the effects of hostilities.363 Yet while it expanded substantive protections, Protocol II restricted the scope of application of those protections to be consistent with the rules of international armed conflict. Article 1(1) limits application of Protocol II to conflicts between states parties and armed forces or groups “under responsible command . . . as to enable them to . . . implement this Protocol.”364 Thus only conflicts between states and groups committed and able to reciprocate observance of Protocol II trigger its protections. In this respect, some states regarded Article 1 as a step backward for the law of non-international armed conflicts.365 However, armed with an appreciation of the persistence of negative reciprocity in the law of war, one is less surprised to find states willing to reverse a trend of expanded application to preserve reciprocity. C. Political and Military Context The shared political-military context of the Vienna Convention and the Additional Protocols casts doubt on the extent to which states envisioned the actual operation of Article 60, paragraph 5, as well as its customary status. States negotiated, concluded, and widely ratified both the Vienna Convention and the Additional Protocols in an era when nuclear weapons dominated military strategy. Indeed, just as representatives to the Diplomatic Conference set out to draft the Protocols to the Geneva Conventions in 1974, U.S. nuclear strategy abandoned its emphasis on limited strikes in favor of “Assured Destruction.” In response to advances in Soviet nuclear delivery capacity, Secretary of Defense Robert McNamara committed the United States to developing the capacity to launch a second strike capable of destroying twenty to twenty-five percent of the population of the Soviet Union’s largest cities.366 Such plans were almost entirely incompatible with the Protocols’ nascent limits on targeting.367 The ICJ acknowledged as much in its equivocal 1996 advisory opinion on the legality of nuclear weapons under the law of war and 361. Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protection of Victims of Non-International Armed Conflicts (Protocol II), June 8, 1977, 1125 U.N.T.S. 609. 362. Id. Part III. 363. Id. Part IV. 364. Protocol II, supra note 361, art. 1(1). 365. Letter of Transmittal from Ronald Reagan, U.S. President, to the United States Senate and State Department, reprinted in 81 AM. J. INT’L L. 910–12 (1987) (including analysis and commentary on Protocol II). 366. See David Alan Rosenberg, Nuclear War Planning, in THE LAWS OF WAR, supra note 124, at 180 (noting U.S. shift in nuclear target planning from Soviet nuclear force or military targets to urbanindustrial centers). 367. The ICJ later took up the issue of whether nuclear weapons comply with the law of war. See Paul Kahn, Nuclear Weapons and the Rule of Law, 31 N.Y.U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 349 (1999).

R

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

Seq: 67

25-JUN-09

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

7:50

431

human rights law.368 The NATO powers reconciled their plans with the Protocols by an appeal to exceptionalism. Many NATO states insisted that nuclear weapons be regulated separately from conventional weapons.369 The assumption was that use of nuclear weapons, or a non-nuclear attack of sufficient scale to provoke self-defense using nuclear weapons, would occasion a large-scale and reciprocal suspension of much of the law of war. Cold War nuclear exceptionalism indicates states’ extraordinary commitment to conditions of reciprocity. The explicit carve-outs for nuclear exchanges are in some respects equivalent to anticipatory negative reciprocity. Although nuclear exchanges are commonly understood to constitute reprisals, they more closely resemble suspension or even termination of the entire norm in question—distinguishing characteristics of negative reciprocity. The nuclear example thus further undermines the claim that reciprocity has been eliminated as a condition of observance of the law of war.370 A dispositive determination of the customary status of paragraph 5 remains elusive. Indicia of state practice with respect to security efforts and particularly the conduct of hostilities are closely guarded. But claims that paragraph 5 reflected customary law at the time of its drafting or that it matured into custom at some later point suffer from an oversimplified understanding of reciprocity under the law of war. The developers of the law of war did not clearly address the role of reciprocity in the instruments that followed the Vienna Convention. Proponents of paragraph 5 likely overstate its conventional effects and customary status. In short, reciprocity remains an underdeveloped consideration within the discussion of how to apply and revise the law of war. With a more complete understanding of reciprocity’s persistence in the law of war, some prescriptions that may guide efforts to apply and reform the law become apparent. V. CONCLUSION: RECIPROCITY, THE LAW OF WAR, PRESCRIPTIVE CONSIDERATIONS

AND

To some extent, state practice vindicates the claim that states’ insistence on reciprocity has subsided over time. Practice has mirrored the positive law’s shift toward a more subtle doctrine of reciprocity. Despite enduring textual authority to do so, states have not frequently exercised negative reciprocity under the law of war. Invocations of the Hague Regulations’ si omnes clause are effectively extinct.371 The Geneva Conventions have rarely, if ever, 368. See id. 369. George Bunn notes that the U.S. signature of Protocol I included the understanding that the rules established by the Protocol were not intended to have any effect on and do not in fact regulate or prohibit the use of nuclear weapons. George Bunn, U.S. Law of Nuclear Weapons, NAVAL WAR C. REV. 46, 58 (1984). 370. See supra discussion accompanying notes 108–16. 371. See supra discussion accompanying note 213.

R R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

432

unknown

Seq: 68

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

been deemed inapplicable on the basis of an adversary’s failure of observational reciprocity. Yet states have regularly resorted to secondary rules within the law of war to vindicate the same concerns that informed traditional reservations or exercises of negative reciprocity. As the preceding analysis has shown, twentieth century law of war instruments lacking express conditions of reciprocal observance or obligation have included restrictive conditions on application and scope that vindicate the same concerns. States have held fast to these secondary rules as conditions on the de jure application of the law of war.372 While they have admitted that some law of war provisions apply to situations and persons who do not meet the sovereign-focused criteria of the traditional law, states have also been careful to characterize such applications as policy-based or gratuitous extensions and not de jure operations of the law. The categorical claim that reciprocity no longer conditions the operation of the law of war is greatly overstated and fails to appreciate how other secondary rules act as proxy or ersatz conditions of reciprocity. Military historian Martin van Creveld has argued that “what is and is not considered acceptable behavior in war is historically determined, neither self-evident nor unalterable.”373 The reactive nature of the law of war confirms in many respects Crevald’s analysis. It is now axiomatic that, to be effective, the law of war must account for both the operational demands of armed conflict as well as contemporary notions of humanity. Historically, allegations that the law of war is out of touch or irrelevant have indicted provisions that overly burden military operations or do not adequately accommodate states’ security needs. Such provisions have withered from disuse and even disdain.374 However, if the laws of war have been unresponsive to military necessity, they have also failed to keep pace with our evolving sense of humanity and decency.375 War rules that are out of touch with modern conceptions of humanity, justice, and human rights present as great a threat to effectiveness and the rule of law as rules that fail to adequately account for military necessity. The law of war has proved a relatively dynamic body of law, periodically evolving to balance conceptions of military necessity against maturing ex372. Professor Geoff Corn highlights three recent examples in which the United States has cited strict application provisions, including those of Common Article 2 of the 1949 Geneva Conventions, to deny the operation of the full body of the law of war. Geoff Corn, Hamdan, Lebanon, and the Regulation of Hostilities: The Need to Recognize a Hybrid Category of Armed Conflict, 40 VAND. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 295, 303–11 (2007). 373. Martin van Creveld, The Gulf Crisis and the Rules of War, 3 MIL. HIST. Q. 23, 23 (1991). 374. See The League of Nations and the Laws of War, 1 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 109 (1920–21); Scott R. Morris, The Laws of War: Rules by Warriors for Warriors, THE ARMY LAWYER 4 (Dec. 1997). Major Morris chronicles the involvement of military officers in the development of the laws and customs of war leading up to and including the 1863 Lieber Code. Morris argues that their influence ensured the relevance and effectiveness of these rules on the battlefield. Id. 375. For example, the ambiguous and permissive principle of proportionality may be ripe for reconsideration because some may consider it out-of-touch with modern sensibilities.

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

unknown

2009 / Reciprocity and the Law of War

Seq: 69

25-JUN-09

7:50

433

pectations of humanity in war. Yet the role of reciprocity remains underappreciated as a factor for consideration. As a critical element of both early and extant war conventions, reciprocity warrants deliberate scrutiny to determine whether it fulfills current military needs. As Crevald’s observation suggests, the future role for reciprocity should depend not on its pedigree but rather on whether it remains consistent with notions of modern military necessity and humanity. While law of war reformers have cited evolving standards of decency and humanity as well as the changing nature of states’ adversaries, few have gazed inward to inquire whether changes in states’ own military doctrine and operations call for humanitarian revisions of the law. Most discussions focus on how changing external threats challenge or should provoke change in the law. Thus efforts to humanize humanitarian law have leveraged increased awareness of the human costs of conflict and the tactical and strategic challenges presented by asymmetrical foes. Yet there has been little analysis of whether states’ own military concerns might provide impetus for further evaluation or humanization of the law. If vestiges of negative reciprocity persist in the law of war, they should be scrutinized to determine their relevance and compatibility with military doctrine and strategy. In a follow-on piece that leverages the framework identified by this Article, I hope to highlight such normative issues concerning the persistence of reciprocity. Recent developments in states’ military strategies and doctrine necessitate a critical examination of the propriety of reciprocity’s persistence in the law of war. Greater appreciation of the importance of public support for military operations and a revival of counter-insurgency doctrine may cast doubt on the propriety of negative reciprocity as a measure of state self-help. Counterinsurgency strategy’s emphasis on political over military considerations creates the possibility of new coincidences of interest between military doctrine and humanity.376 More importantly, counter-insurgency strategy counsels states and their armed forces to know themselves. Sir James Graham declared in 1849 that the principle of reciprocity made “the interest of others the measure of our 376. DEP’T OF THE ARMY, FIELD MANUAL 3–24, COUNTERINSURGENCY OPERATIONS 1–19 (Dec. 15, 2006). Field Manual 3–24 observes, “The primary objective of any [counterinsurgency] operation is to foster development of effective governance by a legitimate government. Counterinsurgents achieve this objective by the balanced application of both military and nonmilitary means.” Id. Of course, current counter-insurgency strategy is not the first or only observation of the alignment of interest between military necessity and humanity. For example: On May 18, 1859, at Marengo, Marshal Regnaud de Saint-Jean d’Angely addressed these words to the Imperial Guard: ‘Soldiers of the Guard, . . . you will give the army an example of fearlessness in danger, of order and discipline on the march, of dignity and restraint in the country in which you are engaged. The memory of your own families will make you considerate of the people of the country and will keep alive your respect for property, and you may be sure that victory awaits you. DUNANT, supra note 165, at 42, n.1.

R

\\server05\productn\H\HLI\50-2\HLI205.txt

434

unknown

Seq: 70

25-JUN-09

7:50

Harvard International Law Journal / Vol. 50

interest . . . it makes the folly of others the limit of our wisdom.”377 In fact, long before Graham, Sun Tzu counseled leaders to “[k]now your enemy and know yourself.”378 It may be no small irony that categorical insistence on reciprocity distracts us from accomplishing the latter. Military and political planners appear to better appreciate the relationship between why they wage military operations and how they wage them. The prominence of Rule of Law or Stability Operations in modern doctrine emphasizes a new consciousness about integrating the day-to-day conduct of operations with their desired end state.379 Such operations call on states not only to foster respect for the rule of law in developing states but also to examine their own relationship to the law.380 Thus, whether insistence on reciprocity complements or retards the execution of emerging military strategy deserves critical examination. Outing reciprocity in both the preterit and extant law of war does not address the entire spectrum of challenges facing the law. However, an understanding of the law of war that explicitly considers reciprocity may focus debate over law of war reform into a more fundamental conversation about the appropriate role of reciprocity in regulating the conduct of hostilities. The appreciation of negative reciprocity in the law of war offered by this Article provides a much-needed platform for such reform discussions.

377. 104 PARL. DEB., H.L. (3d ser.) (1849) 662. 378. SUN TZU, THE ART OF WAR 84 (Samuel B. Griffith trans., Oxford at the Clarendon Press 1963) (6th Century B.C.). 379. DEP’T OF THE ARMY, FM 3–07 STABILITY OPERATIONS 3–1 to 3–2 (Oct. 6, 2008). The FM (“Field Manual”) observes, “Essential stability tasks lay the foundation for success of the other instruments of national power. This foundation must sustain the burdens of governance, rule of law, and economic development that represent the future viability of a state.” Id. 380. See Sarah Sewall, Remarks at Rule of Law Conference at TJAGLCS (Sep. 24, 2006) (notes on file with author).