Esta investigación estudia el concepto de entendimiento en textos de Práctica ... Este trabajo intenta contribuir a llenar este vacÃo, basado en la suposición ..... MARTINS, H. (2000) Sobre a estabilidade do significado em Wittgenstein. Veredas ...
Cristiane Cerdera Understanding ‘understanding’ in Exploratory Practice Cristiane Cerdera holds a doctorate in Linguistics from the Pontifical Catholic University of Rio de Janeiro and teaches EFL in a federal school in the same city. She has worked as an English teacher in schools and universities for 20 years. Her main research interests include Exploratory Practice, ESP and themes related to Wittgenstein’s philosophy and Education. Abstract This work will present and discuss the notion of ‘understanding’ in Exploratory Practice in the light of concepts of philosophy of language. Attention will be drawn to the way the notion is used in EP articles and papers and the possible consequences to foreign language pedagogy. Paper UNDERSTANDING ‘UNDERSTANDING’ IN EXPLORATORY PRACTICE: AN ALTERNATIVE VIEW1 “We regard understanding as the essential thing, and signs as something inessential” (Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar) ABSTRACT: This research paper investigates the notion of understanding in the texts of Exploratory Practice. According to Dick Allwright, Exploratory Practice is “an approach to practitioner research that is devoted to understanding the quality of language classroom life”. Practitioners regard understanding as the most relevant notion in the theoretical rationale of Exploratory Practice. However, while reading the seminal articles devoted to the topic, it has been noticed that, despite the attempts to shift from a traditional view of understanding, Exploratory Practice does not elaborate an alternative concept to ground theoretically this new pedagogical approach. This work attempts to contribute to fill this gap, based on the assumption that there is substantial affinity between the principles of Exploratory Practice and the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein.
11
Cristiane Pereira Cerdera. Anglo-Germanic Languages Department, Colégio Pedro II/RJ.
Keywords: Exploratory Practice, understanding, Wittgenstein RESUMEN: Esta investigación estudia el concepto de entendimiento en textos de Práctica Exploratoria. De acuerdo con Dick Allwright, la práctica exploratoria es una modalidad de investigación profesional que estudia la comprensión de la calidad de vida dentro de la clase de lengua extranjera. Los profesionales consideran el entendimiento como la idea central en el aparato teórico de la Práctica Exploratoria. Sin embargo, al leer los artículos básico dedicados al tema, nos damos cuenta de que, a pesar de los intentos de renunciar a una visión tradicional del concepto, la práctica exploratoria no elabora una visión alternativa de entendimiento que pueda justificar ese abordaje pedagógico. Este trabajo intenta contribuir a llenar este vacío, basado en la suposición de que existe una afinidad sustancial entre los principios de la Práctica Exploratória y la filosofía de Ludwig Wittgenstein. Palabras clave: Práctica Exploratória, entendimiento, Wittgenstein 1. Introduction Exploratory Practice is a pedagogical perspective in which teachers and students work collaboratively in order to understand life inside and outside classrooms. For EP practitioners’ (i.e. teachers and students together) the focus of their investigation is ‘puzzling situations’, which might be anything that raises the group’s interest. This is a perspective that contrasts, for example, with Action Research, since, differently from the latter, EP does not necessarily propose solutions to ‘problems’, but offers a sustainable way to understand life within the teaching practice (Allwright & Miller, 1998). According to Allwright (2003, p.114), Exploratory Practice can be regarded as a set of principles and also as a continuous process of local and global thought. 2. Working by principles As a pedagogic investigative tool, EP assumes a constructivist perspective on the approach of the puzzles to be researched. Such a position diverges considerably from a positivist paradigm, which is guided by the idea of efficiency and problemsolving. Conversely, in Exploratory Practice, practitioners face the challenge of reconstructing the understanding of each situation, according to the general principles of this pedagogical approach. It is important to notice that those principles
should not be taken as a set of ‘ready-made’ fixed rules, but as a set of ideas derived from practical experience. Thus, the principles that have been elaborated by practitioners so far, can be summarized as follows: Principle 1: put ‘quality of life’ first. Principle 2: work primarily to understand language classroom life. Principle 3: involve everybody Principle 4: work to bring people together Principle 5: work also for mutual development Principle 6: integrate the work for understanding into classroom practice. Principle 7: make the work a continuous enterprise One of the consequences of adopting the principles of EP in classrooms is that teachers might feel encouraged to think about the role of students in acquiring their own knowledge. They might also feel encouraged to reflect upon students’ capacity of being in charge of taking decisions, enhancing their agency potential. Taking the notion of ‘agency’ as a ‘who-does-what’ issue, Allwright and Hanks (2009) state that agency can be considered a point of view through which those who most need the understandings generated in classroom (i.e. the students) should be the agents of developing those understandings. Furthermore, one must not forget that “Learners are not passive recipients of teacher talk under the sway of institutional authority but are social individuals with agency, who shape and are shaped by divergent discourses of learning.” (Tseng & Ivanič, 2006, p. 136) 3. Why Wittgenstein and Exploratory Practice? Ludwig Wittgenstein’s work is traditionally divided into two phases; in the first one, called the ‘early’ Wittgenstein, there is a more ‘essentialist’ orientation; whereas in the second, known as the ‘late’ Wittgenstein, we can see an emphasis on issues related to language meaning and on the pursuit of a ‘method’ which is, at the same time, pedagogical and therapeutic. Through this ‘method’, Wittgenstein intended to
shed light on ‘conceptual confusions’ created by our ordinary language. According to Burbules and Peters (2001), the elements in the wittgensteinian text are characteristic of a way of writing about philosophy that is more oriented to triggering a shift in thought than in demonstrating a proof; more to showing than to saying; more to pointing than to leading (note the frequent references in Wittgenstein’s later work to signposts, wandering through a city, being lost, needing a guide, finding one’s way about, and knowing how to go on). This is a conception of teaching, and teaching through writing (…) The main work of this phase, the Philosophical Investigations, is considered one of the most important contemporary philosophical works and has a strong pedagogical orientation2, an aspect that is made clear in the structure of the work itself, with its ‘aporetic’ and dialogic nature (Burbules & Peters, 2001). The philosophy of the late Wittgenstein elaborates a sharp criticism towards the traditional themes of Western philosophy and poses great emphasis on language as an essentially human institution, intertwined with our non-linguistic practices. His work also approaches traditional elements of philosophical studies in a totally new perspective, rearranging them in a way that includes The idea that language can only be understood from the perspective of language-in-use; the denial of a private inner realm of phenomena; the emphasis on the body as the objetification of the human soul; the replacing of the division between matter and mind with a division between the living and the non-living (...); the appeal to a pre-epistemic relation to other human subjects which is rooted in our immediate responsiveness to them (…) (McGinn, 1997) One of the fundamental aspects that highlight the difference between both the wittgensteinian philosophy and Exploratory Practice and more traditional philosophical and pedagogical approaches is the practice of raising and asking
2
Savickey (1998) claims that “The Philosophical Investigations is an inherently pedagogical work. Wittgenstein claims throughouthis later writings to be teaching a method and this method is both philosophical and pedagogical.According to Moore and Fann he remarked to the effect that it did not matter whether his results were true or not, what mattered was that a method had been found (…)”
questions, trying to understand them, without aiming at an answer or a change in behavior, for example. That fact might lead us to a convergence between these two perspectives, which is manifest, mainly, in the way both deal with the concept under investigation here – the notion of understanding. 4. The notion of understanding in Exploratory Practice: a dialogue with the wittgensteinian philosophy One of the central aspects of understanding Wittgenstein brings to light is that we never understand more than we are able to explain. Our common sense, possibly fed by centuries of philosophical tradition, paints a distinct scenario ‘inside’ our minds. Grounded in the belief that language has an ‘innefable’ dimension, we continuously use expressions in our daily language such as ‘It is impossible to explain’ or ‘It is beyond my words and understanding’. Nevertheless, Wittgenstein states that it is exactly the opposite: “But then doesn’t our understanding reach beyond all examples?” – A very curious expression, and a quite natural one! – But is that all? Isn’t there a deeper explanation; or at least, mustn’t the understanding of the explanation be deeper? – Well, have I myself a deeper understanding? Have I got than I give in the explanation? – But then, whence the feeling that I have more? Is it like the case where I interpret what is not limited as a length that reaches beyond every length? (Wittgenstein, PI § 209) “But do you really explain to the other person what you yourself understand? Don’t you leave to him to guess the essential thing? You give him examples – but he has to guess their drift to guess your intention” – Every explanation which I can give myself I give to him too. – “He guesses what I mean” would amount to : “various interpretations of my explanation come to his mind and he picks one of them.” So in this case he could ask; and I could and would answer him. (Wittgenstein, PI § 210) The way Exploratory Practice approaches the notion of understanding seems to be rather contradictory. On the one hand, understanding cannot be dissociated from mental change; but, on the other hand, according to practitioners, understandings are concrete and observable. We notice a convergence with the traditional mentalist view in this respect, as can be seen in the quotes below:
Our main problem seems to arise from the irony that we believe the profoundest understandings to be somehow beyond words. (…) First, the words we find may serve to conceal, rather than successfully communicate, the true extent of our understandings. Worse, having found words, we may believe we have also found understanding, and so the effort to communicate might inhibit any further effort to understand. (Allwright, 2003, p. 121) Practitioners need deep ‘human’ understandings of their immediate situation, understandings that may even be ‘too deep for words’. (Allwright & Hanks, 2009, p. 147) Such understandings are non-reductionist because they reflect our acceptance of all the complexity we live with and through every day, and ‘deep’ to the extent that we are able to make some sort of sense of that complexity. But such understandings are going to be extremely difficult, at times, impossible, to express in words. (Allwright & Hanks, 2009, p. 148)
It is particularly elucidative the words of Allwright (2009), drawing a parallel between the understandings developed in classroom interaction and the Taoism: I suggest there is a third possibility (well-recognised in Taoism) that deserves our urgent and earnest attention here – the possibility of aiming downwards (…) towards understandings that are perhaps ‘too deep for words’. This possibility recognises the potential value of trying to articulate our developing understandings. It does indeed seem typically to help people to try to work out their understandings in words, on paper (as I am doing here) or in collective discussion (my personal preference). But this new position, looking downwards, emphasises the limits of attempts to articulate understandings. Instead it draws attention to the possibility that people, throughout life, develop understandings that are much too subtle for them, or anyone else, to articulate adequately. This is especially clear, perhaps, in the experience of the many gifted teachers who are unable to say anything useful about what it is that makes them successful. They have understandings that they can, and do, live successfully, but which they cannot articulate. Developing such lived understandings can be the proper aim of practitioner research, I believe. Indeed, unless we incorporate such a position into our conception of research, we risk allowing ourselves to take seriously only those understandings that can be made fully explicit. Unfortunately, these are few and far between, and likely to be relatively trivial for all immediate practical, and practitioner,
purposes, especially when compared to the subtle understandings we can actually live. (Allwright, 2009, p. 23) Conversely, under Wittgenstein’s point of view, understanding cannot be considered a mental process, an experience, a state, event, or anything that could possibly happen in the hearer’s mind: In the sense in which there are processes (including mental processes) which are characteristic of understanding, understanding is not a mental process. (Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 154) On the contrary, the philosopher points out that understanding is an ability, an abiding condition (“Understanding a sentence means understanding a language” Wittgenstein, PI § 199), which is manifest in three different ways: The way we use language: “The application is still a criterion of understanding” (Wittgenstein, PI, § 146) The way we react when other people use language; The way we explain the meaning of a word, when people ask us to do so. Thus, understanding is a correlate of explanation, action and meaning (“meaning is the correlate of understanding and understanding the correlate of explanation” Baker & Hacker,1980, p. 30). Wittgenstein challenges the traditional view by saying that: The whole point of communication lies in this: someone else grasps the sense of my words – which is something mental: he as it were takes it into his own mind. If he then does something further with it as well, that is no part of the immediate purpose of language. (Wittgenstein, PI, § 363) According to Wittgenstein, the only criteria we have to ascribe understanding is our praxis, that is, what we do after hearing someone’s words: “he understands” would mean: “if you ask him for the rules, he will tell you them”; in the other case “if you require him to apply the rule, he will carry out your order”. (Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar, p. 84) What’s the sign of someone’s understanding a game? Must he be able to recite the rules? Isn’t also a criterion that he can play the game, i.e. that he does in fact play it, even if he’s baffled when asked for the rules? Is it only by being told the rules that the game is learnt and not simply by
watching it being played? (Wittgenstein, PG, p. 62) A convergence between the wittgensteinian notion of understanding as an abiding condition and the notion of understanding in Exploratory Practice, among other aspects, can also be noticed in EP writings. EP regards understandings as local and provisional, that is, understanding a situation in classroom is akin to understanding life. Therefore, a criterion to ascribe understanding in classroom is continuity, which makes the act of understanding a never ending enterprise: Continuity is important because understandings are never fixed and final. Any work for understanding must therefore be a continuous enterprise. (Allwright, 2009, p. 27) If the work for understanding is fully integrated it then becomes possible to think of it as something that can be continuous – a normal part of classroom practice. And this fits very well with the perception that we cannot expect to reach understanding of something and then assume that that understanding is going to be valid for the rest of our lives. Life, especially life in the classroom perhaps, is volatile, and constantly puzzling. So our last principle is that work for understanding should be continuous, not ‘projectised’. (Allwright, 2003d, p. 21) Life is continuous and dynamic. Our understandings are therefore always going to be provisional, at best, and valid only briefly, if at all. Our work for understanding, therefore, needs to be a continuous enterprise. (Allwright & Hanks, 2009, p. 153) 5. Final considerations Besides all the aspects presented, it also important to say that the use of the notion of understanding in EP is governed by rules, according to what Wittgenstein emphasizes about language in general. For him, language is a regulated activity, just like a game, but it does not mean these rules are immutable: “And is there not also the case where we play and—make up the rules as we go along? And there is even one where we alter them—as we go along.” (PI, § 83). In EP, practitioners use the term ‘understand’ to describe actions aimed at reflection, in order to shed light upon multiple aspects of life. Most importantly, drawing a parallel with Wittgenstein’s words, when he says that understanding is akin
to action, an idea that pervades EP activities is that “Exploratory Practice is action for understanding” (Allwright & Hanks, 2009). Finally, it is possible to say that the guiding principles of EP are compatible with a Wittgensteinian-oriented characterization of understanding as a concept that, among other factors: (a) is taken as an abiding condition and not as a mental occurrence; (b) is determined by regulated and public actions shared by members of the exploratory community; and (c) is considered as an occasion ultimately favorable to denaturalization of well established cultural practices.
References ALLWRIGHT, D. (1996)
Monitoring. Unpublished manuscript, Lancaster
University, Lancaster. ALLWRIGHT, D. (1999) Three major processes of teacher development and the appropriate criteria for developing and using them. Unpublished manuscript, ‘Voices from the field conference’, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2000) The notion of progress in research on language teaching and learning. Unpublished manuscript, Lancaster University, Lancaster. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2001a) Learning and teaching as well as you know. Why is it so difficult?
In: WAGNER, J. (Ed.) Pædagogik og læring i fremmed- og
andetsprog. Odense Working Papers in Language and Communication, No 22, 1-41. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2001b) Towards a new history of language teaching over the last five or six decades. Unpublished manuscript, Lancaster University, Lancaster. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2002) Bringing Classroom Language Learning to Life. Pesquisas em Discurso Pedagógico: qualidade de vida na sala de aula. PUC/Projeto IPEL Escola, Rio de Janeiro, Vol. 2.
ALLWRIGHT, D. (2003a) Why social science research needs to be practioner research: arguments for “Exploratory Practice”. Unpublished manuscript, PUC, Rio de Janeiro. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2003b) Exploratory Practice: re-thinking practitioner research in language teaching. Language Teaching Research, 7, 2, 113-141. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2003c) Exploratory Practice and Academic Research: the nature of the inter-relationship. Unpublished manuscript, PUC, Rio de Janeiro. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2003d) Planning for understanding: A new approach to the problem of method. Pesquisas em Discurso Pedagógico: vivenciando a escola. PUC/Projeto IPEL Escola, Rio de Janeiro, Vol. 2. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2005) From teaching points to learning opportunities and beyond. Tesol Quarterly, v.39, n.1, 9-31. ALLWRIGHT, D. (2006) Six Promising Directions in Applied Linguistics. In: GIEVE, S.; MILLER, I. (Eds) Understanding the Language Classroom. New York: Palgrave/McMillan. ALLWRIGHT, D. & BAILEY, K. (1991) Focus on the Language Classroom: An introduction to classroom research for language teachers. Cambridge: CUP. ALLRIGHT, D. & HANKS, J. (2001) Exploratory Practice as a Contribution to Classroom Method. Unpublished manuscript, Lancaster University, Lancaster. ALLRIGHT, D. & HANKS, J (2009) The developing language learner. An introduction to exploratory practice. New York: Palgrave/McMillan. ALLWRIGHT, D. & MILLER, I. K. (1998) Developing understandings of what happens in classrooms. Paper presented at IATEFL 32nd International Annual Conference. Manchester: Manchester Conference Selections, v. 1, 53-54.
BAKER, G.P. & HACKER, P.M.S. (1980) An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, vol. 1. BURBULES, N. & PETERS, M. (2001) Ludwig Wittgenstein. Retrieved October, 2007 from http://faculty.ed.uiuc.edu/burbules/papers/lw.html CAVELL, S. (1979) Excursus on Wittgenstein’s Vision of Language. In: The Claim of Reason. Oxford: OUP. CAVELL, S. (1996) The Normal and the Natural. In: The Cavell Reader. Massachusetts, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. GLOCK, H. (1998) Dicionário Wittgenstein (Helena Martins, Trans.). Rio de Janeiro: Zahar. GRAYLING, A.C. (1996) Wittgenstein (Milton Camargo Mota, Trans.). São Paulo: Ed. Loyola. HACKER, P. M. S.(2000) Wittgenstein: sobre a natureza humana (João Virgílio Gallenari Cutter, Trans.). São Paulo: UNESP. HACKER, P. M. S. (2001) Wittgenstein and the Autonomy of Humanistic Understanding. In: HACKER, P.M.S. Wittgenstein Connections and Controversies. Oxford: OUP. LUGG, A. (2000) Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1-133: A guide and interpretation. London: Routledge. MARTINS, H. (2000) Sobre a estabilidade do significado em Wittgenstein. Veredas, 7, 19 - 42. MARTINS, H. (2004) Entre a teoria e a prática. Anais do I Encontro em PLE. Unpublished manuscript, PUC, Rio de Janeiro. McGINN, M. (1997) Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations. London: Routledge. OLIVEIRA, M. A. (1996) Reviravolta Linguístico-pragmática na Filosofia
Contemporânea. São Paulo: Loyola. OLIVEIRA, P. (2004) Implicações do pensamento de Wittgenstein para o ensino de línguas. Cadernos de História da Filosofia da Ciência, 14 (2), 335 – 363. PETERS, M. (ed.) (1997) Education and the Postmodern Condition. London: Bergin & Garvey. PETERS, M. (2002) Wittgenstein, education and the philosophy of mathematics. Theory and Science, 3 (2). Retrieved September, 2008, from http://theoryandscience.icaap.org/content/vol003.002/peters.html WITTGENSTEIN, L (1992) O Livro Azul. (Jorge Mendes, Trans.). Lisboa: Edições 70. WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1996) Investigações Filosóficas (Marcos G. Montagnoli, Trans.). Petrópolis: Vozes. WITTGENSTEIN, L. (2000) Cultura e Valor (Jorge Mendes, Trans). Lisboa: Edições 70. WITTGENSTEIN, L. (2005) Philosophical Grammar. Berkeley: University of California Press.