on the ideological value of talk about art and science in medicine and law. ...... contemporary European law and that of newly colonised regions, such as India.
Art or Science? Understanding Medicine and the Common Law John A. Harrington*
Tho se of you who have either had or seen the process of a magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) scan cannot fail to be impressed with the scientific or tech nologic marvel of this huge diagnostic machinery. After a relatively noisy series of manoeuvres, the machine turns out a beautiful set of images on film. That is the science. What happ ens next, though, is that the films are given to a radiologist who gazes at them, puzzles for awhile and then gives an opinion on what they might mean. That is the art. 1
I.
Introduction
T he relationship between law and medicine has been considered from a number of perspec tives. Dominant among these is ethics, conceived o f as a normative system distinct from and superior to both practices. Particular features of health care provision and particular forms of legal regulation c an on this model be evaluated by reference to the values and p rinciples of various moral philosop hies. 2 Such theorizing normally takes the co ntent and modes of medical knowledge and practice as given and p roceeds d irectly to examine their significance for individuals and the wider society. Chiefly in dispute is the nature of moral personhood: when it begins, when it ends, what procedures and rules it entails, and so on. 3 The emphasis is, thereby, more upon questions of ontology than of epistem ology. The substance of medical knowledge is only opened up to philosophical consideration at its experimental marg ins.4 Even then the chief object of inquiry is to ascertain the noumenal implications of increasing medical
*
John A H arrington is a Jean Monnet Fellow, European University Institute, Florence, Italy. The author is grateful to Gavin Anderson, John McEldowney, Ambreena Manji, and Gary Watt for discussing with him the id eas c ontain ed h erein . The com m en ts o f B arb ara von Tigerst rom are also gr ate fully acknowledged. All responsibility is the author’s. 1 R. M arks, “ The Art, the Science and the Practice of Dermatology in the Next Millenium” (1999) 38 Int’l J. Dermatology 343 at 344. 2 One of the m ost influen tial e xamples of this is to be found in T.J. Beauchamp & J.F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. (Ox ford: Oxford U niversity Press, 1994). 3 This, for example, is the starting point of H.T. Engelhardt, The Found ations of Bioethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 19 86). 4 A noteworthy exception to this is E. Pellegrino & D. T hom asm a, A Philosophical Basis of Medical Practice: T o w ard a Philosophy and Ethic of the Healing Professions (N ew Yo rk: O xfor d U niver sity Press, 198 1).
130 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
knowledge and advances in medical technology. Cloning, embryo research and animal-to-human transplantation, for example, are seen as threats to stable understandings of what it is to be a human being and a moral person. 5 Law is usually taken to have an instrumental role: that of protecting the moral subject against the unethical and unjust actions of others and of restraining progress which threatens the ontological foundations of human personhood and o f society. 6 Sociological writing under the particular influence of Max W eber has, by contrast, focussed upon the legal and med ical pro fessions as elite social groupings and upon professionals as privileged eco nomic ac tors. 7 On this view doctors and lawyers seek to monopolize the provision of valua ble services to the rest of society, by circumscribing or de-legitimating the work of rival practitioners and the knowledge of laype rsons. The law is seen as an important resource in achieving and legitimating this occupational closure and the status and econom ic gains which go with it.8 Most importantly, licensing requirements and the state-supported mon opo ly are anchored in legislation. However, although largely produced by Anglo-American scholars, this work has not concerned itself to any significant extent with the relevance to professionalization of the common law, the most distinctive eleme nt of the leg al system in Anglophone countries. This essay see ks to develop these hitherto neglected perspectives. On the one hand, it moves beyond traditional philosophical writing in advancing a tentative understanding of the legal regulation of medicine based upon widely accepted epistemological foundations of both practices. It seeks to explain the specific similarities which allow medicine and the law to interact as practices and as forms of knowledge. On the other hand, it expands upon the familiar sociological literature by focussing on the relationship between medicine and the common law. The discussion is structured as follows. First we note the distinctively favourable liability regime to which medicine is subjected in English law. Rea sons for this – none of them wholly satisfying – can be found in the shared background o f doctors and judges, in the political origins of the British health care system, and in judicial concern to conserve scarce resources. A more profitable line of inquiry focuses on the similarities between medicine and the common law, as constructed in the discourses of their leading practitioners. Through a representative study, we consider the manner in which a variable ideal of medicine has been constructed out of an opposition between art and science models of practice. In each case the profession as a whole or groups within it have sought to attain specific material and symb olic objectives. Thereafter an attem pt is made to reconstruct these strategic
5 See e.g. H. J onas, Philosophical Essays: From Current Creed to Technological Man (Chicago: University of Chicago P ress, 1980 ). 6 A classic statement of this position is to be found in I. Kenn edy, The Unm asking of Medicine (London: Allen & U nwin, 19 81). 7 See particularly, F. Pa rkin, M a rx is m and Class Theory (London: Tavistock, 1979); and T.J. Johnson, Professions and Power (London: M acm illan, 1972 ). 8 See A . W itz, Professions and Patriarchy (London: Routledge, 1992) at 53-69.
Harrington # Art or Science? 131
discourses in philosophical terms. From the work of M ichael Oakeshott and Michael Polanyi we derive a number of ideal typical elements of medicine as an art. These can also be seen to fea ture strongly in jud icial and theoretical characterizations of the common law as a practical activity and as an implicit body of knowledge. We rely on the epistemological writings of Karl Poppe r to help clarify the central features of medicine as a pluralistic and progressive science. The common law too has been shown to obey an evolutionary dynamic. At a quotidian level the engine of this progre ss is frequently taken to be the phenomenon of plural and minority judgments in the higher courts. We conclude by commenting b riefly on the ideological value of talk about art and science in medicine and law. The varied elabo ration o f professional self-unde rstandings do es not just serve to legitimate the status of doctors and lawyers. It also articulates the ideals of dominant socio-economic groups and, thus, contributes to the achievement of consensus in une qual societies.
II.
Judging Medicine in English Law
The English courts have traditionally set the standard of care by which doctors’ work is judged in terms particularly favourable to the medical profession. Under the well-known “Bolam test” a doctor will not be held liable in negligence if they have conformed to the practice of a “responsible body of medical practitioners.” 9 This practice does not even have to be followed by a majority of professiona ls working in the same field as the defendant. All that is required is that the practice have a logical basis, meaning that it is only proposed after a careful risk-benefit analysis.1 0 In consequence, professional custom as attested to by expert witnesses almost always determines what is culpable and what not in the context of diagnosis, treatment and the d isclosure of risks. 1 1 This is more or less exceptional as regards professions generally in English law.1 2 It is the subject of more o r less plausible exp lanations which are set out in the following passages. W hat we might term the “class conspiracy” theory has been advanced by a leading Australian judge who saw judicial lenience as “arising from the class system and the hierarchical nature of English society and reflecting the unwillingness of one profession ... to countenance ordinary people challenging the rules laid do wn by a nother profession.” 1 3 Ho wever, this of itself does not explain
9
The test comes from the decision of McNair J. in Bolam v. Friern Hospital Managem ent Comm ittee, [1957 ] 1 W .L.R. 582 (Q .B.). 10 The responsible body of opinion must have a “logical bas is,” m ean ing th at it has to have been preceded by an a nalysis of risk s: Bolitho v. City and Ha ckn ey H ealth Au thor ity, [1988] A.C . 23 2 (H .L.). T his is a fairly weak qualification in practice. 11 For a recent discussion, see J. M iola & M . Brazier, “Bye-Bye Bolam : a Med ical Litigation Revolution?” (2000 ) 8 M ed. L. Rev. 85. 12 Edward Wo ng F inan ce C o L td v. Johnson Stokes & Master, [19 84] 1 A .C. 296 (P.C .); Cavanagh v. Ulster Weaving Co., [1960 ] A.C . 145 (H .L.). 13 M . Kirby, “Patients’ Rights - Why the Australian Courts Have Rejected ‘Bolam’” (1995) 21 J. Med. Ethics 5.
132 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
the courts’ exceptional response to doctors, as opposed to architects or even solicitors. A crude sense of class loyalty should bind the judiciary to members of these other professions too, yet the relevant rules of the common law evince considerably less solicitude o f their interests. A more politically informed understanding would note the implicit contract between the medical profession and the Labour government which ceded control of health care resources to doctors in return fo r their participation in the National Health Service (NHS) from 1 948 on. 1 4 It can be hypothesized accordingly that the courts sought to reinforce the macro-contract by preserving the autonomy of doctors in the micro-situation o f decisio ns as to d iagnosis, therap y and d isclosure. This theory explains too little, ho wever. Judicial tenderness towards medica l defendants was already evident in the decades before 1948.1 5 Furthermore, it has survived several fundamental changes in the structure and governance of the NHS since then, changes which have diminished the authority of the medical profession within the health care system.1 6 The “scarce national resources” theory reflects the persistent concern among the judiciary that funds be retained within the NHS for the primary purpose of health care rather than effectively reallocated to injured patients in the form of dama ges. 1 7 Negligence decisions also note the importance of not deterring “young men from entering the profession” through fear of litigation.1 8 This theory is certainly plausible as regards judicial m otivation. Ho wever, it is insufficiently specific as an account of judicial reaso ning. Since the early 19 80s, English courts have been wary of basing their negligence decisio ns on e xplicit gro unds of po licy. 1 9 Reaso nableness tests are p referred which reflect b oth the nuanc es of the activity under scrutiny an d the constraints of precedent. 2 0 Thus, an adequate explanation of the origins of the Bolam test will have to be based on the distinctive features of medical activity, as reconstructed by the law.
14
R. K lein, T he Ne w P olitic s o f th e N H S, 3d ed. (London: Longman, 1995) at 1-27. Consider, for example, the decisions in M ars hall v. Lin dse y C oun ty Co unc il, [1935 ] 1 K.B . 516 (C .A.); and Hillyer v. The Governors of St Bartholomew’s Hospital, [1909 ] 2 K.B . 820 (C .A.). 16 For a d iscuss ion of thes e chan ges, see Klein, supra note 14 at 147-54. 17 Whitehouse v. Jordan, [1 980 ] 1 A ll E.R. 650 (C. A.) , D enn ing M .R. ; Wilsher v. Ess ex A rea He alth Au thor ity, [1986] 3 A ll E.R. 801 (C.A.), M ustill L.J.. In a closely related context it has been held that an app lication f or ju dicia l review of N HS allocation dec ision s is likely to f ail sinc e “a c ourt [ can not] prop erly express opinions upon the way in which national resources are allocated or distributed... The cou rts of this cou ntry ca nno t arran ge the lists in th e ho spita l ...”: R v. Central Birmingh am He alth Authority, ex parte Collier, (C.A.) 6 Jan uary 1988 p er Stephen B row n L.J.) e xtrac ted in I. Ken ned y & A. G rubb , M edic al L aw . Te xt w ith M ater ials, 2d ed. (London: Butterworths, 1994) at 428-29. 18 Whitehouse v. Jordan, ibid. at 65 8d, De nnin g M .R. Th is ha s be en d iscu ssed in term s of a “ne ed to secure a socially valued service” in J. Montgomery, “Medicine, Accountability and Professionalism” (1989) 16 J. L. & Society 319 at 328-30. 19 M . Jones , Textbook on Tort, 7th ed. (London: Blackstone, 2000) at 41. 20 Ibid . at 174. 15
Harrington # Art or Science? 133
By contra st with the foregoing exp lanations, the theory of “identification” focusses specifically on the formal similarities between medical and legal practice. As Allen Linden put it: “[e]vidence of general practice is accorded more respect in medical matters than it receives in other types of cases because there is a greater judicial trust in the reasonableness of the practices of a sister profession than there is in the methods of com merc ial men.” 2 1 Bo th med icine and law can be shown to be oriented to uncertain phenomena which call forth the exercise of fine jud gment; both are taken to exhibit progress through a pluralistic contes t of ideas. There is much in this explanation. Lord Denning, for one, took a “there but for the grace of God go I” appro ach to medical negligence cases. 2 2 In fact, the p resent essay is an attempt to reconstruct judicial intimations of the similarity between medicine and the law. It explores the “epistemic underscore”2 3 of both disciplines through an elaboration of the distinction, fam iliar from med ical rheto ric, between art and science.
III. The “Art-Science” Distinction in Medicine In exploring the distinction between art and science in medicine we turn to medical history, no t in search of definitional certainty, but in order to find examples of the work do ne by b oth term s in specific professiona l and so cial contexts. B oth have been deployed strategically in a discourse of opposites in order to advance the interests o f the who le pro fession o r factions within it. In the early decades of the nineteenth century general practitioners and provincial doctors in England promoted an idea of scientific medicine as a means of overcoming the social and occupational barriers to their advancement erected by the metropolitan, consultant elite.2 4 Tertius Lydgate, a charac ter in George Eliot’s novel Middlemarch, is a typical example of such reforming d octors. 2 5 Lydgate had studied first in Edinb urgh, then in Paris, where he encountered the new science of pathological anatomy. In England, by contrast, “this was a dark period ” for medicine, when the “venerable colleges used great efforts to secure purity of knowledge by making it scarce and to exclude error by a rigid exclusive ness in relation to fees and ap pointments.” 2 6 Rejecting the “empty bigwiggism” of London, Lydgate “was ab sorbed ... in the ambition of making his life recognized as a factor in the better life of mankind like other heroes of science who had nothing but an
21
A.M. Linden, “Custom in Negligence Law” (1968) 11 Can. Bar J. 151 at 157. Whitehouse v. Jordan, supra note 17 at 658, Lord Denning M.R. 23 This phrase is used in a related context in W .T. Murphy, “The O ldest Social Scie nce ? Th e Ep istem ic Properties of the Comm on Law Tradition” (1991) 54 Mod. L. Rev. 182. 24 See J.H. W arner, “The Idea of Science in English Medicine: The ‘Decline of Science’ and the R hetor ic of Refo rm , 181 5-184 5" in R . Frenc h & A. W ear, eds ., British Medicine in an Age of Reform (London: Routledge, 1991) 136. 25 Its fidelity is confirmed by stud ies in the history of medicine; for a useful summ ary, see C. Lawrence, Medicine in the Making of Modern Britain 1700-1920 (London: Routledge, 1994) at 27 [hereinafter M akin g of M ode rn B ritain ]. 26 G. E liot, Middlemarch (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1994) at 141. 22
134 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
obscure country practice to begin with.” 2 7 The contrast between progressive, scientific medicine and its unscientific counterpart is manifest in the very different diagnoses and treatments offered by Lydgate and his traditionalist rival Wrench. On being called to attend the young Fred Vincy, Wrench hastily concludes that the stricken man is suffering from “a slight derangement.” He prescribes and provide s, at a pro fit to himself, “the usual white parcels which this time had black and d rastic contents.” 2 8 When these prove useless, Lydgate is called. He observes the patient closely and hears “a narrative which insisted on every point of mino r impo rtance.” As a result V incy is diagnosed precisely as suffering from “the pink-skinned stage of typhoid fev er,” exacerb ated b y taking the wrong med icines. Im med iate rest is ordered, along with the use of “various appliances and precautions ... about which Lydgate was particular.” 2 9 In a co uple o f days Fred Vinc y is cured.3 0 W hat is important in this incident is not so much Lydgate’s fictional success as the positive dimensions of scientific medicine which it communicates: careful observation and reasoning towards an inductive diag nosis, co ntrasted with hunch; systematic experimentation and revision of kno wledge, contrasted with stagnation; a d ynamic of progress which identifies medicine with public well-being, contrasted with the financial exploitation of patients. By the mid nineteenth century scientific medicine had been broadly accepted by the lead ers of the profession. In deed it pro vided the cog nitive and corp orate unity which in turn led to the legal enshrinement of the medical mo nopoly in 1858. 3 1 Over the following century the social and material status of the profession profited handsomely from sc ientific breakthro ughs in p hysiology, bacteriology and pharmac ology.3 2 Neither factionalism within the profession, nor threats to its autonomy from without were entirely eliminated, however; and it is in the defensive strategies of practitioners thus concerned that we find the fullest articulation of the art conception of m edicine. As Lawrence ha s shown, many late Victorian practitioners resisted experimental physiology and the introduction of new medical devices with epistemological arguments which privileged experience, common sense and personal character over technical and generalizable knowledge. For instance, Professor Frederick Roberts of University College London, writing in the British Med ical Journal in 1892, ridiculed the notion of organ specific disorders. In his view, such theories were inspired by a scientific monomania, quite alien to the holistic philosophy of English medicine and the generalism of its gentleman
27
Ibid . at 160. Ibid . at 250. 29 Ibid . at 251. 30 Uns urprising ly Lydgate’s “showy foreign ideas” and his social impu dence provoked both scepticism and resentment am ong his rural peers. Eliot has Chicheley, the coroner, say that “[y]ou never hear of re fo rm , but it means some trick to put in new men,” a comment which also points up the m aterial dimen sion to stru ggles o ver m edic al know ledge and links th em with the p olitical con flict between radicalism and reaction in the 1820s and 30s: see ibid. at 152. 31 M akin g of M ode rn B ritain , supra note 25 at 56. 32 R. Porter, Th e G rea test B ene fit to M ank ind. A M edic al History of Humanity from Antiquity to the Pre sen t. (London: Harper Collins, 1997) at 428. 28
Harrington # Art or Science? 135
practitioners. 3 3 Instruments such as the sphagmometer, for measuring blood pressure, or the be tter-known stetho scop e, were deno unced as threatening to “pauperize the senses and weaken clinical acuity.” 3 4 The doctor was better off relying “upon the information yielded by the trained finger ... [which], if not very precise, would be sufficient for all practical p urpo ses.” 3 5 In resp onse to the initiation of controlled clinical trials of new drugs in the 1930s and 40s critical commentators again stressed the limited applicability of science to medicine.3 6 Professor Lionel Whitby of Cambridge informed readers of the L ancet in 1946 that, “it is true that medicine will never be an exact science because the normal variations in individuals have such a w ide range that autom atic and mechanica l treatment is prohibited .” 3 7 On the art view, therefore, medical knowledge is embodied, personal, and ineffable. Science provides a base for practice, but at the bedside it mu st yield to the fine and irreducible judgment of the experienced practitioner. This emphasis on “producer virtualities”3 8 remains a feature of polemics concerning medical knowledge up to the present day. As much has been demonstrated by Anderso n in his account of a failed attempt to replace the traditional, impressionistic medical record with a co mpu ter-gene rated system at the Royal Melbo urne Hospital in the 1970s. 3 9 T he new system was designed by clinica l scientists to fo rce doctors to make explicit, logical co nnections between all the available clinical knowledge and the individual patient’s diagno sis. Perhaps surprisingly, the project’s failure was not due to any crucial experimen tal result which demonstrated its inefficacy. Rather, computerization was perceived to impinge upon physicians’ “symbolic domain of competence” by downgrading craft knowledge and clinical memory. Though keen to have science ratify their judgments, the medics were unwilling to let it restructure the clinical encounter co mpletely. 4 0 Art values have also been reaffirmed programmatica lly in an attem pt to extract co ntemp orary med icine from its perceived crisis. In a recent popular critique James Le Fanu traces this crisis to the profession’s hubristic desire for scientific knowledge and its concomitant willingness to treat p atients merely as b undles of clinical material.4 1 A re-
33 C. Law ren ce, “In com m un ica ble Knowledge: Science Technology and the Clinical Art in Britain 18501914" (1985) 20 J. Contemp. Hist. 503 at 513. 34 Ibid . at 505. 35 Quoted in ibid. at 516. 36 Th is wa s an im porta nt ch allenge to exis ting therapeutics ,much of w hich had remained unchallenged since the Middle Ages: see D. Armstrong, “Clinical Sense and Clinical Science” (1977) 11 Soc. Science & M ed. 599 at 599. 37 Quoted in ibid. at 600. 38 See R. W hitley, “The Transformation of Expertise b y N e w K nowle dge : Co nting enc ies an d Lim its to Skill Scientification” (1988) 27 Soc. Science Information 391 at 403. 39 W . Arm stong, “The Reasoning of the Strongest: The Polemics of Skill and Science in Medical Diagnosis” (19 92) 22 S oc. Stud. of Science 653. For other examples, see M Balint, “The O ther Part of Med icine” [7 Ja nuary1 961 ] Th e Lance t 40; S.C . Schoen baum , “Improving the Art and Science of Medical Practice” (1998) 10 Int’l J. for Quality in Health Care 81. 40 Arm stong, ibid. at 672. 41 J. Le Fan u, The Rise and Fall of Modern Medicine (London: Abacus, 1999) at 196.
136 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
moralization of clinical practice is necessary to restore public trust in medicine. This is only possible, however, on the basis of an epistemic reorientation of medical activity away from the present “obsession with the new” and toward “the wisdom of the past”.4 2
IV. The “Art” Model: Practical Knowledge In this section we attempt to reconstruct the idea of medicine as an art using the insights of the philosophers Michael Oakeshott and M ichael Polanyi. Oakeshott identifies knowledge in modern societies as having a dual form: technical and practical. 4 3 Technica l knowledge is explicit and precise. It can be formulated in rules of the sort contained in cookery b ooks and the Highway Code . By co ntrast, practical knowledge exists only in use. As with the know ledge actually used in cooking and driving, it cannot be formulated in rules. Po lanyi characterizes this as personal knowledge, subsidiary to that of which the subject is focally or consciously aware.4 4 It forms the indispensable “tacit coefficient” of all knowledge and of all practice based o n that kno wledge. Fo r both philosophers practical (or perso nal) knowledge is logically prior to technical knowledge: the rules and maxims of the latter are merely an ex p ost facto abridgement of the forme r. This demotion of explicit knowledge has a num ber of imp ortant implications. First, the authentic form of knowledge is that which is personal to the knower. Polanyi in particular emphasizes the significant cognitive input of the individual subje ct. He rejects external criteria of objectivity on the basis that such criteria have no referent. There is no detac hed, universal knowledge to which they apply. A commitment to finding the truth on the p art of an investigator is the only warrant of the objectivity of the knowledge that he o r she prod uces. 4 5 Second, where as technical knowledge is taught and learned in the ab stract, practical knowledge is imparted and acquired by imitative participation in the relevant activity. 4 6 Explicit knowledge can only be transmitted through books and other written materials, tacit knowledge through a period of apprenticeship to a master. Third, technical knowledge is of its nature equally available to the veteran, the newcomer and even the uninvolved layperson. By contrast, since practical knowledge is acquired o ver time, those who know most about a given practice will
42
Ibid . at 408. M . Oa kesho tt, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays, 2d ed. (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1991). 44 M . Polanyi, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1958) at 55. 45 Ibid . at 65. 46 Polan yi refer s to th e latter a s “m im etic tran sm ission ’: ibid. at 206. 43
Harrington # Art or Science? 137
be those who have been involved in it for the longest time. Experience, therefore, should determine seniority within a given discipline. Fourth, the significance of individual experience has as its corollary the preeminent status of tradition as a storehouse of wisdom and as a guide to future activity. Apprenticeship is first and foremo st an initiation into the ine ffable traditions of the particular discipline. T hese are not static howe ver. Fo r Oakesho tt, each tradition represents “a flow o f sympathy,” an o ngoing series o f attemp ts to pursue intimations revealed in present practice.4 7 This in turn suggests a constraint upon the “commitment” theory of objectivity which was mentioned above. Knowledge can only be extended or practice modified in ways which cohere with the traditions of the discipline. Fifth, reading the previous two p oints together, we can conclude that those best able to testify to the traditions of a disc ipline at any given time are those w ith the greatest perso nal exp erience of it. This mea ns that they are the best judges o f what is and is no t an authentic instance of the practice. In Polanyi’s terms they constitute an “organized consensus” which distinguishes authoritatively between, for example, the scientific and the unscientific.4 8 In the following section we consider the extent to which these ideal-typical attributes of medicine as an art are reflected in the historic self-understandings of comm on lawyers.
V.
The Common Law as Art: Tradition and Judgment
The common law has long been taken to be a form of practical knowledge.4 9 Indeed Polanyi himself argued that it was “the most important system of reasoned traditional activities.” 5 0 As lex non scripta the commo n law exists before and beyond the judgments in which it is applied.5 1 In fact the decision of the individual judge, on this view, does not itself amount to law. Rather it is (merely) the opinion of an expert as to what the law is.5 2 As such the co ntent of judicial reasoning is inherently contingent and revisable: there is no “possibility of a court, however elevated, reaching a final, au thoritative stateme nt of wha t the law is in a general abstract sense.” 5 3 No t only this, it is even possible that the judge involved may give
47
Oa kesho tt, supra note 43 at 15. Polanyi, supra note 44 at 163. 49 For a recent discussion, see M . Loughlin, “Rights Discourse and Public Law Thought in the United K in gd om ” in G.W . And erson, e d., Rights and Dem ocracy: Ess ays in UK -Canadian C onstitutionalism (London: Blackstone, 1999) 193. 50 Polanyi, supra note 44 at 54. 51 For a dis cus sion of this with partic ular re feren ce to work of Coke, Hale, Blackstone and Burke, see G.J. Postem a, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (Oxford : Clarendon Pres s, 1986) at 37 ff. 52 Ibid . at 9. 53 A.W.B. Simpson, “Th e C om m on La w a nd L egal T heo ry” in A.W .B. S imp son, ed ., Ox ford Ess ays in Jurisprud ence (2nd series) (Oxford: Clarendon, 1973) 77 at 90. 48
138 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
an incorrect exp lanation of what he or she has do ne in the case itself. This “essentially shadowy character of the common law”5 4 clearly distinguishes it from both English statute law and the codes in force in civilian jurisdictions. Critics of the common law, usually proponents of codification such as Jerem y Bentham, held that it was not law at all since it could not be given a fixed verbal formulation. 5 5 The resulting uncertainty was at one and the same time detrimental to the general welfare and beneficial to an elite caste of lawyers, who alone were able to report on what the law was. Bentham’s legal theories were, thus, of a part with his other plans for the ra tionaliza tion of so ciety as a whole. It is worth noting, in this connection, that these plans marked Bentham out for scathing criticism more than a century later by M ichael Oakeshott.5 6 The work of the utilitarian philosopher anticipated the rationalist elevation of technical knowledge which Oakeshott deplored in his own contemporaries. The rules contained in such cod es were me re abridge ments, equivalent to grammarians’ rules which summarize but can never sum up the living languages (or laws) to which they refer.5 7 The com mon law can be seen as an art in ap plication, as much as in fo rm. T his has two related dimensions: namely, that cases arising are unique; and that the decision of each is a matter of fine and irred ucible judgment. It is not unusual for judges to refer to the novelty of the case before them and to limit the precedential value of their decision to a very specifically defined type of fact-situation. But this flight into particularism is not necessarily a bad faith attempt to evade the burden of establishing and following precedents. Just as no two patients presenting for diagnosis are completely alike, so no two cases are who lly comparable. Ind eed it is the concern of both medicine and law with a variable subject matter which distinguishes them from more theoretical or speculative sciences, like physics and chem istry. Each of the former, as a non-comprehen sive “science of p articulars,” requires the exercise of an inevitably fallible judgm ent. 5 8 Lawyers do not reason entirely by deduction or by indu ction. T he ma ss of legal material, and the ineffable nature of the common law make this impossible. Instead, as Stone observed, they ope rate an informal logic of analogy, which he labels “paraduction.” This involves “the ferreting out from particular instances of those resemblances which need not belong to every particular of a kind, but which some bear to others but not necessarily to all, like family resemb lances.” 5 9 The ability to reason effectively in this manner requires the cultivation of skills of discrimination and distinction; the development, that is, of a “feel” for the similarities and dissimilarities between cases. As we have seen, medical practitioners also commonly affirm the primacy of personal experience as a basis for knowledge and action. To paraphrase Geertz,
54
Ibid . at 87. Postem a, supra note 51 at 290. 56 Oa kesho tt, supra note 43 at 140-41. 57 Sim pson , supra note 53 at 94. 58 For an illuminating discussion, see S. Gorovitz & A. MacIntyre, “Toward a Theory of Medical Fallibility” (1976) 1 J. Med. & Phil. 51. 59 R. Stone, “Ratiocination not Rationalisation” (1965) 74 Mind 463 at 477-478. 55
Harrington # Art or Science? 139
both doctors and “lawyers are connoisseurs of cases in point, cognoscenti of matters in hand .” 6 0 How is this connoisseurship, this judgment to be taught? As Hale wrote, “[m]en are not born commo n lawyers, neither can the bare exercise of reason give a man a sufficient knowledge of it.” 6 1 The “artificial reason” of the common law could not be acquired through the study of systematic or generalized principles either. In fact it was just this type of education in technical knowledge which Oakesho tt condemned as useless “training.” 6 2 Rationalists started from the ideal of an empty mind, a blank sheet on which knowledge could be directly imprinted. If, as is always the case in reality, the mind is not empty, the teacher should administer a “mental purgative” and start afresh. 6 3 However, nothing of any worth could be imparted in this manner. By definition, ineffable or tacit knowledge could not be taught directly but only through a lengthy initiation into the traditions of the relevant discipline. Thus, common lawyers had long been educated by app renticeship to adm itted practitioners. The pre-eminence of this model was however, challenged in the nineteenth century by the rise of academic law in England.6 4 Pro ponents of the latter were frequently Benthamite utilitarians. They regretted that the law had nothing comparable to British medical schools, which provided a thorough scientific education as a prelude to an apprenticeship on the wards. 6 5 However, as Cocks show s, reform , if not who lly thwarted , was certainly domesticated and weakened by conservatives in the profession.6 6 Their arguments emphasized practical exp erience ove r formal learning. Some went as far a s to suggest that “the only real test of a good lawyer was success in practice exam inations were irrelevant.” 6 7
VI. The “Science” Model: Progress Through Pluralism W e have seen that the idea of medicine as a science has also been deployed by the medical profession (or factions within it) to defend its social status and occupational privileges. It is centra l to this idea that medicine demonstrates progress bene ficial to hum anity. By contra st, its rivals, such as folk or non-
60 C. Geer tz, Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (London: Fontana Press, 1993) at 168. 61 Qu oted in P ostem a, supra note 51 at 33. 62 Oa kesho tt, supra note 43 at 16. 63 In a similar vein Oakeshott quotes Voltaire as saying that “the only way to have good laws is to burn all existing laws a nd to start a fresh” : Oak eshott, supra note 43 at 9. 64 D . Sugarman, “Legal Theory, the Comm on Law Mind a nd the M aking of Tradition” in W . Twining, ed., Legal Theory and the Common Law (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986) 26. 65 R. Cock s, Foundations of the Modern B ar (London: Sw eet & M axwell, 1983) at 191 ; for a study of this form of education, see P. Atkins on, The Clinical Experience: The Construction and Reconstruction of Medical Reality (Aldershot: Gowe r, 1981). 66 Cock s, ibid. at 194. 67 Ibid . at 180.
140 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
European med icine, are portrayed as static and irrational. 6 8 The value of orthodox, W estern med icine is thus closely associated with a specific epistemic property: the fact that it is seen to renew its knowledge base in an orderly, open and intelligible manner. In this section we seek to reconstruct the idea of medicine as a progressive science with reference to the work of Karl Poppe r. This work has be en highly influential and embodies an ideal of rational progress which corresponds to that shared by many scientists and doctors themselves, as well as by the wider lay public.6 9 Change in science, according to Popper, can be modelled upon Darwinian evolutionary biology. 7 0 Like plant and animal life, scientific knowledge develops through a continuous process of variation and selection.7 1 At the first stage, just as the gene structure of an organism responds to environmental pressures by internal mutation and recombination, so science responds to theoretical problems by developing tentative new theories. At the second stage, just as there is selection as between available genetic mutations and variations, so scientific theories are tested experimentally and the erroneous eliminated. Science is accordingly not characterized by attem pts to generate true statements about nature inductively, as had previously been assume d. Instead the scientist seeks to falsify expe rimentally the theories which hav e been p ropo sed by them selves or others. 7 2 This evolutionary m ode l and the metho d of falsification allow us to distinguish science from non-science. First, statements which are not capable of being falsified are by definition not scientific. W here they are nonetheless put forward as such they are in the nature of mere dogma o r ideo logy. T he latter are generally hind rance s to pro gress. Second, scientists take (or should take) a thoroughly critical attitude b oth to their own theories and to those which are already well established. As a matter of intellectual good faith, it is not p ermitted systematically to reject exp erimental
68 I.A.J. Semali, “Associations and H ealers: Attitudes toward s Collaboration in T anz ania ” in M . Last & G. Ch avun duka , eds., The Professionalization of African Medicine (M anc hes ter: M anc hes ter U niver sity Press, 1986) 8 7; for further discussion of the interaction between medicine and law in a colonial and post-colonial settin g, se e J. H arrin gton, “B etw een the S tate an d C ivil Soc iety: M edic al D iscip line in Tanzania” (1999) 37 J. Mod. Afr. Stud. 207. 69 B. M agee, Popper , 3d e d. (Lo ndo n: Fo ntan a, 19 85) at 10 ; I. Lakatos , “H istory of Scie nce and its Rational Rec onstruc tions” in I. H acking, ed ., Scientific Revolutions ( Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981) 107 at 113. 70 K. Popper, “E volution and the Tree of K no w ledge” in K. P oppe r, Objective Knowledge - An Evolutionary Approach, rev. ed. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1979) 256. 71 K. P oppe r, “Th e Ra tionality of Scientific R evolutions” in Ha cking, supra note 69, 80 at 82 ff. 72 In developing this mod el of science, Popper b uilt upon the work of the n ineteenth century pioneer of physiology Claud e Be rnard. S ee G. C angu ilhem , A Vital Rationalist: Selected Writings (New York; Zone Books, 1994) at 139.
Harrington # Art or Science? 141
results which confound theoretical exp lanations: for examp le, by ap pealing to prob lems of observation or b y postulating unapp rehende d interfering factors. 7 3 Third, science does not progress towards any type of immutable or transcendental truth. It is instead immanently or procedurally rational, seek ing only to generate well-tested theories an d solutions to current prob lems. 7 4 Accordingly the knowledge produced thereby is inevitably contingent and subject to revision or rejection. Fourth, the evolutionary model is based on a pro cess of rational learning by feedback. 7 5 Information as to the success or failure of an expe riment is returned to the theoretical level whereupon new research problems are generated for further testing and so on. The know ledge produced thereby is public, not private in form. It is laid down in the objective fo rm of written sources and is therefore available for all to study and to criticize.7 6 Fifth, scientific ideas are most likely to evolve under conditions of free and open com petition. In other word s, theoretical pluralism drives progress. 7 7 Centralization and uniformity in the production of scientific ideas leads inevitab ly to a failure of adaptatio n; that is, to stagnation and b ackwardness. Sixth, the existing state of scientific knowledge sets limits to the extent of perm issible pluralism at any given time. It is implicit in the evolutionary model that new theories can only be generated recursively; that is, they must draw upon and mod ify previous theories. T he trad ition of the discipline is therefore an im portant, although ever-shifting constraint upon scientific work.7 8 Only hypotheses which are developed in this way (and which meet the “falsifiability” criterion) can be classed as truly scientific. The rest fall into the category of pseudo-science and can be disregarded. In the following section we examine the extent to which the common law is equally seen as embodying an evolutionary, conflict-driven dynamic.
73
“The Rationality of Scientific Revolutions,” supra note 71 at 96. See L. Laudan, “A Problem Solving Approach to Scien tific Progres s” in H acking, supra note 69, 144. 75 See M agee, supra note 69 at 65. 76 K. Popper, “E pistemology without a Knowing Subject” in Objective Knowledge - An Evolutionary Approach , supra note 70, 106 at 112. 77 Th is corre spo nds to “organized scepticism,” one of M erton’s four organizational norms of science: see R. M erton, The Sociology of Science (Chicago: U niversity of Chicago Press, 197 3). 78 “The Rationality of Scientific Revolutions,” supra note 71 at 87. 74
142 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
VII. The Common Law as Science: Evolution and Dissent It is useful to examine the idea of progress in the common law from two perspectives. 7 9 First, we discuss briefly an influential tradition in legal history and legal anthropology which sees law as evolving over centuries from primitive origins to modern complexity. Second, we consider the routine development of the common law from case to case and, in particular, the distinctively Anglo-Saxon phenom enon of the d issenting judgm ent. The most important formulation of the evolutionary understanding of the common law is undoubtedly to be found in Henry Maine’s Ancient Law,8 0 first published in 1860. M aine sketched a history of law, from pre-customary decrees, through the law of the Roman republic and empire, and on to the legal systems of W estern Europe in the nineteenth century. Law had developed, he argued, from custom to rule-based systems, from disparate to centralized power structures, and from dominating its subjects to guaranteeing individual self-determination. Maine famously summed up the dynamic by saying that “the movement of the progressive societies has hitherto been a movem ent from Status to Contract.” 8 1 Two features of Maine’s work are significant for this discussion. First, he distinguished progressive from stationary societies. This was necessary to explain the divergence between contemporary European law and that of newly colonised regions, such as India. The colonies were Europe’s pa st made p resent to itself, affirming both its origins and the immense progress which it had achieved.8 2 Second, Maine was influenced by the uniform itarian doctrine of Charles Lyell, a con temporary geolo gist. According to this, changes in the Earth’s surface were constant, gradual and imperceptible, the result of regular physical forces. As Stein has noted, “this provided an attractive analo gy with the tra ditiona l view of the com mon law.” 8 3 Notwithstanding, or perhaps beca use of, his lack o f detailed research, M aine’s grand generalizations ra pidly b ecam e “the co mmon currency of legal tho ught.” 8 4 Furthermore, they were seen as being in accord with the natural scientific writings of Charles Darwin, “the predominant mythmaker o f evolutio n.” 8 5 Thus, Pollock could write that: “Maine showed that legal ideas and institutions have a real course of development as much as the genera and species of living creatures. [And also] that law has a history of its own, not at all confined to its political and constitutional
79
These ideas are discussed more fully in J. Harrington, “‘Red in Tooth and Claw’: The Idea of Progress in Medicine and the Comm on Law” (2002) 11 Soc. & Legal Stud. 211. 80 H . M aine, Ancient Law: Its Connection with the Early History of Society and its Relation to Mo dern Ideas (London: John M urray, 1870). 81 Ibid . at 141. 82 See P . Fitzpatrick, The Mythology of Modern Law (London, New York: Routledge, 1992) at 100. 83 P. Stein, Legal Evolution: The Story of an Idea (Camb ridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980) at 88. 84 Ibid . at 98. 85 The Myt hology of Modern Law , supra note 8 2 at 9 3. It sh ould, how ever , be n oted th at D arw in’s spe cific ideas had not been widely disseminated by the time Ancient Law wa s pu blish ed. A s state d in the text, they significantly conditioned its reception.
Harrington # Art or Science? 143
aspects.” 8 6 Fitzpatrick has explained the p opularity of M aine’s thesis on the grounds that it located law within a general nineteenth century epistemic scheme predicated upon “pervasive and inexorable change.” 8 7 In particular, middle and upper class Victorians were eager to embrace theories which ascribed the immense changes through which they were living to ineluctable and irresistible forces. 8 8 Current circumstances of inequality were thus justified and removed from the realm of political contestation and intervention. To lawyers the evolutionary perspec tive revea led that the law was able to ad apt itself gra dually, that is without convulsion or revolution, to new so cial and economic circumstanc es. 8 9 This pattern was also taken to be characteristic of medicine in the late 1800s, whereb y the sectarianism and theoretical disjunctures of the early century were replaced by a unified knowledge base and a regime of ord erly progress. 9 0 The growing armoury of medical techniques and the responsiveness of the common law to new conditions were both identified strongly with the public interest. The common law can be viewed as progressing, not just over the longue durée from time imm emo rial to the p resent, but also from case to c ase. T he eng ine of this progress is, in the higher courts at least, the production of plural opinions and dissenting judgments. It is in the form of the latter, we would submit, that the common law exhibits progress through ordered conflict in the manner of medical science. Majority, as opp osed to consensus decision making has been practised in the English courts since at least the fifteenth century. In a recent study, Alder has helped to clarify the chief practical and p olitical justifications for this distinctive phenomeno n. 9 1 Most obviously, the possibility of op en co ntradiction serves to sharpen majority judgments. In addition, minority opinions provide the resources for future correction and reform of the law.9 2 This view o f the dissent is nicely captured by E.H. C arr’s co mments on progress generally. “Pregnant failures are not unknown in history. History recognizes what I may call “delayed” achievement: the apparent failures of to day may turn out to have made a vital contribution to the achievement of tomorro w - prophets born before their time.” 9 3 This quasi-religious language evokes the important political and moral dimension of dissent. Alder argues that in a liberal society, judges must be taken to have their own profound lyheld views on matters of ethical and political importance. Their rights as ordinary citizens demand that these views should not be suppressed. Furthermore, judges can be said to give utterance in their reasoning to the range of moral positions held in society. Thus, a move to single-judgmen t decisions would effectively stigmatize unorthod ox beliefs and disenfranchise their adherents. 9 4
86
Qu oted in S tein, supra note 83 at 98. The Mythology of Modern Law , supra note 82 at 93. 88 Stein, supra note 83 at 99. 89 Ibid . at 113. 90 M akin g of M ode rn B ritain , supra note 25 at 45. 91 J. Alder, “Dissents in Courts of Last Resort: Tragic Choices?” (2000) 20 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 221. 92 Ibid . at 241. 93 E.H . Carr, What is History?, 2d ed. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1987) at 128-29. 94 Alder, supra note 91 at 223. 87
144 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
VIII. The Ideological Uses of “Art” and “Science’ In the preceding discussion we have seen that ideas of art and science figure prominen tly in talk about medicine and law. It will have been clear that these ideas have been articulated in specific historical contexts. In this section we seek to reflect briefly upon these contexts and to investigate the role of professional rhetoric in the production and reproduction of social and o ccupational structures. Up to the 1960 s, socio logists tended to employ a so-called “trait ap proach” in their work on the professions. 9 5 Accordingly, professional status was read off from the possession of a list of essential attributes: for example, a code of ethics, selfregulation, altruism, etc.9 6 More recently this approach has been rejected b ecause of its uncritical reliance upon the self-definitions o f professional elites. 9 7 Instead, as was mentioned in the introduction to this essay, professiona lism has come to be understood in processual terms as the monopo lization of lucrative work through the creation of legally supported market shelters. 9 8 A structure of subordination is established whereby the successful occupational group closes off opportunities to outsiders defined as inferior and ineligible.9 9 How ever, the sinecures, thus created, are ende mically prone to usurpation by excluded groups and to d issolution by state or market forces.1 0 0 The groups ma king (and resisting) these challenges are obliged to engage in political and cultural work. As Murphy puts it, “[t]he structural fault of exclusion is the source of a m oral and ideological struggle to m ake tha t fault either obscure or transparent, legitimate or illegitimate.” 1 0 1 It is as part of this struggle that discourses of art and science are articulated in the occupational context. Talk of doctors as intrepid scientific researchers, or of common lawyers as exercising fine and irreducible judgment, serves to create common professional cultures, or pseudo -ethnicities,1 0 2 which increase the cohe sion and imp erme ability of the relevant occupational group. Beyond this, as Larson has shown, the distinctive ideas of art and science support occupational closure in specific ways. In so far as a practice is taken to be based on implicit, uncodifiable know ledge , it is impossible to subject it to precise regulation.1 0 3 In so far as it is held to display orderly, cumulative progress, it participates in the form of cognition dominant since
95 A.M . Carr Saunders & P.A . W ilson, The Professions (London: Frank C ass, 1933 ); H.M . Vollmer & D.L. M ills, Professionalisation (Englewood C liffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1966). 96 For further d iscuss ion, see B . Turn er, Medical Power and Social Knowledge, 2d ed. (London: Sage, 1995) 132. 97 The m ost searc hing critiqu e is to be fou nd in J ohns on, supra note 7. 98 G. Larkin , Occupational Monopoly and Modern Medicine (London: Tavistock, 1983 ). 99 W itz, supra note 8 at 40. 100 Parkin , supra note 7 at 75. 101 R. M urph y, Social Closure: The Theory of Monopolization and Exclusion (Oxford: Clarendon, 1988) at 48. 102 The phr ase a nd th e su ppo rting analysis are tak en from R. C ollins, Conflict Sociology: Toward an Explanatory Science (New York: Academic Press, 1975) at 87. 103 M.S. Larson, The Rise o f P ro fe ss io na lis m : A S ocio logic al A naly sis (Be rkeley: U niver sity of C aliforn ia Press, 1977) at 42.
Harrington # Art or Science? 145
the Enlightenment, and becomes, thereby, indispensable to the pursuit of the common good.1 0 4 The forego ing analysis is persuasive as far as it goes. However, it too has been criticized for failing to situate occupational exclusion within broader patterns of social subo rdination.1 0 5 Murphy provides us with a useful model in this regard. Drawing on Weber, he identifies legal title to private property as the principal form of exclusio n in society. 1 0 6 Invocation or enforcement of this title facilitates the accumulation of capital and the monopolization of opportunities on grounds of wealth. By contrast, the monopolies enjoyed by medical and legal practitioners are of a secondary nature, being predicated in the first instance upon legislative enactmen ts, rather than upon the rights of private property. 1 0 7 Both forms of exclusion are nonetheless linked in a reciprocal relationship.1 0 8 On the one hand, considerable barriers to entry into both professions mean that practitioners have traditionally been drawn disproportionately from the capital-owning classes. On the other hand, legal mo nopolies enable professiona ls to crea m off surplus we alth and, thus, to participate directly in the principal form of exclusion in society. There results, therefore, a convergence of interests between wealth-owning classes and self-employed p rofessionals. 1 0 9 Just like occ upational clo sure, broad er form s of do minatio n are subjec t to contestation and usurpation. The fault lines of social and economic exclusion are, thus, the focus of competing ideological explanations and bids for legitimacy. 1 1 0 It is in this connection that we can apprehend a hegemonic dimension to professional rhetoric, which transcend s its merely corporatist effects.1 1 1 In reflecting on their own practice, doctors and lawyers simultaneously function as conceptive ideologists, articulating the interests of the dominant classes and generalizing them as the interests of society as a whole.1 1 2 Thus, as well as creating their own pseudo-
104
Ibid . at 32. M . Cain, “The General Practice Lawyer and the Client: Towards a Radical Conception” in R. D ing wa ll & P . Lewis, e ds., The Sociology of the Professions: Lawyers, Doctors and Others (London: M acm illan, 1983 ) 106 at 108 . 106 M urph y, supra note 101 at 70. 107 Ibid . at 72. 108 Ibid . 109 It is important to d isting uis h b etw een th ose p rof essio na ls w ho are tra dition ally self-standing and those in salaried employment. The latter, far from being reliable class allies of the d om inan t grou p, ten d to support strategies of usurp ation against the principal form of exclusion. The role of teachers in leftist political movem ents is an important example of this: see ibid. at 173. 110 M . W eber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1922) at 635. 111 For a discu ssion of th is distinction, s ee R . Bellam y & D . Sch echter, Gramsci and the Italian State (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1993) at 130 112 K. M arx, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London: Lawrence and W ishart, 1976) at 60. For a d iscussion of this idea in relation to the legal profession, see M. C ain, “Gramsci, the State and the Place of Law” in D. S ugarm an, ed ., Leg ality, Id eolo gy a nd th e Sta te (London: Academic Press 1983) 95 at 97.
105
146 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
ethnicities, doctors and lawye rs have been significant contributors to elite culture.1 1 3 In this connection we part company with the notion that the ideas of the dominant classes are exclusively directed at subordinate classes in order to assure the consent of the latter to the orde r of things.1 1 4 A moment’s consideration of the restricted diffusion of the ideas of leading doctors, lawyers, philosophers, clerics, and so on, will bear out the limited possibilities for complete intellectual and moral domination of the working classes, particularly in the formative period of the nineteenth century. More nuanced acco unts sho w that elite culture also functions to sustain unity of purpose among members of the elite itself.1 1 5 We would argue, in fact, that the prima ry hegemon ic effect of talk about art and science has been to facilitate the creation and consolidation of a historic bloc between different fractions of capital in Britain over the last two ce nturies.1 1 6 In the early nineteenth century, British society was chara cterized by the emergence of an ind ustrial bourgeoisie which challenged the po litical and econ omic dominance of the old landed aristo cracy. 1 1 7 During this period the fault line between old and new wealth was a site of ideological contest, whose terms were also those of the parties to contemporary intra-professional struggles in medicine and law. Aristocratic wealth legitimated itself through a traditionalist ideology, which emphasized the imp licit, natural o rder of unequal social relations and the importance of custom and usage. It also sanctioned a web of regulatory and pro tective controls that tended to prevent the penetration of market forms of exchange and the unen cumbered acc umulation of capital. 1 1 8 The art model of medical and legal practice can easily be shown to participate in and contribute to this ideology. As has been seen, it justifies professional autonomy, and thus market restrictions, with reference to the tacit form of prac titioner knowledge and the ineffable traditions of the discipline. Th e emerging bourgeoisie legitimated its advances through an individualist and utilitarian philosophy, which was premised upon the formal equa lity of market relations, as ratified in the law o f contract. 1 1 9 According to this ideology, competitive pluralism was the chief engine of social and econo mic progress. 1 2 0 Again it is not difficult to dem onstrate the significant extent to which the science model of medicine and law drew upon and contributed
113 Making of M ode rn B ritain , supra note 25 at 57; P. Goodrich & Y. Hachamovitch, “Time out of Mind: An Intoduction to th e Sem iotics of the C om m on Law ” in P. F itzpatrick, ed ., Dangero us Supplements: Resistance and Renewal in Jurisprudence (London: Pluto, 1991) 167. 114 For a useful discussion, see P. Anderson, “The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci” (1976-77) 100 New Left Rev. 5 at 20. 115 N . Abe rcrom bie, S. H ill & B.S . Turn er, Th e D om inan t Ideo logy Th esis (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1980) at 6. 116 O n the im porta nce of ide ology in the creation of alliances between dom inan t grou ps, s ee A . Gr am sci, Quadern i del Carcere (Torino: Einaudi, 1977) at 1526. 117 For a general introduction, see A. Briggs, The Age of Improvement: 1783-1867 (London: Longman, 1979). 118 Abe rcrom bie, H ill & Turn er, supra note 115 at 96. 119 A. N orrie, “Pashukanis and the Com modity Form Theory: a Reply to Warrington” (1982) 10 Int’l J. Sociology of L. 429. 120 Abe rcrom bie, H ill & Turn er, supra note 115 at 97.
Harrington # Art or Science? 147
to this ideology. 1 2 1 A valorization of pluralism and a rejection of d ogm atic encumbrances has been shown above to be central to the scientific character of med icine and the comm on law. Thus, talk about medicine and law contributed to the ideologies of the two main groups within the ruling elite in Britain in the nine teenth century. T he variable emphases placed on either art or science, suggest both the contingency of professional formations and the uneasy nature of the historic co mpro mise between the aristocracy and the bourgeoisie. This measure of contingency has no t been fatal, however, either to professional or class-based supremacy. Ideologies of art and science would seem on the contrary to provide a means of expressing tensions while also co ntaining them. Indeed it has been noted that in the later nineteenth century the bourgeoisie underwent a process of gentrification, whereby it adopted much of the culture of the a ristocra cy. 1 2 2 At the same time the landed gentry absorbed much the individualist philosophy of the utilitarians. Trad itionalism became for them a peripheral, rather than a guiding ideology. 1 2 3 Equally in medicine, the art idea o f practice has taken on the role of a supplem entary discourse which aims at refining and humanizing the now dominant scientific mode. T he idea of legal knowledge as tacit and ineffable has also been dislodged by a flood of highly detailed statute law. The recent incorporation of the European Convention on Human Rights furthers this trend toward codification (however unsystematic) of British law. 1 2 4 Nonetheless the common law remains at the idealized core of the legal system in the curricula of British law schools and in the texts of scholars and judges. 1 2 5 Tra dition, it see ms, rem ains an indispe nsable legitimating device.
IX. Conclusion This essay originated in a conc ern to e xplain the extremely favourable liab ility regime to which doctors are subject under English law. The attempt to do so led us to consider the interaction be tween med icine and law, not from the familiar perspective of philosophical ethics, but from that of epistemology. To be m ore precise, we examine d historical evidenc e of what doc tors and lawyers say about what they do. This revealed a largely shared set of self-understandings structured around a distinction between art and science. An ideal-typical reconstruction of the poles of this distinction was possible through a consideration of work on the philosophy of knowledge. The idea of medicine and law as an art was seen to rest on a view of knowledge as implicit or tacit in its pristine form, and on a ratification of tradition as the ultimate sou rce of authority in practice. The idea of medicine and
121
A qua lified in divid ualism also str uctu res th e En glish law on in formed consent, see J. Harrington, “Privileging the Medical Norm: Liberalism, Self-Determination and Refusal of Treatment” (1996) 16 Legal Stud. 348. 122 Abe rcrom bie, H ill & Turn er, supra note 115 at 106. 123 Ibid . at 107. 124 Loughlin, supra note 49. 125 Good rich & Ha cham ovitch, supra note 113.
148 Health Law Journal Vol.9, 2001
law as a science rested on a view of knowledge developing incrementally through vigorous conflicts of opinion. Pluralism and the toleration of pluralism were integral to this view of science. Finally, we noted the important ideological effects of this talk about the nature of professional knowledge and practice. It was argued that doctors and lawye rs, in theorizing their own work, functioned as conceptive ideologists on two planes. Elaboration and reiteration of the art-science distinction served both to bolster professional monopo lies and to solidify alliances between the dominant classes in British society. W e suggested that there was a significant tension between tradition and pro gress in the professional and political discourses examined. This tension is nicely captured in the following comment of Michael Polanyi: Can we face the fact that no matter how liberal a free society may b e, it is also profoundly conservative. For th is is the fact. The recognition granted in a free society to the independent growth of science, art and morality, involve s a dedicatio n of society to the fostering of a specific tradition of thought, transmitted and cultivated by a particular group of authoritative specialists, perpetuating themselves by co-option. To upho ld the independence of thought implemented by such a society is to subscribe to a kind of orthodoxy which, though it specifies no fixed articles of faith, is virtually unassailable within the limits imposed on the process of innova tion by the cultura l leadership o f a free society. 1 2 6 In sum, the rhetoric of art and science reflects both the reality and the contingency of structures of dominance and inequality at work and in society at large.
126
Polanyi, supra note 44 at 244.