1 Argumentative polylogues in a dialectical framework

29 downloads 0 Views 382KB Size Report
and evaluation miss important aspects of argumentative polylogues. ...... 15 а“Even if the principle а'No common logic, no communication' held, it would not ...
Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Argumentative  polylogues  in  a  dialectical  framework:  A  methodological  inquiry   Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M.

1.  Research  problem   Our  chief  concern  in  this  paper  is  with  the  analysis  and  evaluation  of  argumentation  in   multi-­‐party  discussions  (polyogues).  Complex  multi-­‐party  discussions,  as  opposed  to   simple  two-­‐party  encounters,  are  a  familiar  and  ordinary  argumentative  phenomenon.   They  arise  whenever  different  speakers  take  up  and  discuss  more  than  two  positions   (standpoints)  at  a  time  –  an  event  instigated,  for  instance,  by  an  open  Wh-­‐question   (Who  should  become  the  professor  of  the  year?  How  to  help  Greece?  Which  wine  should   we  drink  first?).  Answers  to  such  questions  typically  form  a  set  of  multiple  contrary   positions  on  an  issue:  they  can  then  be  critically  examined  to  judge  which  one  of  them  is   “correct”  or  “best.”  While  such  multi-­‐party  and  multi-­‐position  discussions  are   characteristic  of  a  large  class  of  argumentative  activities,  especially  of  a  deliberative   type,  in  argumentation  theory  they  are  typically  analyzed  and  evaluated  with  the  help  of   dialectical  models.  Such  models  theorize  argumentation  as  a  dyadic  exchange  between   two  and  only  two  parties  (such  as  protagonist  and  antagonist  or  proponent  and   opponent)  who  take  up  only  two  basic  positions  (such  as  pro  and  con  or  agree  and   doubt).  We  will  explore  the  problem  dyadic  assumptions  pose  for  adequate   argumentative  analysis  by  scrutinizing  how  extant  methods  of  dialectical  reconstruction   and  evaluation  miss  important  aspects  of  argumentative  polylogues.  We  aim  to  reveal   some  challenges  to  such  methods  and  suggest  possible  improvements  that  pave  the  way   for  conceptualizing  a  polylogical  model  of  argumentative  discussion.         Our  main  research  problem  is,  accordingly,  this:  How  do  the  complexities  of   multi-­‐party  argumentative  discussions  (polylogues)  affect  the  capacity  for  the  analysis   and  the  conditions  for  evaluation  of  argument  through  dialectical  models?  The  question   of  the  analysis  and  evaluation  of  polyogues  brings  about  too  many  fundamental  issues   to  be  dealt  in  one  paper.  Therefore,  we  will  focus  on  the  following  research  question:   What  options  for  analyzing  and  evaluating  argumentative  polylogues  do  extant   dialectical  models  offer  and  why  are  they  limited  (section  3)?  On  the  basis  of  this  critical   inquiry,  we  hope  to  lay  out  a  tentative  argument  expressing  the  need  for  an  improved   model,  suggesting  some  rudimentary  elements  of  the  model  (section  4).1  As  an   illustration  of  the  issues  discussed  we  will  use  an  example  of  a  university  committee   arguing  over  the  “researcher  of  the  year”  prize  (section  2).  This  example  is  a  case  of   1   We   only   discuss   here   the   dialectical   approach   to   analyzing   and   evaluating   argumentative   polylogues.  

There   are   of   course   other   perspectives   investigating   argumentative   (rhetoric,   logic)   or   some   other   aspect   of  rationality  in  collective  decision-­‐making  (decision  theory,  social  choice  theory,  game  theory,  etc.).  We   notice   though,   that   while   they   have   much   to   recommend,   none   of   them   focuses   on   the   analysis   and   evaluation  of  argumentation  qua  interaction  to  the  extent  that  dialectical  approaches  do.  

1    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

practical  reasoning  in  the  common  context  of  multi-­‐party  deliberation  where  the   governing  question  –  “What  to  do?”  –  concerns  future  actions.  However,  we  believe  that   our  point  is  generalizable  to  cases  of  theoretical  reasoning  in  other  contexts  in  which   the  truth-­‐related  question  of  “What  is  the  case?”  is  discussed;  for  instance:  What  is  the   mass  of  the  new  asteroid?  How  many  bottles  of  wine  did  we  drink  last  night?  To  such   questions,  many  competing  responses  (positions,  hypotheses)  may  too  be  formed  and   discussed  in  an  argumentative  polylogue.  That  is  to  say,  while  for  the  purposes  at  hand   we  work  through  a  specific  example  and  type  of  deliberation,  we  see  a  broader   relevance  of  our  investigations  to  argumentation  theory.             2.  Who’s  the  best  professor?       To  provide  a  place  to  start,  consider  the  following  example  of  a  committee  meeting   within  a  university’s  school.  The  example  is  constructed  so  as  to  allow  us  to  focus  on  the   aspects  of  the  committee’s  argumentation  that  are  relevant  to  our  inquiry  and  yet  are   real  concerns  of  a  deliberating  group.  The  committee  meets  to  decide  whom  to  award   the  annual  best  researcher  prize,  for  which  only  one  faculty  member  can  be  selected.   Prior  to  the  meeting,  in  accordance  with  the  school  procedures,  three  nominations  have   been  officially  proposed  by  the  school’s  faculty.  Each  candidate  comes  from  a  different   department  of  the  school  that  comprises  of  five  departments;  two  of  the  departments   are  thus  not  represented  in  the  nominations.  Five  faculty  members  -­‐-­‐  one  per   department  -­‐-­‐  take  part  in  the  meeting,  which  is  presided  over  by  a  chair  whose  sole   role  is  to  manage  the  meeting  rather  than  actively  contribute  to  the  discussion  of  the   candidates.  Following  the  procedures,  before  the  meeting  the  committee  members  were   given  the  portfolio  (updated  CV,  recent  publications,  grants  awarded,  etc.)  of  the  three   nominees  in  order  to  come  prepared  to  the  meeting  and  advocate  for  one  chosen   candidate.  Each  committee  member  is  expected  to  support  only  one  candidate,  but  one   candidate  may  be  supported  by  more  than  one  member.  Committee  members  are  free   to  change  their  support  based  on  the  committee  discussion.  It  is  customary  in  the  school   to  make  such  decisions  on  the  basis  of  arguments  and  criticisms  traded  during  the   meeting  rather  than  using  the  meeting  as  a  stage  for  rubber-­‐stamping  deals  struck   beforehand  behind  the  scenes.  It  is  also  acceptable  for  the  committee  to  decide  that  no   award  can  be  given  that  year  but  it  is  not  acceptable  to  give  more  than  one  award.   At  the  beginning  of  the  meeting,  the  chair  invites  each  committee  member  to   make  a  case  for  a  selected  candidate  –  a  short  piece  of  argumentative  discourse  in  which   the  merits  of  a  given  candidate,  as  compared  to  the  remaining  two,  are  argued  for.  After   each  member’s  presentation,  it  becomes  evident  that  faculty  members  A  and  B  support   candidate  α,  member  C  supports  candidate  β,  and  members  D  and  E  support  candidate   γ.  Having  argued  for  their  preferred  researcher  of  the  year,  they  are  expected  to   convince  the  remaining  members  of  the  committee  that  their  candidate  deserves  the   award  more  than  the  others.    The  committee  members  are  of  course  free  to  eventually   change  their  position  (some  indeed  have  to  do  it  for  a  decision  to  be  taken).  To  this  end,   2    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

arguments  are  traded  for  and  against  the  three  candidates,  as  each  committee  member   makes  a  case  for  their  professor  in  an  ordered  sequence  overlooked  by  the  chair.  The   ultimate  goal  is  for  the  committee  members  to  converge  on  the  decision  on  meritorious   grounds.  That  means  that  the  final  decision  is  not  taken  as  a  result  of  a  simple  majority   voting,  but  rather  on  the  basis  of  a  consensus,  at  least  in  the  form  of  “reluctant   adherence”  of  those  who  ran  out  of  arguments,  of  all  the  members  over  the  best   researcher  of  the  year.2   An  argumentative  situation  after  the  committee  members’  presentations  is  as   follows: Issue:

Who  should  receive  the  best  researcher  award  of   2012/2013?

Positions  on  the  issue:

Candidate/Position  1:   Candidate/Position  2: Candidate/Position  3:

Prof.  α Prof.  β   Prof.  γ    

(A  and  B) (C) (D  and  E)

It  is  worth  noting  that  α,  β,  and  γ  are  logically  speaking  contrary  positions  -­‐-­‐  the  “truth”   of  one  of  them  entails  the  “falsity”  of  the  remaining  ones,  however  the  “falsity”  of  one  of   them  does  not  entail  the  “truth”  of  the  other  (as  would  be  the  case  with  contradictory   positions)  (see  Author1,  2013).3  So  for  instance  selecting  Prof.  α  excludes  the  two   remaining  candidates,  but  dropping  her  does  not  amount  to  selecting  Prof.  β  or  Prof.  γ   (only  one  of  them  can  be  selected,  and  the  committee  still  has  to  decide  between  the   two;  also,  there  is  an  option  of  not  awarding  the  prize  at  all).  This  makes  the   deliberation  in  question  a  decision-­‐making  activity  in  which  positions  are  clearly   defined  and  explicitly  advocated  by  a  given  party,  and  the  goal  is  to  select,  upon  critical   examination,  one  of  these  positions.  There  are  thus  “winners”  and  “losers”.  This  stands   in  contrast  to  other  forms  of  multi-­‐party  argumentation,  such  as  for  instance  in  open-­‐ problem  tasks  where  positions  are  not  attached  to  the  speakers  all  along  and  the  goal  is   to  collectively  “construct”  a  solution  that  would  best  satisfy  the  arguers’  critical   judgment.  In  this  case,  there  are  not  necessarily  “winners”  and  “loser”,  since,  ideally,  the   end-­‐result  satisfies  everybody  or,  as  the  case  may  be  in  real  circumstances,  nobody.4   Despite  five  actual  conversational  participants  (see  the  pentagon  in  Figure  1),  we   thus  have  three  argumentative  parties  advocating  three  standpoints,  since  A  and  B   converge  in  their  support  of  Prof.  α  and  D  and  E  in  their  support  of  Prof.  γ.  Thus,  during   2   Exactly   how   they   start   the   discussion   is   a   secondary   concern   for   our   present   purposes   as   ultimately   whether   they   come   in   with   established   position   or   develop   positions   in   the   course   of   the   conversation,   they  still  must  end  up  at  a  single  choice  based  on  their  argumentative  discussion  of  the  options.   3  Since  we  speak  here  of  actions  to  be  taken  (whom  to  award  a  prize)  rather  than  beliefs  in  the  strict  sense,  

we   put   the   belief-­‐related   terms   such   as   truth   and   falsity   in   inverted   commas.   Of   course,   the   decision   to   select  a  given  candidate  is,  ideally,  grounded  in  a  belief  that  this  is  indeed  the  best  researcher.   4   See   Author

1,   forth.,   for   a   distinction   between  role-­‐based   dialectics,   where   arguers   take   up   the   roles   of   the   proponents   and   opponents   of   given   positions,   and  issue-­‐based   dialectics,   where   arguers   examine   the   pros   and  cons  of  a  given  issue  without  making  their  case  for  a  selected  position  on  the  issue.  

3    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

the  initial  portions  of  the  meeting,  at  least,  each  of  the  argumentative  parties  (whether   made  up  of  a  team  or  an  individual)  is  a  proponent  of  one  of  the  three  contrary   positions  (α,  β,  γ),  and  at  the  same  time  an  opponent  of  the  two  remaining  ones.  They   are  expected  to  argue  for  their  position/candidate  and  against  the  two  remaining   positions/candidates  since  only  one  award  can  be  given.  Each  proponent  has  thus  two   opponents  who,  in  turn,  are  opponents  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  each  other  (Figure  1). Figure  1  –  “Triangulated”  argumentative  discussion  with  3  distinct  parties  supporting  3  contrary   positions:  conversational  situation  and  argumentative  situation.

This  type  of  small  group  deliberation,  despite  its  apparent  simplicity,  generates  a   rather  complex  argumentative  discussion  that  we  will  use  as  a  basis  for  our   methodological  inquiry  into  the  analytic  tools  offered  by  the  extant  dialectical  models  of   argumentation.  The  case  is  on  face  value  representative  of  many  kinds  of  everyday   argumentative  encounters  and  thus  we  also  draw  upon  examples  taken  from  others’   work  in  argumentation  analysis  to  further  illustrate  and  examine  the  implications  of  the   position  we  develop  here.  We  can  also  imagine  many  variations  to  the  example,  but  our   aim  is  to  start  from  a  simple  exemplary  case  from  which  relevant,  important  variations   can  be  taken  up  in  due  course.     3.  Dialectical  understanding  of  polylogues   3.1  Analyzing  argumentation  in  a  dialectical  framework The  guiding  two-­‐fold  question  of  this  section  is:  How  would  dialectical  analysis  treat   polylogues  where  multiple  positions  are  advanced  and  developed  through  multi-­‐party   discussion  and  with  what  consequence  for  evaluating  argument?  Before  we  set  off  to   4    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

answer  this  question,  we  need  to  clarify  what  we  understand  by  “dialectical  analysis”.  It   is  a  largely  procedural  form  of  analysis  of  actual  argumentative  discourse  that   approaches  all  varieties  of  argumentation  -­‐-­‐  mono-­‐logical,  di-­‐logical,  poly-­‐logical  -­‐-­‐  as  a   more  or  less  straightforward  instantiation  of  a  dyadic  dialogical  exchange  between  the   arguing  party  (protagonist,  proponent)  and  the  critiquing  party  (antagonist,   opponent).5  The  goal  of  dialectical  analysis  is  to  render  the  structure  of  argumentative   exchanges  in  dialectical  terms  (i.e.,  as  moves  in  a  dyadic  exchange  of  pros  and  cons)  and   subsequently  evaluate  them  by  a  comparison  to  a  set  of  rules  stipulated  for  idealized   models  of  dialectical  discussion  (Hamblin,  1970;  Rescher,  1977;  van  Eemeren  &   Grootendorst,  1984,  1992,  2004;  Walton,  1984,  1998;  Walton  &  Krabbe,  1995).   Interestingly,  while  dialectic  is  by  definition  an  approach  to  studying  and   practicing  argumentative  interactions  (e.g.,  Krabbe,  2000),  some  most  prominent   dialectical  approaches  have  relied  heavily  on  static  methods  of  argument  analysis  (see   analytic  overviews  in  pragma-­‐dialectics  or  argumentation  schemes  in  Walton’s  dialectics)   that  basically  lay  out  the  monological  structure  of  arguments  put  forth  by  one  of  the   parties.6  By  contrast,  in  the  following  we  consider  what  we  think  is  the  gist  of  dialectical   analysis,  that  is,  a  method  of  approaching  the  argumentative  aspect  of  conversation  that   is  dynamic  while  retaining  the  normative  aim  of  evaluation.  Profiles  of  dialogue  used  by   Walton  (1999)  and  Krabbe  (1999)  and  dialectical  profiles  used  by  pragma-­‐dialecticians   (van  Eemeren,  Houtlosser,  &  Snoeck  Henkemans,  2007)  are  two  examples  of  methods   that  very  well  fulfill  the  requirements  of  rational  dialectical  reconstruction  of  the   dynamics  of  argumentative  dialogues  in  a  step-­‐by-­‐step  fashion.  The  profiles  are   primarily  normative  constructs  which  spell  out  the  moves  in  ideal  dialectical  models   such  as  pragma-­‐dialectical  critical  discussion.  Therefore,  the  dialectical  sequences  in  the   profiles  are  modeled  as  neat  two-­‐party  interactions  with  simple  dyadic  turn-­‐taking  (A-­‐ B-­‐A-­‐B)  between  the  proponent  (protagonist)  and  opponent  (antagonist).  This,  of  course,   is  an  element  of  the  idealization  inscribed  in  the  profiles.  Some  difficulties,  however,   may  arise  when  the  profiles  serve  a  heuristic  function,  that  is,  when  they  are  used  to   reconstruct  and  evaluate  actual  argumentative  exchanges  as  more  or  less  imperfect   instantiations  of  the  idealized  dialectical  sequences.  One  such  difficulty  is  how  to  mold  a   complex  multi-­‐party  interaction  into  a  dyadic  dialectical  profile.   Taking  this  specification  into  account,  we  recognize  two  basic  ways  in  which  a   multi-­‐party  and  multi-­‐position  argumentative  polylogue  such  as  our  committee  meeting   can  be  analyzed  dialectically.  We  identify  different  variants  of  these  two  basic  ways  and   5  A  di-­‐logue  in  which  two  parties  trade  arguments  and  criticisms  is  a  paradigmatic  object  for  dialectical   analysis.  However,  monological  reasoning  can  be  also  reconstructed  as  an  internal  critical  dialogue  (e.g.,   Blair,   1998;   Jacquette,   2007;   Johnson,   2000).   The   possibilities   and   perils   of   dialectically   reconstructing   polylogues  will  be  discussed  in  the  remainder  of  the  paper.   6   Walton’s   framework   of   different   dialectical   dialogue   types   allows   for   a   dynamic   dialogical   analysis   of   the  

entire  procedure  of  activities  such  as  deliberation;  but  such  analyses  take  into  account  all  communicative   aspects   of   deliberation   (proposal   making,   bargaining,   preference   aggregation,   voting),   rather   than   the   strictly  argumentative  exchange  of  reasons  and  criticisms  (Walton,  1998,  Ch.  6;  McBurney,  Hitchcock,  &   Parsons,  2007;  Rehg,  McBurney,  &  Parsons,  2005).  

5    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

discuss  the  shortcomings  of  such  an  orientation  for  grasping  the  nature  of  polylogue   and  its  reconstruction  for  argument  analysis. 3.2  Polylogue  as  argumentation  between  two  basic  camps The  first  option  is  to  reduce  the  multiplicity  of  positions  argued  for  and  against  to  two   basic  camps.  This  method  would  seek  to  interpret  any  discussion  involving  multiple   parties  and  multiple  positions  as  an  essentially  dyadic  encounter  revolving  around  two   dominant  poles.  The  argumentative  and  conversational  status  of  those  who  do  not   easily  fit  into  the  bi-­‐polar  division  would  be  demoted  to  the  one  of  third  parties,   secondary  addressees,  uninvolved  bystanders,  or  simply  undifferentiated  members   composing  “the  other”  or  “the  audience.”   The  reduction  of  an  argumentative  polylogue  to  two  main  opponents  can  be   justified  on  a  number  of  grounds.  The  crudest  form  of  justification  seems  to  be   theoretical  stipulation,  such  as  in  formal  dialectical  models.  For  instance,  Prakken,  in  his   formalization  of  a  “persuasion  dialogue”,  takes  into  account  only  one  proponent  and  one   opponent  and  proposes  that  “[t]he  remaining  participants,  if  any,  are  the  third  parties   with  respect  to  [a  thesis]  t,  assumed  to  be  neutral  towards  t”  (2009,  p.  286).  There  is   thus  nothing  else  left  to  analyze  but  t  vs.  t?  and  t  vs.  ¬t  dialogues,  because  in  a  dialectical   sense  “third  parties”  are  neither  parties  (they  do  not  participate  in  a  persuasion   dialogue  by  making  or  doubting  a  case)  nor  third  (they  cannot  offer  any  alternatives).   Such  formalization  does  not,  however,  apply  to  cases  like  our  committee  meeting.  While   its  chairman  is  by  institutional  definition  a  “neutral  third  party”,  we  are  still  left  with   three  other  parties  each  of  them  having  a  contrasting  opinion  with  respect  to  a   proposition  of  who  should  be  given  the  title  of  the  best  researcher.         In  contrast  to  such  theoretical  fiats,  empirically  oriented  dialectical  analysts  have   marshaled  factual  evidence  for  excluding  some  “third  parties”.  For  instance,  Salmon  and   Zeitz  note  regarding  the  argumentative  conversations  they  examine:  “Although  more   than  two  persons  are  participants  in  the  conversation,  usually  two  of  them  are  engaged   in  a  dialogue  while  the  third  participates  only  incidentally.  At  different  points  in  the   conversation,  different  participants  play  the  role  of  the  ‘third’”  (1995,  p.  14).  Therefore,   in  their  method  of  representing  argumentative  exchanges,  Salmon  and  Zeitz  (1995)   render  multi-­‐party  discussions  as  di-­‐logues  held  predominantly  between  arguers  B  and   C,  with  occasional  or  no  contributions  from  the  taciturn  arguer  symbolized  by  A.  A   similar  solution  is  adopted  by  van  Rees:  “In  the  fragment  which  is  analysed  below,  most   of  the  conversation  takes  place  between  A  and  B.  C  makes  the  occasional  contribution.  D   is  the  secretary  to  the  hospital  management  and  rarely  speaks.  When  he  does  so,  it  is   usually  to  express  support  for  A”  (1995,  p.  346).  Accordingly,  van  Rees’s  dialectical   analysis  focuses  on  the  argumentative  exchanges  between  A  and  B,  largely  glossing  over   the  other  participants’  “occasional  contributions”.  In  such  empirical  analyses,  the   reconstruction  of  multi-­‐participant  speech  events  as  dyadic  dialectical  exchanges  is   justified  on  purely  observational,  conversational  grounds.  Some  participants  are  simply   outtalked  or  virtually  “left  out”  by  the  two  dominant  ones,  a  distinct  regularity   6    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

mentioned  already  by  early  conversation  analysts  (Sacks,  Schegloff,  &  Jefferson,  1974,  p.   712).       All  the  same,  van  Rees’s  (1995)  in-­‐depth  analysis  of  a  “problem-­‐solving   discussion”  over  a  possible  merger  of  two  local  hospitals  in  the  Netherlands,  includes   some  instances  of  multi-­‐party  argumentation.  Despite  van  Rees’s  largely  dyadic  analysis   of  argumentation  between  participants  A  and  B,  the  occasional  contributor  C  does   interfere  at  points  trying  to  argue  his  own  case,  different  from  both  A’s  and  B’s.  This   breaks  the  basic  dyadic  dynamics  of  A-­‐B-­‐A-­‐B  exchanges:  “a  misunderstanding  about  the   relevance  of  B’s  contribution  develops:  B  intends  it  as  a  return  to  his  own  point,  while  A   treats  it  as  support  for  C.  They  are  talking  at  cross  purposes.”  (1995,  p.  356).  For  this   reason,  in  van  Rees’s  view,  A’s  move  to  engage  the  relatively  taciturn  C  rather  than   argue  just  with  B  suffers  from  irrelevance,  a  major  source  of  dialectical  fallaciousness   (Walton,  2004).  But  this  irrelevance  cannot  be  adequately  accounted  for  without  a   reference  to  a  third  party  (C).  A  is  not  simply  irrelevant,  and  thus  fallacious,  in  a  dyadic   dialectical  encounter  with  B.  He  commits  an  alleged  fallacy  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  B’s  argument  in  the   context  of,  and  because  of,  C’s  argumentative  move  that  is  a  relevant  and  legitimate   contribution  to  the  current  discussion.7  (A  is  not  merely  distracted  by  a  bird  or  a   notable  passer-­‐by.)  A’s  irrelevance  thus  possibly  lies  in  the  eyes  of  the  beholder  focused   entirely  on  the  dyadic  exchange  between  him  and  B.  Therefore,  with  different  eyes   which  take  C’s  arguments  into  view,  we  may  reconsider  A’s  retort  as  an  argumentatively   reasonable  thing  to  do.  In  sum,  some  important  considerations  go  amiss  in  a  neatly   dyadic  analysis  focused  (primarily  or  even  exclusively)  on  the  discussion  between  A  and   B.  In  this  and  similar  instances,  we  can  thus  speak  of  argumentative  moves  that  are   apparently  unreasonable  on  dialectical  grounds  but  reasonable  in  a  polylogue.     Van  Rees’s  study,  however,  also  reveals  a  different  possibility,  that  of  one   participant  “expressing  support”  for  another  one  (1995,  p.  346).  This  conversational   phenomenon  has  been  well  analyzed  under  the  label  of  a  “tag-­‐team  argument”  (Canary,   Brossmann,  &  Seibold,  1987;  Brashers  &  Meyers,  1989)  or  “argumentative  coalitions”  in   conversational  polylogues  (Bruxelles  &  Kerbrat-­‐Orecchionni,  2004).  Argumentation   teams  or  coalitions  are  formed  whenever  a  group  of  participants  gather  behind  a   position  they  favor,  and  consistently  co-­‐produce  various  arguments  for  that  position   (and  against  the  opposing  one),  in  effect  mutually  supporting  each  other.  Noticeably,  the   experimental  research  design  and  general  framework  for  analyzing  argumentation   within  and  between  tag-­‐teams  is  characteristically  limited  to  but  two  positions  on  an   issue,  such  as  a  risky  vs.  conservative  solution  to  a  choice  dilemma,  each  of  which  is   supported  by  one  of  the  two  sub-­‐groups  confronting  each  other  (Brashers  &  Meyers,   1989).  For  instance,  out  of  five  arguers,  two  are  assigned  a  risky  option  and  are  set   against  three  who  are  assigned  a  conservative  one.  Thus,  again,  we  obtain  two   argumentative  parties  out  of  a  number  of  conversational  participants.   This  mode  of  analysis  also  leads  to  difficulties  in  some  “uncontrolled”  natural   contexts  of  argumentation.  To  take  but  one  example:  Author1  (2010)  analyzed  the   7  See  van  Rees’s  (1995)  study  for  the  transcripts  of  entire  exchanges  and  her  detailed  analysis.    

7    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

pattern  of  collective  criticism  (collective  antagonist)  in  online  political  discussions.   While  the  collective  antagonist  seems  to  be  a  mere  counter-­‐part  of  the  tag-­‐team   (collective  protagonist),  there  are  important  differences  between  the  two,  one  of  them   crucial  in  the  context  of  a  polylogue.  Tag-­‐teams  are  by  definition  clearly  demarcated   groups  that  consistently  co-­‐produce  arguments  for  one  position,  whereas  collective   antagonist  “is  collective  only  in  the  sense  of  the  object  of  criticism”,  because  arguers  that   engage  in  collective  criticism  “do  not  seem  to  be  jointly  defending  any  one  consistent   position”  (2010,  p.  95).  For  instance,  Republican  critics  of  Barack  Obama’s  tax  policies,   are,  quite  unsurprisingly,  consistently  challenged  by  the  supporters  of  the  Democratic   agenda,  but  also,  less  expectedly,  by  advocates  of  “the  third  way”  in  American  politics   who  are  critical  of  both  Republican  fiscal  conservatism  and  Obama’s  tax  plans,  because   “the  Dems  and  the  GOP  [the  Republicans]  are  two  sides  of  the  same  coin”  (op.  cit.,  p.  92).   Hence,  critics  of  the  GOP  from  the  Democratic  position  are  “united”  with  the  third-­‐way   advocates  only  temporarily  as  critics,  but  quickly  disagree  with  them  when   argumentation  in  support  of  Obama  is  to  be  put  forth.  They  thus  never  create  a  tag-­‐team   that  can  be  approached  as  one  dialectical  party  with  a  consistent  commitment  set  (see   Walton  &  Krabbe,  1995).  Again,  even  when  taking  collectivities  of  arguers  into  account,   we  face  three  (or  perhaps  more)  distinct  positions  that  must  not  be  analytically  merged   and  conflated.     Beyond  such  empirical  studies,  a  bi-­‐partisan  divide  can  be  justified  on  analytic   grounds  whenever  the  multiplicity  of  positions  is  merely  apparent.  This  happens,  for   instance,  when  different  positions  are  variants  of  some  overarching  position  or  when   they  are  compatible  and  can  be  merged  into  one.  Moreover,  depending  on  the  level  of   generality  of  the  contested  issue  around  which  a  dispute  revolves,  some  in-­‐group   differences  of  opinion  can  be  reconciled  or  swept  away  as  insignificant  nuances  when   facing  the  challenge  from  the  out-­‐group.  In  this  way,  two  dominant,  opposing  sides  to   the  issue  emerge.  (Think  of  how  some  well-­‐known  divisions  within  political  parties,   such  as  American  Republicans  or  Russian  Bolsheviks,  fade  into  the  background  once  the   big  antagonist,  the  Democrats  or  the  Tsarists,  is  to  be  opposed.) Another  solution  to  dualize  the  multiplicity  of  parties  is  to  follow  rhetoricians,   who  typically  analyze  any  multi-­‐party  discussion  as  though  arguers  were  rhetors   persuading  diverse  audience.8  The  basic  framework  for  rhetorical  analysis  is  a  dyad   consisting  of  the  speaker  and  the  audience  she  is  addressing.  When  the  speaker   confronts  the  audience  which  cannot  be  taken  to  be  a  monolithic  group,  but  is  for   instance  divided  into  “several  organized  factions”    (Perelman  &  Olbrechts-­‐Tyteca,   1958/1969,  p.  22),  the  rhetorical  analyst  can  preserve  the  duality  by  approaching  the   speaker  as  an  arguer  that:  builds  multiple  argumentation  consisting  of  individual  lines   of  reasoning  catered  to  different  parts  of  the  audience  (op.  cit.,  p.  21-­‐22;  van  Rees,   8  

Perelman   &   Olbrechts-­‐Tyteca   (1958/1969)   use   the   term   “composite   audience”;   Zarefsky   (2008)   “heterogeneous   audience”;   van   Eemeren   (2010,   p.   110)   distinguishes   between   “multiple”   audience   (“consisting   of   individuals   or   subgroups   having   different   positions   in   the   difference   of   opinion”)   and   “mixed”  audience  (“consisting  of  individuals  or  subgroups  having  different  starting  points”).  

8    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

2003);  addresses  a  universal  audience  whose  concerns  raise  above  the  particularities  of   concrete  factions  (Perelman  &  Olbrechts-­‐Tyteca,  1958/1969,  pp.  31ff);  or  at  least   attempts  to  persuade  a  primary  audience,  the  chief  target  of  the  speaker’s  arguments,  to   which  the  other  parts  of  the  audience  are  mere  conduits,  or  secondary  audiences  (van   Eemeren,  2010,  pp.  108-­‐109).     Rhetorical  concepts,  such  as  composite  or  heterogeneous  audience,  work  well  for   understanding  the  complexities  of  the  rhetorical  situation  in  which  a  speaker  needs  to   meet  multiple,  and  sometimes  conflicting,  demands  if  her  or  his  speech  is  to  be   successful  with  the  addressees.  However,  our  focus  here  is  on  the  dialectical  rather  than   rhetorical  analysis  and  evaluation  of  argumentation.  Indeed,  when  argumentation  is   reconstructed  as  interaction  rather  than  one-­‐way  public  speaking  -­‐-­‐  which  marks  a   significant  difference  between  dialectical  and  rhetorical  study  of  argumentation  (e.g.,   Krabbe,  2000;  Blair,  2012)  -­‐-­‐  the  rhetorical  concepts  (such  as  “audience”)  do  not  neatly   correspond  to  the  dialectical  ones  (such  as  “antagonist”).  Zarefsky,  who  provides   insightful  analyses  of  the  ways  a  heterogeneous  audience  can  be  handled  in  political   oratory,  cautions  that:     If  one  were  to  imagine  the  audience  as  simulating  the  antagonist  in  a  dialogue,  then  one  would   have  to  say  that  the  antagonist  is  schizophrenic  or  has  multiple  personalities.  Yet  the  arguer  often   tries  to  appeal  to  these  multiple  personalities  at  the  same  time.  (Zarefsky,  2008,  p.  320)            

The  antagonist’s  “schizophrenia”  an  arguer  may  encounter  in  multi-­‐party  discussions   affects,  prominently,  the  basic  dialectical  requirements  of  consistency  and  relevance.   Examples  of  this  are  plentiful  (e.g.,  Bonevac,  2003;  Perelman  &  Olbrechts-­‐Tyteca,   1958/1969,  p.  31).  Author1  (2012)  analyzes  a  case  of  a  centrist  European  government   which  must  convince  some  of  the  opposition  parties  to  support  further  austerity   measures.  It  seems  to  be  a  straightforward  case  of  a  protagonist  (government)  vs.   antagonist  (opposition)  debate,  nicely  suitable  for  dialectical  analysis  and  evaluation.   But  the  opposition  parties  are  divided:  leftists  criticize  the  proposal  for  being  too   unresponsive  to  the  needs  of  the  poor,  while  conservatives  argue  it  curbs  far  too  much   the  entrepreneurial  spirit  of  able  businessmen.  The  government  defends  the  proposal   with  what  seem  like  well-­‐justified  arguments,  but  what  is  relevant  and  convincing  for   the  leftists  hardly  strikes  a  chord  with  the  conservatives  (and  the  other  way  round).  So   the  government  faces  the  following  predicament.  It  can  either  focus  exclusively  on  a   dialectical  discussion  with  but  one  of  the  opposition  parties,  thus  avoiding  the  burden  of   proof  against  criticisms  of  the  other  opposition  party;  or,  it  can  try  to  be  simultaneously   responsive  to  both  parties’  concerns,  thus  possibly  getting  itself  into  uncomfortable   inconsistencies  (e.g.,  “we  are  diverting  rich  people’s  taxes  to  alleviate  the  poor”  and  “we   are  not  overtaxing  the  rich”).  Straightforward  dialectical  evaluations  of  such  activities   are  hard.     Finally,  an  argument  critic  can  analyze  any  multiparty  discussion  as  though   involving  third  parties  that  play  an  auxiliary  role  in  argumentation.  There  are  various   kinds  of  roles  that  can  be  taken  up  in  collective  situations:  the  judge,  chair,  facilitator,   9    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

moderator,  mediator,  etc.  From  a  dialectical  view,  these  different  roles  are  all  versions   of  third-­‐parties  to  a  discussion  and  are  (expected  to  be)  dialectically  neutral  in  the  sense   that  while  their  function  is  to  shape  or  overlook  the  activity  of  argumentation,  they  are   in  principle  not  supposed  to  produce  or  criticize  arguments  over  the  issue  in  question.   Detailed  analyses  of  discursive  manifestations  of  such  roles  have  been  undertaken  by   argumentation  scholars:  both  those  who  aim  at  a  close  “dialectical  reconstruction”  of   argumentation  (e.g.,  van  Eemeren  et  al.,  1993,  esp.  Ch.  4;  van  Eemeren  &  Houtlosser,   2005)  and  those  who  start  from  a  dialectical  view  to  investigate  what  happens  under   conditions  that  are  dialectically  less  than  ideal  (Author2,  2003;  Jacobs  &  Author2,  2002).     Noticeably,  however,  these  dialectical  analyses  of  argumentative  discourse  of   various  third-­‐parties  to  a  dispute  remain  somewhat  vague  on  the  very  notion  of  a  “third   party”  in  argumentative  interaction.  While  such  analyses  focus  on  the  argumentative   roles  of  third  parties,  these  roles  do  not  square  well  with  the  basic  dialectical  capacity  of   trading  pros  and  cons  (or  doubts)  on  a  contested  issue.  Third  parties  are  third  precisely   because  they  are  not  (expected  to  be)  openly  active  in  contention  defined  by  the   conflicting  positions  the  protagonist  and  the  antagonist  take.  Rather,  they  intervene  in  a   simple  support  capacity,  so  this  is  work  done  at  stages  other  than  the  pragma-­‐dialectical   argumentation  stage.  In  theory,  such  third  parties  are  excluded  from  the  basic   dialectical  framework  of  arguers  trying  to  convince  their  critics.  Yet,  as  repeatedly   observed  (Author2,  2003;  Jacobs  &  Author2,  2002)  in  practice  the  “disinterested”  “third   parties”  contribute  substantially  to  argumentative  interactions,  often  skillfully   managing  their  role  of  a  neutral  moderator  with  actual  engagement,  including  direct   contributions  to  the  content  of  arguments  given  and  taken.  This  is  evident  in  third-­‐party   practices  of  questioning  and  summarizing  (Author2,  2003;  Jacobs  &  Author2,  2002).   While  it  is  possible  that  dialectical  analysis  may  still  see  these  kinds  of  substantive   intrusions  of  third-­‐parties  as  necessary  element  of  managing  the  enabling  conditions  for   argumentation,  it  is  important  to  examine  third-­‐parties  who  are  legitimate  in  a   dialectical  sense  because  they  are  principals  to  the  difference  of  opinion.  For  the   purposes  at  hand,  it  is  thus  important  to  consider  cases  when  a  “third   party”  is  considered  an  actual  and  legitimate  contributor  to  argumentation  in  the  sense   of  openly  advancing  and  defending  a  position  that  is  distinct  from  the  (two  or  more)   already  contested  positions.   In  all  such  studies,  the  grounds  for  justifying  a  dyadic  analysis  are  quite  explicit   and  clear.  And  so  is  the  basic  rationale  –  an  analysis  that  reconstructs  a  multi-­‐ participant  debate  in  terms  of  a  (possibly  collective)  protagonist  facing  a  (possibly   collective)  antagonist  allows  to  mold  the  complex  discourse  into  a  basic  dialectical   framework  and  thus  paves  the  way  for  a  precise  dialectical  overview  and  evaluation  of   discourse  (e.g.  using  dialectical  profiles).  However,  such  gains  do  not  come  at  no  cost.  As   we  are  trying  to  show  here,  the  basic  problem  about  the  reduction  of  the  clash  of   positions  to  two  camps,  as  in  any  other  reduction,  is  a  loss  of  some  important  nuance   that  makes  a  difference  for  how  something  is  to  be  understood  and  assessed.    

10    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

  Now,  how  does  all  that  relate  to  our  hypothetical  committee  meeting?  Clearly,  we   notice  two  tag-­‐teams  that  do  consistently  support  one  candidate  (A  and  B  for  Prof.  α,   and  D  with  E  for  Prof.  γ).  But  the  overall  discussion  cannot  be  reduced  to  a  clash   between  these  two  teams  since  C  is  given  an  equal  opportunity  to  support  her  guy  (Prof.   β)  and,  let  us  assume,  she  makes  good  use  of  her  right,  which  is  also  carefully  enforced   by  the  chair.  So,  we  cannot  simply  “silent”  C  on  theoretical  or  empirical  grounds  –  C  does   argue  and  does  not  easily  ally  with  either  the  A-­‐B-­‐camp  or  the  D-­‐E-­‐camp.  Instead,  she  is   expected  to  simultaneously  address  these  two  separate  camps  holding  contrary   positions,  thus  risking  irrelevance  and  inconsistency  of  her  arguments.  As  an  active   distinct  party  in  a  committee  meeting,  C  -­‐-­‐  or  any  other  participant  for  that  matter  -­‐-­‐  is   also  not  a  mere  secondary  audience  that  would  serve  as  the  conveyor  of  arguments  in   some  primary  discussion,  let  us  say  between  A-­‐B  camp  and  D-­‐E  camp.  (Perhaps  in  some   local  instances  such  things  do  happen,  but  not  in  the  global  discussion.)  Likewise,  she  is   not  a  mere  third-­‐party  moderator  or  facilitator  –  this  is  the  role  of  the  (voteless,   impartial)  chair.  In  our  case,  it  seems  in  no  way  can  we  get  just  two  camps  facing  each   other  for  dialectical  analysis  that  adequately  portrays  the  positions  at  stake.  Unless  we   entertain  another  possibility. 3.3  Polylogue  as  a  multitude  of  dual  encounters     To  overcome  the  problems  of  reducing  a  polylogue  to  an  argument  between  two  main   forces,  a  dialectical  analyst  can  instead  follow  the  method  of  analyzing  any  multi-­‐party   discussion  as  if  it  consisted  of  a  multitude  of  dual  encounters.  The  analysis  would  start   by  dividing  the  “messy”  multi-­‐party  discussion  of  issues  instigated  by  a  Wh-­‐question   into  a  set  of  clear  yes/no  questions,  which  by  definition  break  any  issue  into  but  two   sides.  Such  analytically  generated  dyads  can  be  further  adequately  evaluated  to  see   which  of  the  two  sides  fares  better  in  a  dialectical  sense.  In  our  committee  meeting,  the   basic  question  -­‐-­‐  Who  should  receive  the  best  researcher  award  of  2012/2013?  -­‐-­‐  would   thus  be  split  into  three  yes/no  questions  -­‐-­‐  Should  Prof.  α  get  it?  Should  Prof.  β  get  it?   Should  Prof.  γ  get  it?  -­‐-­‐  that  one-­‐by-­‐one  lend  themselves  well  to  a  dialectical  analysis   and  evaluation  on  “both  sides  of  an  issue”. Beyond  this  general  characterization,  we  recognize  three  basic  variants  of  such  a   dualistic  analysis  and  a  fourth,  slightly  different  option.    They  can  be  elucidated   following  the  pragma-­‐dialectical  distinction  between  different  types  of  disputes,  and  a   notion  of  sub-­‐disputes.9 9   In   a   pragma-­‐dialectical   analysis   the   first   option   where   one   proposition   is   asserted   and   doubted   (α   vs.   α?),  the  so  called  “single  non-­‐mixed  dispute”,  is  the  most  elementary  dialectical  form  of  disagreement  into   which   all   other   types   of   disputes   can   be   analytically   broken   (van   Eemeren   &   Grootendorst,   2004,   p.   120);   the   second   type   (α   vs.   ¬α)   is   a   “single   mixed   dispute”   since   the   other   arguer   takes   up   a   contradictory   position   on   the   same   proposition,   instead   of   merely   expressing   doubt   against   it.   Further,   there   is   a   “multiple  non-­‐mixed  dispute”  in  which  a  number  of  propositions  is  doubted  (e.g.,  α  ˄  β  ˄  γ  vs.  (α  ˄  β  ˄  γ)?)   and  a  “multiple  mixed  dispute”  where  a  number  of  propositions  is  contradicted  (e.g.,  α  ˄  β  ˄  γ  vs.  ¬(α  ˄  β  ˄   γ)).  The  last  option  is  called  a  “qualitatively  multiple  dispute”  (see  van  Eemeren  et  al.,  2007,  pp.  26-­‐27)   since  two  qualitatively  exclusive  (contrary)  propositions  (α  vs.  β)  are  discussed.  

11    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

The  first  variant  would  fit  into  the  framework  of  a  “single  non-­‐mixed  dispute”.  To   a  question  “Should  Prof.  α  get  the  award?”  an  analyst  would  take  the  party  that   responds  “Yes,  she  should!”  (in  our  example  A  with  B)  to  be  the  protagonist  of  this   standpoint,  obligated  to  defend  it  when  challenged.  The  remaining  parties  (C,  D  with  E)   would  be  reconstructed  as  antagonists  in  the  strict  sense,  in  that  they  do  not  advance   positions  but  merely  cast  doubt  on  the  protagonist’s  position  by  asking  non-­‐committal   critical  questions  (“Does  she  publish  in  good  quality  journals?”,  “Is  her  research   attracting  grants  from  the  NSF?”).  Hence,  there  is  but  one  protagonist  (a  tag-­‐team   supporting  Prof.  α  and  consisting  of  A  and  B)  facing  one  antagonist,  that  is,  “others”  who   doubt  selecting  Prof.  α  is  the  best  solution.  No  other  options  are  available.  This  analytic   procedure  would  be  repeated  three  times,  likewise  assessing  Prof.  β’s  and  Prof.  γ’s   merits.  Hence,  in  this  variant  of  dialectical  reconstruction  each  of  our  three  parties  (A   with  B,  C,  and  D  with  E)  would  be  once  a  protagonist,  and  twice  an  antagonist  (in  this   role,  along  with  the  other  doubting  party).   A  good  example  of  this  sort  of  analysis  is  Feteris’s  (1999,  ch.  11)  study  of  court   proceedings  that  involve  at  least  three  parties  (in  a  criminal  trial:  prosecution,  defence,   and  the  judge/jury)  as  two  simultaneous  single  non-­‐mixed  disputes:  1)  between   prosecution  (“X  is  guilty”)  and  the  judge/jury  (“Is  X  really  guilty?”),  and  2)  between   defence  (“X  is  not  guilty”)  and  the  judge/jury  (“Is  X  really  not  guilty?”  ).  The  judge/jury   thus  plays  the  role  of  a  dialectical  antagonist  without  an  explicit  position  until  the  very   verdict,  while  prosecution  and  defence  are  two  protagonists  arguing  for  the  (lack  of)   guilt.  (By  presumption  of  innocence  in  most  legal  systems,  the  obvious  asymmetry   arises,  since  the  burden  of  proof  remains  with  the  prosecution-­‐protagonist,  while  the   defence-­‐protagonist  may  well  remain  “argumentless”.)  However,  while  highly   illuminating,  Feteris’s  analyses  pertain  to  a  particular  institutional  activity  that  exactly   allows  or  even  enforces  such  a  dualistic  division  into  single  non-­‐mixed  disputes;  by   definition,  issues  in  criminal  law  are  delineated  by  the  yes/no  question  regarding  the   guilt  of  the  accused.   In  the  second  variant,  a  multi-­‐party  discussion  would  be  divided  into  three  single   mixed  disputes.  In  the  case  of  a  “Should  Prof.  α  get  the  award?”  question,  the  protagonist   of  a  “Yes,  she  should!”  position  (A  with  B)  would  face  the  protagonist  of  a  contradictory   “No,  she  shouldn’t!”  position  (C,  D  with  E),  and  similarly  with  Prof.  β  (C  vs.  A  with  B  and   D  with  E)  and  Prof.  γ  (D  with  E  vs.  A  with  B  and  C).  A  notable  difference  with  the   previous  variant  is  that  each  protagonist  of  a  positive  position  does  not  face  mere   doubters  and  critical  questioners,  but  rather  active  opposition  that  would  argue  for  a   contradictory  position  (“She  doesn’t  deserve  it,  because  she  doesn’t  publish  enough”).   Each  party  in  our  committee  meeting  is  thus  a  protagonist  of  one  positive  position  (α;  β;   γ)  and  at  the  same  time  a  protagonist  of  two  negative  positions  (respectively:  ¬β,  ¬γ;  ¬α,   ¬γ;  ¬α,  ¬β).  In  each  dyadic  encounter  both  sides  thus  have  a  positive  burden  of  proof   regarding  the  advocated  position  (α  vs.  ¬α;  β  vs.  ¬β;  γ  vs.  ¬γ). If  this  seems  somewhat  complicated,  a  strict  dialectical  reconstruction  of  actual   polylogues  would  require  combining  the  two  variants  considered  above.  That  is   12    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

because,  logically  speaking,  a  negative  position  (¬α)  presupposes  doubt  (α?).  This  is   precisely  how  van  Rees  (2001)  proceeds  in  her  analysis  of  a  problem-­‐solving  discussion   regarding  additional  training  for  a  group,  where  three  distinct  positions  are  advanced:   1)  we  need  such  training,  so  let’s  move  to  the  details  (“if”  we  need  it  is  certain,  so  let’s   decide  on  “how”)  (participants  A  and  B);  2)  we  first  need  to  see  the  details  to  decide  on   the  need  (first  “how”,  then  “if”)  (participant  C);  3)  we  don’t  need  any  additional  training   at  all  (participant  D)  (van  Rees,  2001,  esp.  p.  462).  Van  Rees  clearly  distinguishes  the   intricate  problems  involved  in  this  polylogue,  in  particular  the  complexities  of   ascription  of  dialectical  roles:   All  participants  have  the  role  of  protagonist  for  their  own  standpoints.  In  addition,  they  all  have   the  role  of  antagonist  against  the  other  two  standpoints  and  that  of  protagonist  for  the  contra-­‐ standpoints  against  the  same.  In  our  discussion,  however,  the  latter  two  roles  do  not  get   performed  adequately.  (2001,  p.  464)  

We  can  see  that  by  following  the  precise  dialectical  framework  of  analysis  we  run  into   an  increasingly  complex  situation.  A  diligent  dialectician  would  in  fact  end  up  having  to   analyze  and  evaluate  a  three-­‐party  encounter  in  terms  of  three  single  mixed  disputes  (α   vs.  ¬α;  β  vs.  ¬β;  γ  vs.  ¬γ)  which,  strictly  speaking,  can  be  further  split  into  six  simple   non-­‐mixed  disputes  (α  vs.  α?;  ¬α  vs.  ¬α?;  β  vs.  β?;  ¬β  vs.  ¬β?;  γ  vs.  γ?;  ¬γ  vs.  ¬γ?).  And   that  is  a  hefty  task  for  both  the  analyst  and  the  participants  who,  as  in  the  case  above,   may  end  up  not  performing  their  distinct  dialectical  roles  adequately.  Of  course,  again,   we  are  talking  about  a  rational  dialectical  reconstruction  –  in  actual  discourse  our   committee  members  or  van  Rees’s  consultants  “simply”  debate  three  contrary  positions   in  the  give  and  take  of  argumentative  exchange.   This  brings  us  to  the  third  variant.  Well-­‐developed  and  pragmatically  oriented   approaches,  such  as  pragma-­‐dialectics,  recognize  the  possibility  of  directly  analyzing  a   clash  of  contrary  positions  in  a  “qualitatively  multiple  dispute”.  Such  a  dispute  arises   when  a  speaker  “takes  up  an  alternative  standpoint  […]  [that],  viewed  dialectically,   implies  a  standpoint  that  is  opposite  to”  another  speaker’s  standpoint  (van  Eemeren  et   al.,  2007,  pp.  26-­‐27).  An  opposite  standpoint  may  be  both  contradictory  and  contrary  to   the  other  position  (op.  cit.,  pp.  57-­‐62).  What  follows  is  that  a  qualitatively  mixed  dispute   may  clearly  arise  in  response  to  a  Wh-­‐question  which  opens  room  for  a  clash  of   multitude  of  contrary  alternatives.  Van  Eemeren  et  al.  analyze  many  examples  of  such   disputes,  including  this: Where  can  we  still  see  a  glimmer  of  hope  in  that  terrible  genocide  in  Kosovo?  That  hope  does  not   lie  in  a  victory  for  NATO  or  a  victory  for  the  Kosovo  Liberation  Army,  UCK.  And  certainly  not  in  a   victory  for  Milosevic.  (quoted  in  van  Eemeren  et  al.,  2007,  p.  61)

Although  van  Eemeren  et  al.  reconstruct  this  dispute  in  terms  of  a  dyadic  exchange,  it  is   also  plausible  to  see  it  as  a  clash  of  at  least  three  contrary  positions  advocated  by   different  parties:  that  NATO  will  bring  peace  to  Kosovo,  that  UCK  will  do  it,  or  that   Milosevic  will.  The  author  of  the  newspaper  commentary  is  adamantly  against   13    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Milosevic,  and  quite  doubtful  about  two  other  options:  NATO  and  UCK.  Perhaps  he   argues  for  some  kind  of  a  fourth  solution,  but  this  is  not  clear  in  the  quoted  fragment.   What  is  clear,  though,  is  that  we  deal  here  with  a  conflict  of  contrary  opinions  in  a   qualitatively  multiple  dispute.  Yet,  dialectical  accounts  seem  to  fall  short  of  investigating   the  intricacies  of  such  a  discussion  between  contrary  positions,  even  if  there  are  only   two  of  them.  By  definition,  such  positions  cannot  be  both  correct,  yet  they  can  be  both   wrong.  And  this  is  exactly  because  there  is  a  third  (or  fourth,  etc.)  position  that  is   correct.  The  question  remains  how  to  introduce  this  third  or  fourth  position  into  a   dialectical  analysis.     The  fourth  dialectical  avenue  to  split  a  polylogue  into  a  number  of  dyadic   discussions  would  resort  to  the  concept  of  sub-­‐discussions.  A  polylogue  would  thus   amount  to  a  collection  of  sub-­‐discussions  in  one  main  discussion  defined  by  a  single   overarching  issue  (see  van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,  1992,  p.  42).  In  this  method  of   analysis,  the  main  dialectical  discussion  can  branch  out  on  any  disputable  point,   potentially  opening  up  a  profile  of  dialogue  not  unlike  a  conversational  Porphyrian  tree.   Imagine  that  in  our  committee  meeting  the  chair  (an  admirer  of  Plato’s  method  of   diairesis)  suggests  to  address  some  crucial  issues  in  the  following  order:  Shall  we   prioritize  research  achievements,  or  not?  If  so,  shall  we  prioritize  publications  or   grants?  If  publications,  then  papers  or  monographs?  If  papers,  then  empirical  or   theoretical  contributions?  If  empirical,  then  qualitative  or  quantitative?  To  each  of  these   questions,  two  sides  can  form  thus  opening  up  a  sub-­‐discussion  in  the  main  discussion   about  who  should  be  the  professor  of  the  year.  A  reconstructed  discussion  would   resemble  something  like  a  stem  of  hierarchically  organized  issues,  and  dyadic  branches   coming  out  of  it.  The  main  point  of  such  a  reconstruction  is  that  dyadic  sub-­‐disputes,  if   properly  separated  and  resolved,  can  eventually  add  up  to  the  clear  and  distinct   resolution  of  the  entire  discussion,  whether  polylogical  or  not.   The  problem  of  analyzing  polylogues  in  a  dialectical  framework  can  also  be   tackled,  more  or  less  similarly,  in  any  other  dualistic  dialectical  approach,  for  instance   Walton’s  “dialog  theory”.  For  Walton,  participation  in  a  multi-­‐party  discussion  would   amount  to  participation  in  various  dyadic  dialogues  at  the  same  time  (Walton  &   Macagno,  2010,  p.  314),  and  a  polylogue  would  amount  to  a  constellation  of  dyadic   dialogues.  It  seems,  thus,  that  any  addition  of  a  distinct  party  would  increase  the   number  of  dialogues  by  the  number  of  the  parties  previously  involved.  In  the  simplest   case,  adding  one  party  to  a  di-­‐logue,  would  potentially  create  3  dyadic  dialogues  (as  in   our  academic  committee  meeting  –  see  Figure  1);  but,  e.g.,  adding  a  party  to  a  penta-­‐ logue,  would  increase  the  number  of  potential  dyadic  dialogues  from  10  to  15.  This,  no   doubt,  would  heavily  burden  the  participants  and  analysts.  In  any  case,  this  is  another   theoretical  attempt  at  “dualizing”  a  multiple  discussion.  Importantly,  while  Walton  does   not  attempt  to  satisfactorily  solve  the  problem,  he  acknowledges  the  gap  between   “theoretical  simplicity”  (Ibidem)  of  dyadic  dialectical  models  and  complex,  multi-­‐party   argumentative  exchanges,  and  expresses  the  need  to  bridge  this  gap  through  theoretical   improvements.     14    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

  The  splitting  of  a  polylogue  into  analytically  distinct  dyads  allows  for  a  precise,  if   somewhat  microscopic,  insight  into  local  episodes  of  argumentative  exchanges.   However,  at  least  in  some  cases,  it  seems  to  be  missing  “the  logic”  of  the  entire  multi-­‐ party  exchange.  As  we  attempted  to  show,  this  method  of  analysis  divides  polylogues   into  what  is  relevant  from  the  perspective  of  one  or  another  dialectical  model,  but  not   necessarily  from  the  perspective  of  an  analyst  interested  in  the  arguers’  rational  and   strategic  choices  in  the  entire  discussion.  This,  on  an  abstract  level,  is  an  instantiation  of   the  reductionism/holism  problem  -­‐  the  sum  total  of  carefully  separated  parts  does  not   (necessarily)  amount  to  grasping  the  whole.10  One  can  easily  think  of  examples  where   the  analysis  of  the  simple  non-­‐mixed  disputes  or  sub-­‐disputes  does  not  capture  the   interconnections  among  the  dyads  (that  often  develop  simultaneously).  Imagine  that  in   our  committee  discussion  A  and  B  –  responding  to  D  and  E’s  objection  –  repeatedly   stress  the  importance  of  the  monograph  published  by  their  candidate  (Prof.  α),  knowing   full-­‐well  that  D+E  are  paper-­‐oriented  social  scientists  who  cannot  care  less  about  book-­‐ long  monographs.  From  both  a  dialectical  and  rhetorical  point  of  view,  A+B’s  arguments   would  be  irrelevant  or  at  least  counter-­‐productive.  But  perhaps  A+B  advance  them   anyways  for  the  sake  of  C  –  the  third,  and  a  monograph-­‐friendly,  party.  So  what  seems   to  belong  to  one  (sub-­‐)discussion  is  better  seen  as  a  contribution  to  another  (see   Mohammed,  2011).  This  subtle  interconnection  is  easily  lost  in  the  “atomized”  dyadic   form  of  analysis  which  may  lead  to  paradoxical  results:  A+B’s  argument  about  the   published  monograph  is  evaluated  as  irrelevant  and  ineffective  when  the  dyadic   exchange  with  D+E  is  analyzed,  but  “suddenly”  becomes  relevant  and  effective  when  the   analyst  takes  it  as  a  contribution  to  A+B’s  concurrent  exchange  with  C.  The  same  speech   act  is  thus  good  and  bad  at  the  same  time.  While  it  is  crucial,  we  think,  to  have  a  clear   dialectical  understanding  of  what  happens  in  localized  episodes  of  one-­‐on-­‐one   argumentation,  it  is  necessary  to  accompany  it  with  a  broader  analysis  and  evaluation  of   argumentative  moves  in  the  entire  polylogue.  It  is  exactly  the  difference  between  the   two  that  is  most  fascinating:11  an  argumentative  speech  act  might  bear  on  the  resolution   of  a  multi-­‐party  dispute  in  ways  different  from  a  contribution  defined  in  dyadic   dialectical  models,  for  instance  in  precise  sequences  of  dialectical  profiles  (van  Eemeren   et  al.,  2007).12  Admittedly,  one  can  more  or  less  justifiably  reconstruct  a  given  move  as   “primarily”  belonging  to  a  dyadic  discussion  different  from  the  on-­‐going  one.  But  this   10   Bonevac   claims   that   “[s]omeone   seeking   to   defend   a   position   against   a   variety   of   opponents   at   once,   for   example,   must   meet   a   number   of   constraints   that   cannot   be   understood   as   conjunctions   of   constraints   applied  to  each  dispute  taken  individually”  (Bonevac,  2003,  pp.  454-­‐455,  see  also  Author1,  2012).   11   Similarly   to   the   differences   between   what   is   good   in   logical   and   dialectical   approaches   to   argumentation,  so  thoroughly  examined  by  Hamblin  (1970).   12  

One   reviewer   suggested   that   polylogical   factors   in   argumentation   analysis   are   basically   rhetorical   concerns.   But   we   understand   this   as   a   difference   different   than   the   one   between   dialectic   and   rhetoric.   We   focus   here   precisely   on   the   resolution-­‐relevant   moves   which,   as   we   argue,   are   not   always   simply   dyadic.  Our  inquiry,  then,  begins  in  the  realm  of  the  “reasonable”  and  dialectical  –  rather  than  “strategic”   and   rhetorical   –   aspect   of   strategic   maneuvering   in   polylogical   argumentation.   Therefore,   we   disagree   with   a   “defeatist”   position   in   which   all   polylogical   facets   of   multi-­‐party   discussions   are   demoted   to   the   status  of  purely  rhetorical  complications  surrounding  a  dyadic  dispute.    

15    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

might  lead  to  a  dangerous  practice  of  taking  many  prima  facie  irrelevant  arguments  or   criticisms  to  be  relevant  by  virtue  of  belonging  to  some  other  (actual  or  potential)   discussion  that  is  external  to  the  current  di-­‐logue.  Without  precisely  demarcating  which   other  reconstructed  discussions  are  relevant,  we  risk  ad  hoc  and  arbitrary  assessments.   In  a  polylogue,  the  boundary  is  clear  –  those  argumentative  moves  are  relevant  which   bear  on  the  positions  debated  in  a  polylogue.  This  might  happen  on  a  local,  dyadic  level   (a  move  is  relevant  in  a  sub-­‐discussion  with  the  currently  addressed  party)  or  a  global   level  (a  move  is  relevant  to  some  other  parties’  positions).             Moreover,  splitting  into  dyads  may  open  the  problem  of  establishing  the  final   outcome  of  a  discussion.  Imagine  that  during  the  meeting,  A-­‐B  manage  to  overcome  C’s   objections  and  thus  win  their  case  for  Prof.  α;  C  however  convinces  D-­‐E  that  her   arguments  for  Prof.  β  are  cogent  and  reasonable;  finally,  in  a  “separate”  dispute  D-­‐E   convince  A-­‐B  that  their  Prof.  γ  is  better  than  α  on  rational,  dialectical  grounds.  So  α  >  β  >   γ  but…  γ  >  α!  Whose  arguments  are  then  strongest  and  whose  position  should  prevail   according  to  the  rules  of  critical  testing?  Such  a  problem  of  establishing  outcome  is   known  from  sport  tournaments,  including  chess:  in  a  direct  encounter  a  White  player   may  win  over  Black,  Black  defeats  Yellow,  and  Yellow  defeats  White.  Even  though  we   know  perfectly  well  who  the  better  player  in  each  game  is,  we  do  not  know  who  the  best   player  of  the  three  is.  (This  can  be  seen  as  a  discursive  version  of  Condorcet’s  paradox.) Our  goal  in  this  section  was  to  critically  review  the  options  a  well-­‐developed   dialectical  theory  of  argumentation,  such  a  pragma-­‐dialectics  or  Walton’s  dialog  theory,   has  at  its  disposal  in  analyzing  and  evaluating  multi-­‐party  argumentative  discussion.  On   the  basis  of  this  scrutiny  we  are  in  a  position  to  conclude  that  while  various  dialectical   methods  of  analyzing  a  polylogue  are  no  doubt  useful  in  many  routine  cases  where   dyadic  reconstruction  is  warranted  for  one  reason  or  another,  they  do  not  fully  grasp   some  important  aspects  of  multi-­‐party  argumentation,  such  as  in  our  committee   meeting.  These  aspects  relate  to  both  the  understanding  of  the  strategic  rationale   behind  certain  discursive  choices  and  to  their  evaluation  in  terms  of  reasonable  or   fallacious  dialectical  moves.     4.  Towards  a  polylogical  understanding  of  polylogues                 4.1  Why  bother?     In  this  last  section,  we  will  outline  the  elements  of  a  polylogical  approach  to  analyzing   and  evaluating  multi-­‐party  argumentation.  Since  our  point  of  reference  here  are   dialectical  approaches  to  analyzing  argumentative  discussions,  we  will  sketch  a  solution   based  on  a  dialectical  framework.  The  greatest  advantage  of  dialectical  models  is  that   they  theorize  argumentation  as  an  interactive  achievement  of  interlocutors  engaged  in  a   discussion  on  a  disputable  issue.  This  makes  them  fit  for  analyzing  a  wide  range  of   communicative  activities.  Moreover,  recent  dialectical  theories  have  successfully   merged  the  largely  descriptive,  pragmatic  aspect  of  ordinary  argumentation  with  the   16    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

normative,  even  formal  dimension  of  dialectical  models  (van  Eemeren,  2010;  van   Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,  1984,  2004;  Hamblin,  1970;  Walton,  1998;  Walton  &  Krabbe,   1995).  Argumentative  discussions  or  dialogues  are  thus  understood  as  interactions   defined  through  their  pragmatic  and  normative  dimension.  Therefore,  dialectical   models  are  built  on  assumptions  grounded,  on  the  one  hand,  in  pragmatics  and   conversation  analysis  and,  on  the  other  hand,  in  formal  models  of  dialogues.  We  find  it   crucial  to  discussing  argumentative  polylogues  that  the  classic  dyadic  assumptions  on   what  constitutes  interactions  (or  dialogues)  have  been  challenged:  both  in  the   pragmatic  (e.g.,  Clark  &  Carlson,  1982;  Dascal,  2008;  Kerbrat-­‐Orecchionni,  1997,  2004;   Levinson,  1988)  and  dialectical  (e.g.,  Sylvan,  1985)  tradition.  Without  discussing  this   broad  literature  here  (see,  however,  Author1,  2013a,  2013b),  we  note  that  both  these   research  traditions  offer  solid  theoretical  and  methodological  grounds  for  poly-­‐logical   extensions  of  current  di-­‐logical  argumentation  theory  without,  however,  offering  any   such  clear  extensions.       To  be  sure,  dialectical  analysts  themselves  acknowledge  challenges  which  multi-­‐ party  discussions  pose  for  the  analysis  and  evaluation  of  argumentation.  Yet,  they  also   do  not  offer  a  theoretical  solution  that  would  satisfactorily  solve  them:   In  real  life,  argumentative  discourse  often  contains  several  discussions  at  the  same  time  that  may   be  intertwined.  Even  if  the  original  dispute  is  simple,  new  disputes  may  come  up  and  any  number   of  subdisputes  can  still  arise  out  of  argumentation  advanced  to  resolve  the  original  dispute.   These  can,  in  turn,  also  lead  to  discussion  and  hence  to  the  advancing  of  new  arguments.  […]  This   does  not  make  things  any  easier  when  it  comes  to  distinguishing  the  speech  acts  that  are  relevant   to  the  resolution  of  the  principal  dispute.  (van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,  1992,  p.  42;  see  also   Walton  &  Macagno,  2010,  p.  314).  

Our  claim  is  that  such  problems  are  not  mere  complications  of  reality  to  which   theoretical  models  are  immune,  but  are  genuine  problems  for  understanding  and   evaluating  ordinary  argumentation  that  should  be  given  a  precise  theoretical   formulation  within  the  framework  of  argumentation  theory.   We  begin  doing  it  here  by  resorting  to  a  “dialectical  perspective”  on   argumentation,  as  understood  by  Wenzel  (1990).  According  to  him,  “[w]ithin  the   dialectical  perspective,  the  chief  resources  of  interest  are  designs  or  plans  for   conducting  critical  discussions”  (Wenzel,  1990,  p.  21).  Below,  we  limit  ourselves  to  a   theoretical  and  highly  normative  “design  or  plan”  for  conducting  multi-­‐party  “critical   discussions”.  However,  research  within  the  “design  stance”  championed  by  “normative   pragmatists”  may  instead  focus  on  a  design  of  actually  implemented  or  implementable   procedures  for  argumentative  discussions.  This  approach,  in  contrast  to  the  former,   would  seek  “design  principles,”  which  are  a  set  of  topoi  of  sorts  for  arranging  and   orchestrating  the  management  of  disagreement  among  actual  arguers.  These  principles   take  into  account  that  real  arguers  are  constrained  by  concrete  communicative   limitations  which  are  typically  at  odds  with  the  requirements  of  ideal  models  (see   Author2,  2007,  2013;  Author2  &  Jackson,  2005;  Jacobs  &  Jackson,  2006;  Jackson,  1998).   While  different  in  their  direction,  these  two  approaches  to  designing  argumentative   17    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

polylogues  would  face  the  same  (normative  or  empirical)  challenge:  to  go  beyond   designs  for  two-­‐party,  two-­‐sided  issues  in  order  to  address  polylogical  multi-­‐faceted   issues  without  losing  the  multi-­‐party  argumentation  element.     4.2  Towards  an  ideal  polylogical  model     One  can  start  thinking  of  a  normative  model  of  argumentative  polylogues  in  terms  of  the   dialectical  models  we  discussed  above  but  extended  to  incorporate  the  clash  of  more   than  just  two  positions  on  an  issue.  Such  a  model  can  be  constructed  in  a  largely  formal   manner,  as  in  Sylvan’s  (1985)  polylogue  systems,  or  informally,  using  the  extant   pragmatically-­‐oriented  dialectical  approaches  as  a  basic  theoretical  background.  The   pragma-­‐dialectical  model  of  a  critical  discussion  may  be  particularly  useful  in  this   endeavor  as  a  well-­‐defined  normative  account  of  everyday  argumentation.  It  offers  a   useful  heuristic  of  dividing  argumentative  discussions  into  four  “dialectical  stages”:   confrontation,  opening,  argumentation,  and  concluding  (van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,   2004,  pp.  57ff.).  We  use  this  well-­‐known  heuristic  to  highlight,  stage-­‐by-­‐stage,  the  extra   factors  that  a  polylogical  models  should  take  into  account  when  compared  to  a  simpler   dyadic  model.   In  the  confrontation,  pragma-­‐dialectics  requires  of  arguers  to  clearly  define  their   difference  of  opinion  over  a  standpoint  (or  standpoints)  in  terms  of  one  of  the  basic   types  of  dispute  stipulated  in  the  model  (see  above  fn.  9).  It  is  here,  in  other  words,   where  the  disagreement  space  is  interactively  constructed  by  the  arguers:  “A  dispute   arises  when  someone  advances  a  standpoint  and  someone  else  casts  doubt  upon  it”  (van   Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,  1992,  p.  107).  However,  a  standpoint  itself  can  be  seen  as  a   response  to  a  more  or  less  explicitly  stated  issue  that  instigates  position-­‐taking,  such  as   a  problem  that  calls  for  a  solution  or  a  decision  to  be  taken  on  who  the  professor  of  the   year  should  be.  The  first  step  in  determining  a  polylogical  confrontation  would   therefore  be  to  precisely  examine  the  nature  of  the  issue.  Is  it  formulated  in  terms  of  a   polar  yes/no  question,  a  safe  Wh-­‐question  where  a  set  of  relevant  answers  is  finite  and   known  to  the  arguers  (such  as  in  our  faculty  committee),  or  a  risky  Wh-­‐question  where   the  set  of  possible  alternatives  is  open-­‐ended?13  If  the  issue  demands  a  yes/no  choice   (such  as  in  Aristotelian  dialectics  and  all  kinds  of  truth-­‐conditional  investigations  based   on  a  bi-­‐valued  logic),  then  only  two  contradictory  sides  can  be  taken  (either  true  or   false),  and  a  standard  dialectical  inquiry  should  follow.  (As  we  noted  above,  in   approaches  embracing  a  tri-­‐valued  logic,  such  as  pragma-­‐dialectics,  the  simplest  dispute   would  develop  between  the  party  holding  either  the  yes-­‐  or  the  no-­‐position  and  the   pure  critical  doubter  –  the  “I  don’t  know”  respondent  to  the  yes/no  question.)  If  the  Wh-­‐ questions  are  at  issue,  arguers  should  intersubjectively  investigate  how  many  contrary   positions  on  an  issue  can  be  reasonably  put  forth.  If  only  two,  then  again  a  dialectical   discussion  can  unfold  to  judge  their  relative  merits.  If  a  finite  set  of  more  than  two,  then   the  arguers  should  see  if  there  is  a  way  to  split  the  multiple  positions  into  two  basic   13  See  Hamblin  (1970,  p.  216)  for  the  distinction  between  safe  and  risky  questions.  

18    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

camps  (see  above  section  3.2)  or  sequentially  structured  dyads  (section  3.3).  If  any  of   these  works,  again,  some  (complex)  dialectical  procedure  can  be  followed.  Finally,  if   there  is  no  viable  way  to  “dichotomize”  a  finite  set  of  multiple  positions,  or  a  set  is  open-­‐ ended,  then  arguers  should  recognize  they  are  dealing  with  a  genuinely  multi-­‐party   disagreement  space  that  should  be  explored  as  such  through  polylogical  argumentation.   As  we  argued  above,  this  happens  in  our  committee  meeting  where  three  contrary   positions  are  simultaneously  debated.  Ideally,  all  possible  mutual  relations  between   multiple  positions  should  be  clearly  defined  (for  instance  using  the  classic  Aristotelian   “square  of  opposition”  which  distinguishes  between  contradictory,  contrary,  sub-­‐ contrary,  and  sub-­‐  and  super-­‐altern  relations).  Having  done  that,  arguers  would  be  in  a   good  position  to  see  “what  is  at  stake”  in  the  polylogue.14 At  the  opening  stage,  pragma-­‐dialectical  arguers  define  their  roles  as  the   protagonist  and  the  antagonist  of  the  standpoint,  and  further  determine  their  common   starting  points  both  in  terms  of  procedures  they  will  follow  and  the  shared  propositions   from  which  they  will  build  their  arguments  and  criticisms.  This  is  very  clear,  yet   polylogues  require  a  more  complex  notion  of  common  starting  points  or,  for  short,   common  ground.  In  a  dyadic  encounter,  common  ground  is  what  is  shared  by  the  two   interlocutors  –  it  is  there  or  it  isn’t,  and  when  it  isn’t,  reasonable  communication  is   largely  precluded  (see  Fogelin,  1985).  In  a  polylogue,  by  contrast,  one  can  distinguish   between  a  global  common  ground,  what  is  shared  among  all  parties,  and  some  local   common  grounds,  what  is  shared  by  some  sub-­‐set  of  parties.15  Therefore,  some  new   solutions  for  common  starting  points  –  whether  procedural  or  material  –  need  to  be   found  to  account  for  a  reasonable  multiplicity  of  common  grounds  in  one  multi-­‐party   discussion.  Arguers  at  an  ideal  polylogical  opening  stage  should  clearly  delimit  various   levels  of  sharedness  of  their  material  commitments:  Are  the  facts  and  values  shared   among  all  parties,  most  of  them,  or  perhaps  only  two  of  them?  What  is  the  strength  of   the  overlapping  commitments  –  are  they  fully  “asserted,”  merely  “conceded,”  or  hidden   in  the  “dark  side”  (see  Walton  &  Krabbe,  1995)?  How  to  manage  the  “residual”   commitments  –  those  that  are  shared  by  some,  but  not  by  others,  and  thus  cannot  be   employed  throughout  the  discussion?  Such  questions,  if  settled  at  the  start  of  discussion   will  of  course  impact  the  way  argumentation  proceeds  in  each  of  these  cases.  Surely,   some  interesting  work  on  how  arguers  construct  and  negotiate  common  ground  can   develop  when  the  complexities  of  multi-­‐party  commitments  are  taken  into  account  (see,   e.g.,  Clark,  1992).   Above  all,  however,  polylogues  require  a  different  set  of  procedural  starting   points:  compare  the  discussion  procedure  of  a  dyadic  legal  trial  with  a  parliamentary   14   Note   that   it   is   at   the   confrontation   stage   where   the   fallacy   of   a   false   dilemma   can   be   defined   in   a  

polylogical   sense:   “In   a   context   where   one   can   discuss   many   propositions   (poly-­‐lemma),   a   di-­‐lemma   is   false,  because  it  focuses  exclusively  on  two  positions,  thus  preventing  other  positions  (standpoints)  from   being  considered.”  (Author1,  2013b,  p.  14).     15  “Even  if  the  principle  ‘No  common  logic,  no  communication’  held,  it  would  not  follow  that  there  must  be  

a  one  logic  for  each  polylogue,  only  common  ground  for  each  pair  of  parties  in  a  polylogue  that  manage  to   communicate.”  (Sylvan,  1985,  p.  110).  

19    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

debate  to  which  many  members  of  various  parties  contribute.  By  contrast  to  legal   procedures  that  have  inspired  much  of  dialectics,  polylogues  would  require  something   akin  to  the  famous  Robert’s  Rules  of  Order  meant  to  secure  an  orderly  conduct  of  multi-­‐ party  assemblies  (Sylvan,  1985,  pp.  102-­‐103).  This  difference  in  discussion  procedures   is  significant,  as  different  verbal  interventions  would  be  relevant  (‘in  order,’  ‘legal,’   ‘acceptable’)  in  court  and  in  an  assembly.  Indeed,  developing  reasonable  procedures  for   multi-­‐party  and  multi-­‐position  argumentative  discussions  is  a  main  task  for  both   idealized  modeling  of  argumentation  and  for  designing  viable  disagreement-­‐ management  protocols  in  real-­‐life  argumentation.  Crucially,  a  simple  dyadic  turn-­‐taking   model  –  such  as  the  one  on  which  dialectical  profiles  are  based  –  will  not  do  a  good  job   here:     As for the alternating pattern, the famous ababab formula only works for dilogues, whereas for trilogues the alternation does not respect any kind of fixed rules: we are dealing with an infinite number of possibilities, the abcabcabc model being very exceptional. (Kerbrat-Orecchionni, 1997, p. 5).    

  This,  of  course,  is  an  empirical  statement;  an  ideal  normative  model  can  impose  the   abcabcabc  order  –  or  some  other  more  flexible  set  of  rules  for  organizing  argumentative   contributions  from  third-­‐,  fourth-­‐,  etc.,  parties.  In  any  case,  further  work  on  polylogical   procedures  or  profiles  is  badly  needed.   The  central  stage  of  pragma-­‐dialectal  critical  discussion  –  the  argumentation   stage  –  is  where  arguers  engage  in  an  ordered  exchange  of  arguments  and  criticisms.   This  happens  through  dyadic  turns  in  which  the  antagonist  drills  down  on  a   disagreement  and  the  protagonist  responds  with  increasingly  elaborate  complex   argumentation  (Snoeck  Henkemans,  1992).  These  dyadic  turns  are  governed  by  the   rules  of  a  reasonable  discussion,  and  thus  are  the  locus  of  pragma-­‐dialectal  fallacies.   However,  as  we  argued  above  and  elsewhere  (Author1,  2012,  2013a,  2013b),   unexpected  things  can  happen,  both  in  the  sense  of  rational  quality  of  argumentation   and  its  strategic  shape.  As  we  have  seen,  arguers  may  advance  arguments  that  seem   irrelevant  in  a  dyadic  exchange,  but  are  reasonable  since  they  adequately  address   concerns  of  some  third,  or  fourth,  party.  Similarly,  arguers  may  be  seemingly  engaged  in   superfluous  or  over-­‐the-­‐top  argumentation  that  however  seems  just  enough  if  some   additional  parties  are  taken  into  account.  To  be  sure,  some  acceptable  forms  of   inference  should  be  employed  for  arguers  to  remain  reasonable  (but  then,  as  Sylvan,   1985,  pointed  out,  acceptable  on  grounds  of  which  of  the  many  logical  models?).  Many   questions  arise  however  regarding  basic  building  blocks  of  informal  (in  the  logical   sense)  argumentative  exchanges:  if  informal  argument  schemes  are  reasonable  when   they  satisfactorily  address  relevant  critical  questions  (Walton,  Reed,  &  Macagno,  2008),   then  whose  critical  questions  are  they?  Well,  obviously  “the  critic’s”,  but  each  party  to  a   polylogue  faces  more  than  one  critic,  and  they  should  not  be  conflated.  Otherwise,  a   form  of  a  polylogical  (collateral)  straw  man  may  occur  when  an  arguer  attacks  her   opponent  using  commitments  of  a  different  critic  (Author1,  2013b).  In  general,  all  kinds   of  intersubjective  procedures  at  the  argumentation  stage  (van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,   20    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

2004,  pp.  145ff.)  require  a  more  complex  notion  of  intersubjectivity  –  for  instance,  as   suggested  above,  divided  into  some  global  and  local  level.  What  is  shared  by  two  parties,   is  not  necessarily  shared  by  most,  or  all  parties.  Eventually,  deciding  which  argument,  or   criticism,  holds  and  is  thus  decisive  in  the  current  discussion  is  much  more  complex  in  a   polylogue  than  it  is  in  a  dyadic  exchange. This  brings  us  to  the  problems  of  concluding  the  discussion  on  the  basis  of  the   results  of  the  argumentative  procedures.  In  a  dyadic  discussion,  this  is  a  fairly   straightforward  business,  since  arguers  can  choose  from  but  two  options:  that  “the   protagonist’s  standpoint  is  acceptable  and  the  antagonist’s  doubt  must  be  retracted,  or   that  the  standpoint  of  the  protagonist  must  be  retracted”  (van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,   2004,  p.  61).  In  a  polylogue,  since  there  are  by  definition  many  protagonists  of  distinct   positions  and  thus  also  many  distinct  antagonists,  the  choices  may  be  plenty.  One   position  can  simply  be  better  than  any  other,  which  allows  for  a  clear  conclusion.  But   some  positions  can  be  accepted  by  an  equal  amount  of  parties,  which  possibly  leads  to  a   standoff.  Arguers  may  also  decide  to  “sum  up”  all  the  conclusions  of  dyadic  encounters  –   especially  in  the  case  where  they  decide  to  split  their  procedure  into  a  sequence  of  dual   encounters.  Dialectically  speaking,  such  local  concluding  stages  seem  the  most  viable   option,  but  the  final  evaluation  of  the  entire  multi-­‐party  deliberation  may  face  the   problem  mentioned  above  (section  3.3,  p.  15):  each  party  would  be  once  a  winner  and   once  a  loser,  making  it  hard  to  decide  on  a  single  “best”  option  (α  >  β  >  γ  >  α).  Some   novel  methods  of  concluding  the  complex  polylogue  are  yet  to  be  developed.   To  recap  –  one  may  undertake  a  relatively  conservative  (in  a  theoretical  sense)   revision  of  dialectical  models  which  would  bring  them  more  in  line  with  the  challenges   polylogues  present  to  argument  analysis  and  evaluation.  The  basic  assumptions  and   structure  of  the  models  would  remain  intact,  while  some  additional  features  would  be   incorporated  to  address  the  novel  complexities  of  polylogues  we  discussed  above.  Such   a  polylogical  model  would  thus  extend,  rather  than  supplant,  dyadic  dialectical  models   in  order  to  adequately  cover  multi-­‐party  cases  such  as  our  university  committee.   Working  such  a  model  out  would  be  similar  to  devising  rules  for  the  game  of  chess  for   three  –  we  are  still  speaking  of  a  game  on  a  chessboard  with  familiar  rules  and  roles,  but   some  little  tweaks  to  include  “the  third”  are  put  in  place.         5.  Conclusion    

We  have  analyzed  argumentative  polylogues  as  activities  characterized  by  features  that   make  them  problematic  from  the  perspective  of  dyadic  dialectical  analysis  for  the   purpose  of  evaluating  argumentation.  As  we  have  shown,  dialectical  analyses  do  their   job  in  a  great  many  argumentative  activities,  but  not  so  well  in  the  context  of  polylogue.   We  have  pointed  out  key  pitfalls  of  dialectical  analysis  for  polylogues.  These  can  be   briefly  summarized  as  either  descriptive  or  normative.  Descriptive  problems  consist  in   the  fact  that  dialectical  methods  may  not  adequately  perceive  the  strategic  rationality   behind  the  choices  of  arguers  engaged  in  polylogical  encounters.  Normative  problems   21    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

amount  to  the  way  a  polylogue  problematizes  the  dialectical  rules:  some  of  them  seem   to  be  targeting  a  different  form  of  interaction,  some  seem  to  be  missing.   Dialectics  can  be  grasped  as  a  “relational”  approach  to  argumentative  rationality   (note  the  difference  between  relational  and  relative/relativistic  approach).  In  the   philosophical  sense,  dialectics  is  relational  since  its  highest  epistemic  goal  is  that  of   critical  error-­‐correction,  rather  than  monological  truth-­‐tracking.  Dialectical  starting   points  and  conclusions  are  merely  plausible  (defeasible,  corroborated)  and  thus   tentative,  until  there  are  no  overriding  criticisms  or  considerations.  A  position  stands   because  it  is  better  than  some  other  positions  in  that  it  is  capable  of  withholding  a  larger   amount  of  possible  criticisms.  As  soon  as  soon  as  a  position  is  compared  to  another   position  that  successfully  deals  with  more  possible  objections,  it  collapses  or  is   refuted.16 Accordingly,  dialectics  in  its  function  of  a  methodical  analysis  and  evaluation  of   discourse  defines  argumentative  roles  in  terms  of  relations  that  hold  between  the   bearers  of  these  roles  and  some  propositions.  The  basic  relations  are  of  course   acceptance,  doubt,  and  rejection  of  a  proposition.  Furthermore,  these  relations  between   arguers  and  discourse  also  define  relations  between  arguers  themselves.  An  author  of   an  utterance  does  not  become  a  protagonist  until  her  utterance  is  challenged  by   someone  else,  who  thus  becomes  an  antagonist.  These  seem  to  be  basic  assumptions  of   pragmatic  (e.g.,  Jackson  &  Jacobs,  1980)  and  dialectical  approaches  to  argumentative   discourse  alike.  Shortly,  there  are  no  dialectical  parties  without  a  particular  relation  that   holds  between  them.  This  relation  is  defined  in  a  dyadic  sense  of  a  one-­‐on-­‐one   opposition.  A  protagonist  of  a  position  exists  because  there  is  an  antagonist,  and  vice   versa. What  we  are  facing  in  the  simple  polylogue  of  our  committee  meeting  is  a   situation  where  a  protagonist  faces  disagreement  from  two  distinct  parties  who  in  turn   also  disagree  with  one  another.  This  situation  is  possible  whenever  the  positions  are   contrary,  rather  than  strictly  contradictory,  so  that  the  opponent  of  my  opponent  is  not   necessarily  my  ally,  but  possibly  yet  another  opponent  to  engage  with.  In  contradiction,   negations  are  bi-­‐conditional  (-­‐-­‐2  =  2  and  ¬¬α  =  α);  in  contrariness,  we  deal  with  simple   conditionals:  while  β  entails  ¬α,  ¬β  does  not  entail  α  (denying  the  antecedent);  ¬β  may   even  be  used  as  a  support  for  γ,  which  actually  also  entails  ¬α.  So  an  arguer  that  seems   to  be  my  (α)  ally  by  virtue  of  criticizing  my  critic  (such  as  when  γ  claims  “¬β”)  may   quickly  disappoint  me  by  turning  her  critical  edge  against  me  (because  “γ”  means  “¬α”).       As  we  have  endeavored  to  show,  division  of  polylogues  into  dyadically  defined   roles  collapses  for  one  reason  or  another.  Hence,  perhaps  a  new  appreciation  of  a   polylogical  role  of  an  arguer  involved  in  a  multi-­‐party  contest  of  contrary  positions  is   needed.  But  while  there  is  nothing  particularly  odd  in  analyzing  a  clash  of  contrary   positions  (such  as  in  our  committee  meeting),  the  parties  attached  to  these  positions  do  

16   Cf.   basic   Popperian   criteria   for   theory   selection   (e.g.   in   Lakatos,   1974),   as   well   as   their   application   to  

argumentation  theory  in:  van  Eemeren  &  Grootendorst,  1988.  

22    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

not  easily  fit  into  the  protagonist’s  and  the  antagonist’s  shoes,  since  their  relational   dialectical  “identity”  consists  of  more  than  a  single  opposition  from  “the  other”  party.     In  these  ways,  we  hope  to  have  established  the  need  for  further  investigation  of   polylogical  argumentation.                   References:     Author1  (2010).     Author1  (2012).     Author1  (2013a).     Author1  (2013b).     Author2  (1999).     Author2  (2003).     Author2  (2007).     Author2  (2013).     Author2,  &  Jackson,  S.  (2005).   Austin,  J.L.  (1962).  How  to  do  things  with  words.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.   Blair,  J.  A.  (1998).  The  limits  of  the  dialogue  model  of  argument.  Argumentation,  12(2),   325-­‐339.   Blair,  J.  A.  (2012).  Rhetoric,  dialectic,  and  logic  as  related  to  argument.  Philosophy  and   Rhetoric,  45,  148-­‐164.   Bonevac,  D.  (2003).  Pragma-­‐dialectics  and  beyond.  Argumentation,  17(4),  451-­‐459.   Bou-­‐Franch,  P.,  Lorezo-­‐Dus,  N.,  &  Garcés-­‐Conejos  Blitvich,  P.  (2012).  Social  interaction  in   YouTube  text-­‐based  polylogues:  A  study  of  coherence.  Journal  of  Computer-­‐ Mediated  Communication,  17(4),  501–521.   boyd,  d.  (2011).  Social  network  sites  as  networked  publics:  Affordances,  dynamics,  and   implications.  In  Z.  Papacharissi  (Ed.),  Networked  Self:  Identity,  Community,  and   Culture  on  Social  Network  Sites  (pp.  39-­‐58).  New  York:  Routledge.   Brashers,  D.  E.,  &  Meyers,  R.  A.  (1989).  Tag-­‐team  argument  and  group  decision-­‐making:   A  preliminary  investigation.  In  B.  E.  Gronbeck  (Ed.),  Spheres  of  argument:   Proceedings  of  the  Sixth  SCA/AFA  Conference  on  Argumentation  (pp.  542-­‐550).   Annandale:  Speech  Communication  Association.   Bruxelles,  S.,  &  Kerbrat-­‐Orecchioni,  C.  (2004).  Coalitions  in  polylogues.  Journal  of   Pragmatics,  36(1),  75-­‐113.     Canary,  D.  J.,  Brossmann,  B.  G.,  &  Seibold,  D.  R.  (1987).  Argument  structures  in  decision-­‐ making  groups.  Southern  Speech  Communication  Journal,  53(1),  18-­‐37.     23    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Ceccarelli,  L.  (2011).  Manufactured  scientific  controversy:  Science,  rhetoric,  and  public   debate.  Rhetoric  &  Public  Affairs,  14(2),  195-­‐228.   Chen,  H.  (2010).  The  concept  of  the  “polylogue”  and  the  question  of  “intercultural”   identity.  Intercultural  Communication  Studies,  19(3),  54-­‐64.     Clark,  H.  H.,  &  Carlson,  T.  B.  (1982).  Hearers  and  speech  acts.  Language,  58(2),  332-­‐373.   Clark,  H.  H.  (1992).  Arenas  of  Language  Use.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.     Craig,  R.  T.,  &  Tracy,  K.  (1995).  Grounded  practical  theory:  The  case  of  intellectual   discussion.  Communication  Theory,  5(3),  248-­‐272.   Cramer,  P.  A.  (2011).  Controversy  as  News  Discourse.  Dordrecht:  Springer.     Dascal,  M.  (2008).  Dichotomies  and  types  of  debate.  In  F.  H.  van  Eemeren  &  B.  Garssen   (Eds.),  Controversy  and  Confrontation:  Relating  Controversy  Analysis  with   Argumentation  Theory  (pp.  27-­‐49).  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins.   Eemeren,  F.H.  van.  (2010).  Strategic  maneuvering  in  argumentative  discourse:  Extending   the  pragma-­‐dialectical  theory  of  argumentation.  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins.   Eemeren,  F.  H.  van,  &  Grootendorst,  R.  (1984).  Speech  acts  in  argumentative  discussions:   A  theoretical  model  for  the  analysis  of  discussions  directed  towards  solving   conflicts  of  opinion.  Dordrecht:  Foris.   Eemeren,  F.  H.  van,  &  Grootendorst,  R.  (1988).  Rationale  for  a  pragma-­‐dialectical   perspective.  Argumentation,  2(2),  271-­‐291.     Eemeren,  F.  H.  van,  &  Grootendorst,  R.  (1992).  Argumentation,  communication,  and   fallacies:  A  pragma-­‐dialectical  perspective.  Hillsdale,  NJ:  Lawrence  Erlbaum.       Eemeren,  F.  H.  van,  &  Grootendorst,  R.  (2004).  A  systematic  theory  of  argumentation.   Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.     Eemeren,  F.H.  van,  Grootendorst,  R.,  Jackson,  S.,  &  Jacobs,  S.  (1993).  Reconstructing   argumentative  discourse.  Tuscaloosa:  University  of  Alabama  Press.   Eemeren,  F.H.  van,  &  Houtlosser,  P.  (1999).  Strategic  manoeuvring  in  argumentative   discourse.  Discourse  Studies,  1(4),  479-­‐497.   Eemeren,  F.H.  van,  &  Houtlosser,  P.  (2005).  Theoretical  construction  and  argumentative   reality:  An  analytic  model  of  critical  discussion  and  conventionalised  types  of   argumentative  activity.  In  D.  Hitchcock  (Ed.),  The  uses  of  argument:  Proceedings   of  a  conference  at  McMaster  University,  pp.  75-­‐84.  Hamilton,  ON:  Ontario  Society   for  the  Study  of  Argumentation.     Eemeren,  F.  H.  van,  Houtlosser,  P.,  &  Snoeck  Henkemans,  A.  F.  (2007).  Argumentative   indicators  in  discourse:  A  pragma-­‐dialectical  study.  Dordrecht:  Springer.     Feteris,  E.  T.  (1999).  Fundamentals  of  legal  argumentation.  Dordrecht:  Kluwer.   Fogelin,  R.  J.  (1985).  The  logic  of  deep  disagreements.  Informal  Logic,  7(1),    1-­‐8.     Goffman,  E.  (1981).  Forms  of  talk.  Oxford:  Blackwell.   Goodwin,  C.,  &  Goodwin,  M.  H.  (1990).  Interstitial  argument.  In  A.  D.  Grimshaw  (Ed.),   Conflict  talk:  Sociolinguistic  investigations  of  arguments  in  conversations  (pp.  85-­‐ 117).  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.   Hamblin,  C.  L.  (1970).  Fallacies.  London:  Methuen.  

24    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Haviland,  J.  B.  (1986).  'Con  Buenos  Chiles':  Talk,  targets  and  teasing  in  Zincantán.  Text,   6(3),  249-­‐282.   Herring,  S.  C.  (1999).  Interactional  coherence  in  CMC.  Journal  of  Computer-­‐Mediated   Communication,  4(4),  online:  http://jcmc.indiana.edu/vol4/issue4/herring.html.       Hymes,  D.  (1972).  Models  of  the  interaction  of  language  and  social  life.  In  J.  J.  Gumperz  &   D.  Hymes  (Eds.),  Directions  in  sociolinguistics:  The  ethnography  of  communication   (pp.  35-­‐71).  New  York:  Holt,  Rinehart  and  Winston.     Jackson,  S.  (1998).  Disputation  by  design.  Argumentation,  12(2),  183-­‐198.   Jackson,  S.,  &  Jacobs,  S.  (1980).  Structure  of  conversational  argument:  Pragmatic  bases   for  the  enthymeme.  Quarterly  Journal  of  Speech,  66(3),  251-­‐265.   Jacobs,  S.,  &  Author2,  M.  (2002).   Jacobs,  S.,  &  Jackson,  S.  (1989).  Building  a  model  of  conversational  argument.  In  B.   Dervin,  L.  Grossberg,  B.  J.  O’Keefe,  &  E.  Wartella  (Eds.),  Rethinking   Communication.  Vol.  1  (pp.  153-­‐171).  Beverly  Hills:  Sage  Publications.   Jacobs,  S.,  &  Jackson,  S.  (2006).  Derailments  of  argumentation:  It  takes  two  to  tango.  In   P.  Houtlosser  &  M.  A.  van  Rees  (Eds.),  Considering  pragma-­‐dialectics  (pp.  121-­‐ 133).  Mahwah:  Lawrence  Erlbaum  Associates.   Jacquette,  D.  (2007).  Two  sides  of  any  issue.  Argumentation,  21(2),  115-­‐127.   Johnson,  R.  (2000).  Manifest  rationality.  Mahwah,  NJ:  Lawrence  Erlbaum.   Kerbrat-­‐Orecchioni,  C.  (1997).  A  multilevel  approach  in  the  study  of  talk-­‐in-­‐interaction.   Pragmatics,  7(1),  1-­‐20.   Kerbrat-­‐Orecchioni,  C.  (2004).  Introducing  polylogue.  Journal  of  Pragmatics,  36(1),  1-­‐24.       Krabbe,  E.  C.  W.  (1999).  Profiles  of  dialogue.  March  31,  1999.   Krabbe,  E.  C.  W.  (2006).  Logic  and  games.  In  P.  Houtlosser  &  M.  A.  van  Rees  (Eds.),   Considering  pragma-­‐dialectics  (pp.  185-­‐198).  Mahwah:  Lawrence  Erlbaum   Associates.   Levinson,  S.  C.  (1988).  Putting  linguistics  on  a  proper  footing:  Explorations  in  Goffman’s   concepts  of  participation.  In:  P.  Drew  &  A.  Wootton  (Eds.),  Erving  Goffman:   Exploring  the  interaction  order  (pp.  161-­‐227).  Cambridge,  MA:  Polity  Press.   Maeyer,  J.  de.  (forth.).  Towards  a  hyperlinked  society:  A  critical  review  of  link  studies.   New  Media  &  Society,  online  first:   http://nms.sagepub.com/content/early/2012/12/04/1461444812462851.   Maher,  D.  &  Jacobs,  S.  (1995).  The  Clayquot  Sound  controversy:  The  procedural   adequacy  of  news  coverage  and  public  deliberation  of  environmental  issues.  In  S.   Jackson  (Ed.),  Argumentation  and  values:  Proceedings  of  the  ninth  SCA/AFA   conference  on  argumentation  (pp.  344-­‐348).  Annandale,  VA:  SCA.   Marres,  N.  (2004).  Tracing  the  trajectories  of  issues,  and  their  democratic  deficits,  on   the  web:  The  case  of  the  development  gateway  and  its  doubles.  Information   Technology  &  People,  17(2),  124–149.   Marres,  N.  (2006).  Net-­‐Work  is  format  work:  Issue  networks  and  the  sites  of  civil  society   politics.  In  J.  Dean,    J.  Asherson,  &  G.  Lovink  (Eds.).  Reformatting  Politics:  

25    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Networked  Communications  and  Global  Civil  Society  (pp.  3-­‐17).  London:   Routledge.   Maynard,  D.  W.  (1986).  Offering  and  soliciting  collaboration  in  multi-­‐party  disputes   among  children  (and  other  humans).  Human  Studies,  9,  261-­‐285.       McBurney,  P.,  Hitchcock,  D.,  &  Parsons,  S.  (2007).  The  eightfold  way  of  deliberation   dialogue.  International  Journal  of  Intelligent  Systems,  22(1),  95–132.   Mohammed,  D.  (2011).  Strategic  manoeuvring  in  simultaneous  discussions.  In  F.  Zenker   (Ed.),  Argumentation:  Cognition  and  community.  Proceedings  of  the  9th   International  Conference  of  the  Ontario  Society  for  the  Study  of  Argumentation   (pp.  1-­‐11).  CD-­‐ROM.  Windsor,  ON:  OSSA.   Perelman,  Ch.,  &  Olbrechts-­‐Tyteca,  L.  (1969).  The  new  rhetoric:  A  treatise  on   argumentation  (transl.  by  J.  Wilkinson  &  P.  Weaver.  Notre  Dame:  University  of   Notre  Dame  Press.  (Original  work  published  1958.)   Prakken,  H.  (2000).  On  dialogue  systems  with  speech  acts,  arguments,  and   counterarguments.  In  M.  Ojeda-­‐Aciego  et  al.  (Eds.),  Proceedings  of  JELIA’2000.   The  7th  European  Workshop  on  Logics  in  Artificial  Intelligence  (pp.  224–238).   Berlin:  Springer.   Prakken,  H.  (2009).  Models  of  persuasion  dialogue.  In  I.  Rahwan  &  G.  R.  Simari  (Eds.),   Argumentation  in  Artificial  Intelligence  (pp.  281–300).  Dordrecht:  Springer.   Reddy,  M.  J.  (1979).  The  conduit  metaphor:  A  case  of  frame  conflict  in  our  language   about  language.  In  A.  Ortony  (Ed.),  Metaphor  and  Thought  (pp.  284–310).   Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.   Rees,  M.A.  van.  (1995).  Analyzing  and  evaluating  problem-­‐solving  discussions.   Argumentation,  9(2),  343–362.   Rees,  M.A.  van.  (2001).  The  diagnostic  power  of  the  stages  of  critical  discussion  in  the   analysis  and  evaluation  of  problem-­‐solving  discussions.  Argumentation,  15(4),   457-­‐470.     Rehg,  W.,  McBurney,  P.,  &  Parsons,  S.  (2005).  Computer  decision-­‐support  systems  for   public  argumentation:  Assessing  deliberative  legitimacy.  AI  &  Society,  19(3),   203–229.   Rescher,  N.  (1977).  Dialectics:  A  Controversy-­‐Oriented  Approach  to  the  Theory  of   Knowledge.  Albany:  State  University  of  New  York  Press.   Rogers,  R.  &  Marres,  N.  (2000).  Landscaping  climate  change:  A  mapping  technique  for   understanding  science  and  technology  debates  on  the  World  Wide  Web.  Public   Understanding  of  Science,  9,  141–163.     Sacks,  H.,  Schegloff,  E.  A.,  &  Jefferson,  G.  (1974).  A  simplest  systematics  for  the   organization  of  turn-­‐taking  for  conversation.  Language,  50,  696-­‐735.   Salmon,  M.  H.,  &  Zeitz,  C.  M.  (1995).  Analyzing  conversational  reasoning.  Informal  Logic,   17(1),  1-­‐23.       Searle,  J.  R.  (1992).  Conversation.  In  J.  R.  Searle  et  al.  (Eds.)  (On)  Searle  on  conversation   (pp.  7-­‐29).  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins.    

26    

Lewiński, M., & Aakhus, M. (2013). Argumentative Polylogues in a Dialectical Framework: A Methodological Inquiry. Argumentation, 28(2), 161–185. doi:10.1007/s10503-013-9307-x

Snoeck  Henkemans,  A.  F.  (1992).  Analysing  complex  argumentation:  The  reconstruction   of  multiple  and  coordinatively  compound  argumentation  in  a  critical  discussion.   Amsterdam:  SicSat.   Spranzi,  M.  (2011).  The  art  of  dialectic  between  dialogue  and  rhetoric:  The  Aristotelian   tradition.  Amsterdam:  John  Benjamins.     Sylvan,  R.  (1985).  Introducing  polylogue  theory.  Philosophica,  35(1),  89-­‐112.     Traverso,  V.  (2004).  Interlocutive  ‘crowding’  and  ‘splitting’  in  polylogues:  The  case  of  a   researchers’  meeting.  Journal  of  Pragmatics,  36(1),  53–74.         Tindale,  C.  W.  (2004).  Rhetorical  argumentation:  Principles  of  theory  and  practice.   Thousand  Oaks,  CA:  Sage.       Walton,  D.  N.  (1984).  Logical  dialogue-­‐games  and  fallacies.  Lanham,  MD:  University   Press  of  America  Inc.   Walton,  D.  N.  (1998).  The  new  dialectic:  Conversational  contexts  of  argument.  Toronto:   University  of  Toronto  Press.   Walton,  D.  N.  (1999).  Profiles  of  dialogue  for  evaluating  arguments  from  ignorance.   Argumentation,  13(1),  53-­‐71.   Walton,  D.  N.  (2004).  Relevance  in  Argumentation.  Mahwah,  NJ:  Lawrence  Erlbaum.     Walton,  D.N.,  &  Krabbe,  E.C.W.  (1995).  Commitment  indialogue:  Basic  concepts  of   interpersonal  reasoning.  Albany:  State  University  of  New  York  Press.   Walton,  D.N.,  &  Macagno.  F.  (2010).  Wrenching  from  context:  The  manipulation  of   commitments.  Argumentation,  24(3),  283–317.   Walton,  D.  N.,  Reed,  C.,  &  Macagno,  F.  (2008).  Argumentation  Schemes.  Cambridge:   Cambridge  University  Press.   Wimmer,  F.M.  (2007).  Cultural  centrisms  and  intercultural  polylogues  in  philosophy.   International  Review  of  Information  Ethics,  7(9),  1-­‐8.   Zarefsky,  D.  (2008).  Strategic  maneuvering  in  political  argumentation.  Argumentation,   22(3),  pp.  317-­‐330.  

27    

Suggest Documents