Anthropologies as Stories of Life

3 downloads 0 Views 246KB Size Report
philosophers (e.g. Owen 1849). It sat uneasily with recent .... Lewontin, Richard C. The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Vol. 560. New York: Columbia ...
Anthropologies as stories of life Maximilian Holland

REVIEW OF Biosocial Becomings: Integrating Social and Biological Anthropology Edited by Tim Ingold and Gisli Palsson. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013. [Draft Version, 2015 March - Please cite from published version] Biosocial Becomings continues the editors' broader project(s) of overhauling sociocultural anthropology's conception of its relationship with biology (as broadly 'an account of all-of-life') whilst rejecting the colonizing moves of reductionist biologisms (evolutionary psychology and its various genetic relatives). Whilst anthropologies of all stripes (and social sciences and humanities more generally) are now deconstructing biology/culture, nature/nurture and related dichotomies that have defined their disciplines' scope and limits, Ingold and Palsson have been dismantling such borders for decades (e.g. Ingold 1983). They find allies for their holistic project in a motley crew of heterodox biologists and philosophers, whose main contention is announced the book's first sentence "Neo Darwinism is dead." Everything in their project flows from this claim and its echoes throughout the book, so I herein set out its basis for the uninitiated. Ingold has long been acutely aware of neo Darwinists' "disregard... for the historical specificity of their provenance" (Ingold 2000: 2). Darwinism developed in the sociohistoric context of mid 19th century Europe, amid the novel observations of natural philosophers, and urgent concomitant questions that birthed this radical turn. The contemporary perspective, subscribed both outside and inside the academy, was of Godthe-creator; a reassuringly simple account of omnipotent control, causal agency and design, of a fixed world (and all life within it). Darwin and Wallace were both all too wary of this wider theistic context, and its more detailed elaborations by natural philosophers (e.g. Owen 1849). It sat uneasily with recent observations of fossils and apparent extinction, continuity between species, and change in life forms and environments over time. In their radical account, causal agency and design were now instead located within a slowly shifting nature as selector of variant life forms, and fixity was jettisoned. It was a striking recapitulation of the simple omnipotence of the monotheistic account, a simplicity which lent much to its adoption. Mendel's later findings were initially thought to challenge Darwinism but both were reconciled in the Modern Synthesis (Huxley 1942), now more commonly neo Darwinism, wherein natural selection was reconfirmed in the lead causal role, corresponded to (in Mendelian-type inheritance) by a 'statistical population' of mutable genes. In a prominent offshoot of neo Darwinism (the main target of I&P), conflated statistical-and-molecular genes (Moss 2003) have become tangible entities and, reflecting selection's efficacy (Gould 2002), are themselves now hustling, strategizing and increasingly hegemonic (Falk 1991) in their control of life forms. Here then, organisms become merely

1

'genetically determined' vehicles, accompanied by statements such as Dawkins' "This is a truth which still fills me with astonishment. Though I have known it for years, I never seem to get fully used to it" (1976: ix). This variety of neo Darwinism takes on a scientistic status for many adherents (detailed in Ingold's chapter), escaping its sociohistorical context, becoming instead a transcendental truth, more aptly standing in the place of the monotheistic account and its omnipotence. As the ultimate force acting on these genes, the natural selection concept has become so central to neo Darwinism's focus as to effectively crowd-out broader perspectives on life. The Price equation (Price 1970) encapsulates this posture. Its remarkable abstract(ing) simplicity in describing the statistical essence of selection is achieved by parsimoniously bracketing off from consideration all other conditions (or contexts) of and for life and its development. In doing so, it necessarily lacks dynamic sufficiency (Lewontin 1974, Frank 1995). "In the development of a real science about a real and practical world, it is impossible and undesirable to search for an exactly sufficient description. The nature of the physical universe is such that the change of state of every part of it affects the change of state of every other part, no matter how remote." (Lewontin 1974: 8). The simplifying perspective so attractive to selectionists is at the same time precisely the perspective that occludes attention to the plural, messy, contingent, contextual, relational and distinctive conditions of living organisms and their development. This illustrates the different explanatory focuses of more reductionist and essentializing accounts of lifeworlds, and more holistic and emergent accounts (Ruse 1989). Meanwhile, since Darwinism's origins, new observations and different conditions (e.g. the ongoing mass extinction of life-worlds) have emerged and led to different questions and priorities. In short, the perspective, the field of view, and the pressing questions have moved. The narrow selectionist perspective is no longer a satisfying or illuminating account of all-oflife. This brief genealogical sketch, elements of which are found throughout the book, of course resonates with the epistemological stance of (amongst many others) Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Ortega y Gasset, Sapir, Bachelard, Canguilhem, Kuhn, Foucault, and Gibson (let us, approximately refer to it as one of perspectivism, in the Nietzschean sense). Since this stance also overlaps considerably with philosophical and cultural relativism, it is one very familiar to sociocultural anthropologists. Ingold and Palsson's approach then learns from perspectivism(s) and encourages an antiessentializing, holistically conceived, emergent, processual and always-already-relational account of the messy, entangled, co-constructive contexts of developmental systems of life. It is this that they refer to as Biosocial Becomings. Their approach is consonant with the epistemology of 'developmental systems theory' (DST), as well as other systemsinspired approaches (Bateson 1972, Deleuze & Guattari 1987). Oyama (1985, 2001) reflexively describes DST, as not in fact a theory, but modes of approaches, sets of

2

perspectives. In short, an undisciplined motley crew. It is these perspectives that the book recommends to sociocultural anthropologists to rebut reductionist neo Darwinism. The common themes of DST (cf. Oyama et al. 2001) correspond to all that has been occluded: Life processes necessarily go on in and through a context of many interacting factors, an 'ensemble', all entwined with and co-constructing each other. The continuation through time of these interacting factors (some of them themselves 'organisms') makes them part of the inheritances of other organisms developing in the system (inheritance is not just 'genes'). Since all these factors interact to construct the organism (itself permeable, entwined and relational), there is effectively 'distributed influence' on development (thus genes cannot be privileged as the only locus of control). The distinction between life in developmental flow and life in evolutionary flow breaks down somewhat; since in both cases it is the total entwined system of life (at once the developmental system and the 'environmental niche') that moves forward through time. DST's pluralist account of the various intertwined influences on development that can usefully be considered as 'inheritances' includes (as well as traditional 'genes'); epigenetics, niche-construction, behavioural, cultural and symbolic factors (e.g. Jablonka & Lamb 2005, Oyama et al. 2001, current volume); these are glossed as 'multiple inheritance'. Biology/culture, nature/nurture (and other) essentializing dichotomies dissolve; all such 'separate' factors are inherently entwined aspects of the developmental system. Further, since the 'evolution' of regularly arising developmental capacities ('traits' in traditional accounts) of organisms can (conceptually) and does (observably) sometimes occur without any genetic change (e.g. chapters of Ingold, Fuentes, Ramirez); the central claim of gene-centric neo Darwinists - that genetic change is the necessary correlate of evolutionary change - is immediately refuted. What further themes does the book's approach open up that resonate with ongoing discussions of sociocultural anthropologists? The diverse and fertile chapters contain several common strands: Rejecting essentialized natures and emphasizing the always-inprocess-interactive-contingent co-construction (development and ontogeny) of organisms' capacities highlights the processual and relational aspects of becoming human (inspiring this volume's title). These harmoniously resonate with, for example, accounts of Amerindian ontologies such as those of Gow, Viveiros de Castro, Descola, and related discussions of processual becoming, such as nurture kinship (Holland 2012), as well as broader ontological themes in anthropology (e.g. Viveiros De Castro 2012). Several of the chapters here explore resonance with Bourdieu's accounts of practice. These processual and relational themes are most prominently explored in the chapters of Ingold, Palsson, Praet, Vaisman and Mangiameli. The de-essentializing of once familiar dichotomies invites comparison and contrast with the work of Haraway, Franklin, Rabinow, Rose and Strathern (chapters by Palsson, Chatjouli, Vaisman, Al-Mohammed). Resonance with multispecies ethnography is also discussed in several chapters (Palsson, Vaisman, Praet). Finally, phenomenological

3

questions are productively taken up here especially by Al-Mohammed and Palsson (see also Ingold 2000, 2001). Several other resonances are explored in the book's diverse contributions, all of which are innovative and fertile testaments to the productivity and pluralism of the core approach. Fuentes and Ramirez's chapters discuss DST's implications for biological anthropology. As Fuentes notes, stepping from simplifying abstractions into a more holistic approach "adds an extra layer of complication" (p.50) that may entail new methodological habits for some biological anthropologists at the same time as it poses new and potentially productive questions. Fuentes's research has been at the forefront of exploring these questions in biological anthropology. For all anthropological traditions, Palsson reiterates that “Such a broad perspective should not be seen as a fixed baseline or an end in itself but as a starting point for further work, as a tentative framework inviting novel conceptual and theoretical development and elaboration.” (p. 248). I have every expectation that such elaborations will prove yet more fertile as Ingold and Palsson's project moves forwards. Their statement "Neo Darwinism is dead" should be considered an invitation to life.

References Cited Bateson, Gregory. Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution, and Epistemology. New York: Ballentine Books, 1972. Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. New. London: Oxford University Press, 1976. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press, 1987. Falk, Raphael. ―The Dominance of Traits in Genetic Analysis.‖ Journal of the History of Biology 24, no. 3 (September 1991): 457–84. doi:10.1007/BF00156321. Frank, Steven A. ―George Price‘s Contributions to Evolutionary Genetics.‖ Journal of Theoretical Biology 175 (1995): 373–77. Gould, S J. The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge MA: Belknap Press, 2002. Holland, Maximilian. Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship: Compatibility between Cultural and Biological Approaches. North Charleston: CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform, 2012. Huxley, J. Evolution. The Modern Synthesis. London: Allen & Unwin, 1942. Ingold, Tim. ―From Complementarity to Obviation: On Dissolving the Boundaries between Social and Biological Anthropology, Archaeology and Psychology.‖ In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, edited by Susan

4

Oyama, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray, 255–79. Cambridge MA.: MIT press, 2001. ———. ―The Architect and the Bee: Reflections on the Work of Animals and Men.‖ Man 18, no. 1 (1983): 1–20. ———. The Perception of the Environment: Essays on Livelihood, Dwelling and Skill. Abingdon: Routledge, 2000. ———. ―The Poverty of Selectionism.‖ Anthropology Today 16, no. 3 (2000): 1–2. doi:10.1111/1467-8322.00022. ———. ―The Trouble with ‗evolutionary Biology.‘‖ Anthropology Today 23, no. 2 (2007): 13–17. Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Vol. 5. Cambridge MA: MIT press, 2005. Lewontin, Richard C. The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Vol. 560. New York: Columbia University Press, 1974. Moss, Lenny. What Genes Can’t Do. Cambridge MA: MIT press, 2003. Owen, Richard. On the Nature of Limbs. London: John Van Voorst, 1849. Oyama, Susan. The Ontogeny of Information : Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. Oyama, Susan, Paul E. Griffiths, and Russell D. Gray. ―Introduction: What Is Developmental Systems Theory?‖ In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, 1–11. Cambridge MA: MIT press, 2001. Price, George C. ―Selection and Covariance.‖ Nature 227, no. 01 August (1970): 520–21. Ruse, Michael. ―Do Organisms Exist?‖ Integrative and Comparative Biology 29, no. 3 (January 01, 1989): 1061–66. doi:10.1093/icb/29.3.1061. Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. ―Cosmologies: Perspectivism.‖ HAU: Masterclass Series 1 (2012): 45–168.

5