Constructivism

2 downloads 0 Views 407KB Size Report
Constructivism by Annie and John Selden. November, 1996. 1. In mathematics education, especially research in mathematics education. A. Constructivism in itsĀ ...
Constructivism by Annie and John Selden November, 1996

1. In mathematics education, especially research in mathematics education. A. Constructivism in its moderate (also called simple or trivial) form is a philosophical position characterized by the idea that knowledge is not passively received, but rather actively constructed by an individual. This central idea is applies to learning generally and is not limited to any particular setting such as problem solving or listening to lectures. "Knowledge" refers to the contents of an individual mind, not to abstract or public knowledge. "Constructed" refers to the result of mental activity, such as reflecting on one's work or perceptions. It does not necessarily include the physical or abstract aspects of construction, such as assembling a jigsaw puzzle, constructing the rational numbers from the integers, or making a proof, although doing or discussing these might engender mental constructions. New knowledge is seen as constructed out of older knowledge, where "knowledge" refers to more than just remembered "facts," e.g., the area of a triangle is one half its base times its height or the Pythagorean theorem. In addition, it refers to the largely tacit mental structures that allow one to interpret the meaning of words, bring ideas to mind, or effectively explore a new mathematical field. Below we give two simple illustrations of knowledge construction. (There are several views of knowledge and how it is constructed; however, the Piagetian and the Vygotskian theories are too complex to include here.) Illustration 1. A beginning topology student's knowledge about continuous functions can be viewed as a vast web of ideas, images, and personal experiences, some based on mathematical relationships and some not. The word "continuous" may bring to mind the image of a sine wave or of a teacher saying "you can draw it without lifting your pencil from the paper," which, in turn, might bring to mind other associations, e.g., "but to prove it, you need to use an epsilon-delta argument." Consider now how the student might comprehend the proposition that the continuous image of a connected set is connected and develop it into lasting, usable knowledge. Suppose the proposition is presented by a

teacher together with a couple of examples. If the student merely passively observes the presentation, he/she might be able to repeat some of it for awhile, but later the proposition might not come to mind when needed. However, as the student works with the proposition - perhaps examining its proof, applying it, even discussing its significance - he/she might come to associate it with many ideas and images, including aspects of his/her prior knowledge of "continuous" and "connected." Thus, the student "constructs" a mental structure that enhances the probability of the proposition coming to mind when needed. This structure is idiosyncratic and is neither directly observable nor fully communicable. Illustration 2. Consider an abstract algebra student who is fairly familiar with groups, but has just met the definitions of field and vector space. Suppose the student is searching for finite fields, guided by his knowledge of how to find new algebraic structures -- a mainly tacit understanding based on his experiences with groups. The student's way of searching for algebraic structures is not yet likely to be very effective and may be altered, not necessarily consciously, based on new experiences, perhaps including that fields are also vector spaces which constrains somewhat their possible orders. This alteration can be seen as knowledge construction. Note that it might be more appropriate to evaluate such knowledge, which amounts to a way of searching, as effective or not, rather than true or false. B. Constructivism in its radical form can be characterized by two additional ideas. (1) The function of cognition is adaptive in the biological sense of tending toward "fit" or viability. (Trees in a forest have more leaves where there is more light and runners have strong legs. Both have adapted to fit a situation.) (2) Cognition organizes the experiential world, but does not allow discovery of objective reality. [Cf. E. von Glasersfeld, "An Exposition of Constructivism: Why Some Like it Radical," in R. B. Davis, C. A. Maher & N. Noddings (Eds.), Constructivist Views on the Teaching and Learning of Mathematics (pp. 19-29). Reston, VA: NCTM.] This position does not deny the existence of the external world, although it does deny the world can be mirrored objectively by one's own knowledge. It is consistent with one's knowledge appearing to approximately mirror much of the external world, perhaps because of the tendency toward "fit." Notes: Currently much research in mathematics education is guided by, or consistent with, a constructivist perspective. Piaget was perhaps the best known constructivist. He did a great deal of empirical work with children and developed theoretical explanations

including a description of the way knowledge construction occurs. Vygotsky developed a view that depends more on social interaction. Ernst von Glasersfeld, is known for his articulation and development of the ideas of radical constructivism. In the mathematics education community, constructivism appears to have been very influential in legitimizing studies of students' mental processes, such as how they learn to add or develop the concept of function. It has facilitated moving away from behaviorism, with its logical positivist viewpoint, which tended to ignore the internal workings of the mind and thus effectively discouraged research on many interesting mental questions.

2. In popular usage, especially in the press and amongst some teachers and mathematicians. Constructivism is often used to refer to a teaching method, or the advocacy of a teaching method, in which students construct (invent, discover) their own mathematics. Illustration 1. Certain parents dislike a " . . . teaching philosophy called constructivism that says children learn better if they construct something on their own - use a string to measure a circle and 'discover' that the circumference is 3.14 times greater than the diameter . . ." [June Kronholz, "Numbers Racket," The Wall Street Journal, November 5, 1997.] Illustration 2. Constructivism "apparently urges that students construct their own mathematics. It is not clear where this will lead. Perhaps every student will construct his own algorithm for long division." This doctrine "holds that students must somehow construct in their own minds all (?) the basic notions of mathematics." [Saunders Mac Lane, Letter to the Editor, Focus, February 1998.] Notes: This popular meaning of constructivism is very different from the meaning in the mathematics education research community. According to it, what is constructed (discovered) is mathematics, e.g., that the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter is independent of the circle's size. In contrast to this, according to the constructivism of mathematics education research, what is constructed is some kind of (personal) knowledge, i.e., a structure in an individual mind which may not even be fully describable in words and which might, or might not, arise from discovery of

mathematics. Furthermore, the constructivism of mathematics education research does not refer to a particular teaching method, but rather provides a way of viewing learning which can be used when analyzing many kinds of teaching. "Constructivist teaching," if it is used at all in the mathematics education research community, is likely to be an umbrella term referring to teaching that is informed by constructivism, i.e., that takes into consideration the idea that a student uses his/her prior knowledge in mentally constructing new knowledge. Most popular meanings of constructivism appear to be somewhat similar to that of "discovery learning," which refers to a kind of teaching and learning based very roughly on the idea that students learn well when they discover what is to be learned for themselves. Even in the 1960's, when it was espoused by Harvard psychologist J. S. Bruner and others, it was considered an untested hypothesis. [Cf. L. S. Schulman and E. R. Keislar (Eds.), Learning by Discovery: A Critical Appraisal, Rand McNally, 1966.] Currently, "discovery learning" is neither a major area of interest in mathematics education research nor a driving principle in research-based curriculum reform projects.

3. In the history and philosophy of science and mathematics. Constructivism (also called social constructivism) is a philosophy of science in which scientists are viewed as socially constructing knowledge of the external world rather than uncovering it directly from nature. Here "knowledge" means public knowledge, not the contents of an individual mind and the ideas of truth and objectivity have been metamorphosed from their traditional meanings into a form of social acceptance. For example, in the traditional view, ones says it true that gold is heavier than aluminum because of the correspondence to the facts of the matter, as established by observation. Whereas in this view, gold is heavier than aluminum because it has been agreed upon by the physics community. Notes. Constructivism is a philosophical position within the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) which is a subarea of the history and philosophy of science. However, SSK is often identified with constructivism which is its most conspicuous stance. Most research in mathematics education does not appear to be guided or inspired by this kind of

constructivism although there is some interest in a fairly similar philosophy of mathematics. [Paul Ernest, Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics, SUNY Press, 1998.] Many scientists and mathematicians hold views of the nature of science and mathematics which appear to be inconsistent with this kind of constructivism and some are quite concerned about its growing influence. [Paul R. Gross, Norman Levitt, and Martin W. Lewis, The Flight from Science and Reason, New York Academy of Sciences, 1996.]

4. In mathematics. Constructivism in mathematics (also sometimes called intuitionism) refers to a philosophical position (with several variations) that seeks to place mathematics on a firm logical foundation by basing it only on what advocates regard as intuitively clear insights. This includes theorems that can be proved constructively based on integers and finite sets, but avoids the logical laws of double negation and excluded middle, as well as proof by contradiction. Notes: Perhaps the best known constructivist was the Dutch mathematician, L. E. J. Brouwer. There appears to be little connection between the meaning of constructivism in mathematics and its meanings in mathematics education research, the various popular views, or the philosophy of science. Constructivism in mathematics is an absolutist philosophy, i.e., it is concerned with absolute truth, independent of individuals or communities, while the SSK form of constructivism is relativist, i.e., it is concerned, not with truth, but with acceptance, which is dependent on particular communities.

Annotated Bibliography on Constructivism The following annotated list of references is not linked to any particular Research Sampler column. It was prepared as a supplement to our talk "Constructivism in Mathematics Education - What Does It Mean?" given at the RUMEC Conference on Research in Mathematics Education held at Central Michigan University, Sept. 5-8, 1996.

1. Bettencourt, A. (1993). The construction of knowledge: A radical constructivist view. In K. Tobin (Ed.), The Practice of Constructivism in Science Education (pp. 39-50). Washington, DC: AAAS Press. Gives four constraints on knowledge that can be constructed: one's previous constructions, interactions with others, one's experience, "fit" with the rest of one's knowledge. 2. Cobb, P. (1994). Where is the mind? Constructivist and sociocultural perspectives on mathematical development. Educational Researcher, 23(7), 13-20. Describes the (psychological) constructivist and sociocultural views as complementary -- each "tells half a good story," with the former using terms like accommodation, and the latter, terms like appropriation. 3. Cobb, P. & Yackel E. (1995). Constructivist, emergent, and sociocultural perspectives in the context of developmental research. In D. T. Owens, M. K. Reed & G. M. Millsaps, Proceedings of the Seventeenth Annual Meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, Vol. 1 (pp. 3-29). Columbus, OH: ERIC/CSMEE Publications (SE 057 176). Differentiates between psychological constructivist, sociocultural, and emergent (social constructivist) perspectives mainly with regard to the conduct of research, and to a lesser extent, teaching. 4. Dubinsky, E. (1992). Reflective abstraction in advanced mathematical thinking. In D. Tall (Ed.), Advanced Mathematical Thinking (pp. 95-124). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. An extension of Piagetian ideas to the learning of university level mathematics, emphasizing the " genetic decompositions of concepts," i.e., descriptions, based on empirical data and an understanding of the mathematics involved, of the constructions a student might make.

5. Ernest, P. (1991). The Philosophy of Mathematics Education. London: Falmer Press. Influenced by David Bloor and SSK, Ernest proposes a philosophy of mathematics called "social constructivism," which sees mathematics as fallible and objective as meaning socially agreed upon. 6. Golden, G. A. (1990). Epistemology, constructivism, and discovery learning of mathematics. In R. B. Davis, C. A. Maher & N. Noddings (Eds.), Constructivist Views on the Teaching and Learning of Mathematics (pp. 31-47). Reston, VA: NCTM. Argues in favor of "moderate constructivism" and takes issue with radical constructivism from the viewpoint of a physicist who directs the Rutgers Center for Mathematics, Science and Computer Education. 7. Kilpatrick, J. (1987). What constructivism might be in mathematics education. In J. C. Bergeron, N. Herscovics & C. Kieran (Eds.), Proceedings of the Eleventh Conference of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (pp. 2-27). Montreal: University of Montreal. A critique of radical constructivism, together with a common core that most mathematics education researchers today accept. Available through ERIC/CSMEE (SE 055 633). 8. Martin, J. & Sugarman, J. (1996). Bridging social constructionism and cognitive constructivism: A psychology of human possibility and constraint. A revised version of an invited address by the first author presented at the AERA annual meeting in New York. (Available from Jack Martin, Faculty of Education, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, B.C. Canada V5A 1S6.) The sociocultural view (of the appropriation of cultural practices through conversation) does not explain how individual creativity arises, and cognitive constructivism does not account for how individuals come to take knowledge as shared. The authors propose a mechanism whereby individuals are constrained, but not determined by, the surrounding culture. Sophisticated memory capabilities and imagination, together with personal experiences, allow revision of appropriated ideas.

9. Linn, M.C. & Burbules, N. C. (1993). Construction of knowledge and group learning. In K. Tobin (Ed.), The Practice of Constructivism in Science Education (pp. 91-119). Washington, DC: AAAS Press. Argues that advocating group learning for knowledge construction oversimplifies issues concerning the social structure of groups, individuals' goals, and the diverse nature of knowledge construction. Problems include " groupthink," group acceptance of the first idea generated, use of everyday arguments, etc. 10. Phillips, D. C. (1995). The good, the bad, and the ugly: The many faces of constructivism. Educational Researcher, 24(7), 5-12. Takes an exceptionally broad view of constructivism, considering authors like v. Glasersfeld, Piaget, Dewey, Kant, Kuhn, and various feminists. What's good is the emphasis on active participation by the learner. What's bad is the tendency toward relativism and the " jettisoning of any substantial rational justification." What's ugly is the tendency toward sectarianism -- each "harbors some distrust of its rivals." 11. Sismondo, S. (1993). Some social constructions. Social Studies of Science, 23, 515-53. An attempt to sort out what various authors in the social studies of science consider to be socially constructed: knowledge, facts, theories, representations, etc. 12. Slezak, P. (1994). Sociology of scientific knowledge and scientific education: Part I. Science and Education, 3, 265-294. Sociology of scientific knowledge and scientific education Part II: Laboratory Life under the Microscope. Science and Education, 3 , 328-355. A critique, especially of Latour and Woolgar's Laboratory Life, calling SSK "an extravagant deconstructionist nihilism according to which all science is fiction and the world is said to be socially constructed by negotiation," along with the admonition that science teachers resist its findings. 13. Steffe, L. P. & Gale, J. (1995). Constructivism in Education. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Six alternative paradigms of constructivism, applying to fields from mathematics education to family therapy, are considered: radical constructivism (v. Glasersfeld), social constructionism (K. Gergen), information-processing constructivism (R. Spiro), cybernetic systems (F. Steier), sociocultural approaches (J. Wertsch), and social constructivism (H. Bauersfeld).

14. Steffe, L. P. & Kieren, T. (1994). Radical constructivism and mathematics education. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 25, 711-733. An historical account, in JRME's 25th anniversary special issue, describing Piaget's cognitivedevelopment psychology, the "preconstructivist revolution" of the 70s, and JRME's role, from the early 80s on, as a forum for debate of issues related to constructivism within mathematics education. 15. von Glasersfeld, E. (1983). Learning as a constructive activity. In J. C. Bergeron and N. Herscovics (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (pp. 41-69). Montreal: University of Montreal. The paper in which radical constructivism "burst onto the international scene." (P. Ernest) Available through ERIC/CSMEE (ED 289 688). 16. von Glasersfeld, E. (1990). An exposition of constructivism: Why some like it radical. In R. B. Davis, C. A. Maher & N. Noddings (Eds.), Constructivist Views on the Teaching and Learning of Mathematics (pp. 19-29). Reston, VA: NCTM. A brief overview explaining why constructivism "needs to be radical," explaining viability and how one can "manage without the traditional notion of Truth." 17. von Glasersfeld, E. (1993). Questions and answers about radical constructivism. In K. Tobin (Ed.), The Practice of Constructivism in Science Education (pp. 23-38). Washington, DC: AAAS Press. Brief, and mostly easy-to-read, answers to forty-two questions regarding epistemology, the role of "social interaction," and implications of the constructivist orientation for teaching. 18. von Glasersfeld, E. (1995). Radical Constructivism: A Way of Knowing and Learning. London: Falmer Press. "The definitive theoretical account of radical constructivism." (P. Ernest) An autobiographical first chapter lets you in on how v. Glasersfeld came to his views.